The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle's Physics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle's Physics © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 Hypomnemata Untersuchungen zur Antike und zu ihrem Nachleben Herausgegeben von Ewen Bowie, Albrecht Dihle, Dorothea Frede, Hans-Joachim Gehrke, Günther Patzig, Karla Pollmann, Christiane Reitz, Christoph Riedweg, Gisela Striker Band 196 Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 Sebastian Odzuck The Priority of Locomotion in Aristotle’s Physics Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 Verantwortliche Herausgeberinnen: Dorothea Frede und Gisela Striker Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.d-nb.de abrufbar ISBN 978-3-525-25306-9 ISBN 978-3-647-25306-0 (E-Book) Umschlagabbildung: Sanitarium Charleroi, Christian Odzuck, Collage, 18 cm × 24 cm, 2013 © 2013 VG Bildkunst, Bonn. Gedruckt mit freundlicher Unterstützung der Geschwister Boehringer Ingelheim Stiftung für Geisteswissenschaften in Ingelheim am Rhein. © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen / Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht LLC, Bristol, CT, U.S.A. www.v-r.de Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Das Werk und seine Teile sind urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung in anderen als den gesetzlich zugelassenen Fällen bedarf der vorherigen schriftlichen Einwilligung des Verlages. – Printed in Germany. Gesamtherstellung: L Hubert & Co, Göttingen Gedruckt auf alterungsbeständigem Papier. © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 Contents Acknowledgements ........................... 9 1. Introduction ............................ 10 2. The importance of the primary kind of change . 14 2.1 Overview ........................... 14 2.2 The arrangement of the Physics . 15 2.2.1 First option: Books VI–VIII as the treatise On Change 18 2.2.1.1 Andronicus ...................... 19 2.2.1.2 Theophrastus’ letter . 19 2.2.1.3 References in Aristotle . 21 2.2.1.4 Eudemus ........................ 21 2.2.2 Second option: Books V–VIII as the treatise On Change ......................... 22 2.3 The eight books of the Physics . 25 2.3.1 Physics I–IV: Examining change for the sake of understanding nature . 25 2.3.2 Physics V–VIII: The general analysis of change . 27 2.4 Physics VIII .......................... 31 2.4.1 Overview ....................... 31 2.4.2 The argument of Physics VIII . 31 2.4.3 The importance of the primary kind of change . 34 2.5 Conclusion .......................... 40 3. Change in quality and quantity of living beings depends on loco- motion, but not vice versa ..................... 42 3.1 Overview ........................... 42 3.2 Growth and diminution presuppose alteration . 44 3.2.1 Growth presupposes alteration . 45 3.2.2 Diminution presupposes alteration . 48 3.3 Alteration presupposes locomotion . 49 3.4 Does locomotion precede all occurrences of change in quan- tity? .............................. 53 3.5 The reason for the restriction of the argument’s scope . 58 © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 3.6 The sense of priority ..................... 67 3.7 Conclusion .......................... 69 4. Locomotion necessarily accompanies each of the other kinds of change, but not vice versa ...................... 71 4.1 Overview ........................... 71 4.2 What changes in quantity changes with respect to place . 73 4.2.1 Overview ....................... 73 4.2.2 What is growing moves to a larger place . 74 4.2.3 Change in place implies no change in the spatial order of the subject’s parts . 78 4.2.4 A possible objection . 81 4.2.5 Compatibility with the irreducibility of the kinds of change ......................... 85 4.2.6 Conclusion ...................... 88 4.3 What undergoes generation or corruption changes with respect to place ........................ 89 4.3.1 Overview ....................... 89 4.3.2 Generation and corruption in virtue of aggregation and segregation .................... 90 4.3.3 What aggregates or segregates must change with respect to place .................... 96 4.3.4 Conclusion ...................... 97 4.4 What changes in quality changes with respect to place . 98 4.4.1 Overview ....................... 98 4.4.2 What does it mean that condensation and rarefaction are principles of quality? . 100 4.4.3 Every alteration involves a change in the four basic qualities ........................ 104 4.4.4 Every change in the four basic qualities involves con- densation or rarefaction . 