<<

By the same author 's (1966) ARISTOTLE'S Aristotle's (1975) Aristotle's and Propositions (1980) Aristotle's (1981) Aristotle's (1982) Translated with Commentaries Aristotle: Selected Works-with Lloyd P. Gerson (1983) and Glossary by HIPPOCRATES G. APOSTLE

THE PERIPATETIC PRESS Grinnell, Iowa All rights reserved

No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher.

Copyright© 1969 by Indiana University Press Copyright© 1980 by H. G. Apostle cl. ISBN 0-9602870-2-7 To Dr. Nathan Silberstein pa. ISBN 0-9602870-3-5 Library of Congress catalog card number: 80-80037 Manufactured in the United States of America book A

finite or infinite. If finite, but more than one, then they are two5 or three 6 20 or four or some other number; but if infinite, then they are either generically one but differ in shape or kind, as Democritus says,7 or even contrary.8 Also those who inquire into the number of things do so in a similar way; for they first inquire whether the constituents of things are one or 25 many, and if many, whether finite or infinite. Thus they inquire whether 9 the principles or elements are one or many. „ ., . f, Book A Now to inquire whether being is one and immovable is not to inquire 1 1850 about ; " for .just as ,the geometer has no arguments at all against . one who rejects the principles of geometry, seeing that their discussion' belongs to another science or to a science common to all others," so 1 too in the case of principles; for if being is only one and is one in this 184s 10 Since under^stanjding and knowing in every inquiry concerned with 1 manner [immovable], no principle exists at all, seeing that a principle things having principles or causes or elements' results from the knowl- is a principle (ofj/some thing or things.12 Indeed, to inquire whether edge of these (for we think that we know each thing when we know the being is one in this manner is like arguing against any other paradox j first causes and the first principles and have reached the elements), maintained for the. sake of argument, suchJas that of Heraclitus13 or the \ 15 clearly, in thetscience of nature too we should first try to determine 14 2 one which might assert that being is one man, or it is like refuting an what is the gase with regard, to the principles. eristic argument, such as that of Melissus and that of .15 ~~Xhe natural way to proceed^is from what is more known and clearer (The latter two thinkers assume false premises, and the conclusions they to us to what is by nature clearer and more known; for what is known 10 ; j •' 3 draw do not follow from the premises; as for Melissus, his argument is to us and what is known without qualification are not the same. So rather crude and presents no problem, for once an absurd premise is 20 we should proceed in this manner, namely, from what is less clear by granted, the rest follow, and there is no difficulty at all in this,) nature, though clearer to us, to what is by its nature clearer and more known. Now the things that are at first plain and clear to us are rather We, on theother hand, make the assumption that things/existing by nature3^afe\ii|/motion, either all or some of them; and this is clear by <,. i •