108 4.4.5 Condensation and rarefaction are forms of aggrega- tion and segregation . 110 4.4.6 What changes in quality changes with respect to place 112 4.4.7 Conclusion ...................... 113 4.5 Conclusion .......................... 113 5. All changes depend on the first locomotion, but not vice versa . 115 5.1 Overview ........................... 115 5.2 The unity of the eternal change . 118 5.2.1 Two ways in which change may be eternal . 118 5.2.2 Why the eternal change must be one and continuous . 121 © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 5.2.3 The criteria for being one continuous change . 123 5.2.4 What is better is the case in nature . 127 5.3 Locomotion alone can be one and eternal . 130 5.3.1 None of the other three kinds of change can be one and eternal ....................... 131 5.3.2 Only circular locomotion can be one and eternal . 134 5.4 Locomotion has ontological priority . 137 5.4.1 Ontological priority . 137 5.4.2 A third sense in which locomotion is ontologically prior .......................... 139 5.5 Conclusion .......................... 142 6. Locomotion has temporal priority . 144 6.1 Overview ........................... 144 6.2 Locomotion has priority in time, since it is the only change eternals can undergo ..................... 146 6.3 Objection: Locomotion is the last of all changes in perishable things ............................. 148 6.4 Coming to be presupposes an earlier locomotion . 150 6.5 The locomotion of the sun as a cause of generation . 154 6.6 Conclusion .......................... 162 7. Locomotion is prior in essence . 164 7.1 Locomotion is prior in essence, since it is last in coming to be ............................... 164 7.1.1 Overview ....................... 164 7.1.2 The reversed priority claim . 166 7.1.3 A different use of the term ‘locomotion’ . 172 7.1.4 Does locomotion come to things last? . 175 7.1.4.1 Capacities of the soul . 176 7.1.4.2 Priority in essence of the locomotive capacity . 179 7.1.5 Another sense of priority in essence . 182 7.1.6 Conclusion ...................... 184 7.2 Locomotion alone preserves its subject’s essence . 186 7.2.1 Overview ....................... 186 7.2.2 Locomotion does not change its subject’s being . 188 7.2.3 Locomotion preserves its subject’s essence best . 190 7.2.4 Making x depart from its essence by being part of a change in essence? . 195 7.2.4.1 Alteration as part of a change in essence . 195 7.2.4.2 Growth and diminution as part of change in essence . 199 © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 8 Contents 7.2.4.3 Locomotion as a part of a change in essence? . 201 7.2.5 Change in quality or quantity in principle may result in a change in essence . 202 7.3 Conclusion: Locomotion’s priority in essence . 207 8. Conclusion ............................. 211 Bibliography .............................. 220 List of Abbreviations .......................... 223 Index Locorum ............................. 221 Index Nominum ............................ 223 Index Rerum .............................. 221 © 2014, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525253069 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647253060 Acknowledgements This book is a slightly revised version of my dissertation, which was accepted at the Humboldt Universität zu Berlin in 2012. Above all, I would like to thank my three supervisors Jonathan Beere, Ben Morison, and Christof Rapp. My dissertation benefited greatly from working under their guidance and I am most thankful for the generous support they have given me in many different respects both while I was working on this project and afterwards. I was especially fortunate to have had the opportunity to continually work with Ben Morison while on a short stay in Oxford, during several months at Princeton, and – despite being on the other side of the Atlantic – from my desk in Erlangen. Our conversations and his numerous comments and sug- gestions greatly improved my work both in detail and from a broader per- spective and I am very grateful for his support and encouragement. I also want to take this opportunity to thank Friedemann Buddensiek for his constant support over the past few years and for helping me start my inquiry into the priority of locomotion in the first place. Jacob Rosen, in addition to discussing various ideas, read and critiqued an earlier draft of chapter 7 and helped me clarify important points made there. Joshua Crone read the entire work and made many helpful suggestions, for which he has my sincere thanks. I am indebted to many other people for comments and help of various
Recommended publications
  • A Philosophical and Historical Analysis of Cosmology from Copernicus to Newton
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2017 Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton Manuel-Albert Castillo University of Central Florida Part of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Masters Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Castillo, Manuel-Albert, "Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton" (2017). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 5694. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/5694 SCIENTIFIC TRANSFORMATIONS: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL ANALYSIS OF COSMOLOGY FROM COPERNICUS TO NEWTON by MANUEL-ALBERT F. CASTILLO A.A., Valencia College, 2013 B.A., University of Central Florida, 2015 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the department of Interdisciplinary Studies in the College of Graduate Studies at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2017 Major Professor: Donald E. Jones ©2017 Manuel-Albert F. Castillo ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to show a transformation around the scientific revolution from the sixteenth to seventeenth centuries against a Whig approach in which it still lingers in the history of science. I find the transformations of modern science through the cosmological models of Nicholas Copernicus, Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Critical Physiognomy
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (No. 1) 2014 Daniel Wack [email protected] Wittgenstein’s Critical Physiognomy Abstract In saying that meaning is a physiognomy, Wittgenstein invokes a philosophical tradition of critical physiognomy, one that developed in opposition to a scientific physiognomy. The form of a critical physiognomic judgment is one of reasoning that is circular and dynamic, grasping intention, thoughts, and emotions in seeing the expressive movements of bodies in action. In identifying our capacities for meaning with our capacities for physiognomic perception, Wittgenstein develops an understanding of perception and meaning as oriented and structured by our shared practical concerns and needs. For Wittgenstein, critical physiognomy is both fundamental for any meaningful interaction with others and a capacity we cultivate, and so expressive of taste in actions and ways of living. In recognizing how fundamental our capacity for physiognomic perception is to our form of life Wittgenstein inherits and radicalizes a tradition of critical physiognomy that stretches back to Kant and Lessing. Aesthetic experiences such as painting, poetry, and movies can be vital to the cultivation of taste in actions and in ways of living. Introduction “Meaning is a physiognomy.” –Ludwig Wittgenstein (PI, §568) In claiming that meaning is a physiognomy, Wittgenstein appears to call on a discredited pseudo-science with a dubious history of justifying racial prejudice and social discrimination in order to 113 Daniel Wack BY-NC-SA elucidate his understanding of meaning. Physiognomy as a science in the eighteenth and nineteenth century aimed to provide a model of meaning in which outer signs serve as evidence for judgments about inner mental states.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Reversal of Soul Energy Fran De Aquino
    Quantum Reversal of Soul Energy Fran de Aquino To cite this version: Fran de Aquino. Quantum Reversal of Soul Energy. 2012. hal-01129313 HAL Id: hal-01129313 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01129313 Preprint submitted on 10 Mar 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Quantum Reversal of Soul Energy Fran De Aquino Maranhao State University, Physics Department, S.Luis/MA, Brazil. Copyright © 2012 by Fran De Aquino. All Rights Reserved. In the last decades, the existence of the Soul has been seriously considered by Quantum Physics. It has been frequently described as a body of unknown energy coupled to human body by means of a mutual interaction. The Quantum Physics shows that energy is quantized, i.e., it has discrete values that are defined as energy levels. Thus, along the life of a person, the energy of its soul is characterized by several quantum levels of energy. Here, we show by means of application of specific electromagnetic radiations on the human body, that it is possible to revert the energy of the soul to previous energy levels. This process can have several therapeutic applications.
    [Show full text]
  • 19 Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX a Support for the So-Called Second Oldest Or 'Mediaeval' Interpre
    Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX A support for the so-called second oldest or 'mediaeval' interpretation JOB VAN ECK Controversies regarding propositions about the future, occasioned by Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX have occurred throughout the history of logic from Antiquity to the 20th century, especially in the Middle Ages. The question under discussion is: must some such propositions be denied a truth value in order to escape determinism? Or does the law of bivalence also hold for future contingency propositions? And what is Aristotle's position in De Interpretatione IX? Does he say that bivalence implies determinism and thus abandons universal bivalence (this is called the oldest, or traditional, interpretation), or does he reconcile bivalence with indeterminism (the so-called second oldest in- terpretation). Boethius, in his two commentaries on De Interpretatione, shows himself a representantive of the second oldest interpretation. His main thesis is that according to Aristotle it is necessary for a future con- tingency proposition and its negation that one is true and the other false, but not definitely true, nor definitely false. In a recent article Pro- fessor Norman Kretzmann stressed the influence this point of view of Boethius has had on the subsequent discussion' . The second oldest interpretation became so prominent among mediaeval philosophers that some call it the mediaeval interpretation. In modern times most authors reject this interpretation, partly because the phrase "definitely true", which is at the heart of it, is rather obscure and its Greek analogue alêthes aphorismends does not oc- cur in De Interpretatione IX at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Verbal Communication: the First Chapters of De Interpretatione
    EJPC 7 (2) pp. 239–253 Intellect Limited 2016 Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 7 Number 2 © 2016 Intellect Ltd Critical Review. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.7.2.239_3 CRITICAL REVIEW ANITA KASABOVA Sofia University VLADIMIR MARINOV New Bulgarian University Aristotle on verbal communication: The first chapters of De Interpretatione ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This article deals with the communicational aspects of Aristotle’s theory of significa- Aristotle tion as laid out in the initial chapters of the De Interpretatione (Int.).1 We begin De Interpretatione by outlining the reception and main interpretations of the chapters under discussion, verbal communication rather siding with the linguistic strand. We then argue that the first four chap- signification ters present an account of verbal communication, in which words signify things via linguistic expressions thoughts. We show how Aristotle determines voice as a conventional and hence acci- convention dental medium of signification: words as ‘spoken sounds’ are tokens of thoughts, language use which in turn are signs or natural likenesses of things. We argue that, in this way, 1. We follow the standard linguistic expressions may both signify thoughts and refer to things. This double edition of the Greek account of signification also explains the variety of ontological, logical and psycho- text of Int. by Minio- logical interpretations of the initial chapters of Int. Paluello (1949: 47–72), unless otherwise stated. All references to Aristotle’s works 239 11_EJPC 7.2_Critical review article_239-253.indd 239 11/22/16 1:55 PM Anita Kasabova and Vladimir Marinov follow the citation 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Physics
    PROPOSAL : Aristotle’s Physics , A Critical Guide EditedbyMariskaLeunissen,TheUniversityofNorthCarolinaatChapelHill A. Project description The importance of Aristotle’s Physics : Throughout his life, Aristotle was deeply committed to the study of natural phenomena: about one third of the surviving Corpus Aristotelicum investigatesandexplainsthemotionsandattributesofthingsthathaveanature, that is, of things that have an internal principle of change and rest. The Physics – an intellectual masterpiece in itself and one of the mostlywidely readAristotelian treatises – forms Aristotle’s most fundamental treatise in his studies of natural philosophy. In this treatise,Aristotleinvestigatestheprinciplesandcausesofallnaturalthingsingeneral,and,in thecourseofdoingso,definesalargenumberofkeyconceptsofhisnaturalphilosophy, suchasmotionandchange,spaceandtime,matterandform,causalexplanation,luckand spontaneity, teleology and necessity. In addition, Aristotle specifies in the Physics the methodologicalguidelinesforhowoneshouldstudynatureifonewantstogainscientific knowledgeofit,whichincludesthefamousbutstillill-understoodrecommendationtostart fromthingsthatare“moreknownandclearertous”and towork fromthere towhat is “moreknownandclearerbynature”.Inthisway,the Physics laysoutAristotle’sconceptual apparatus and methodological framework for all of his natural philosophy, including his psychology,biology,andotherinquiriesintothemorespecificandmorecomplexsegments ofthenaturalworldpreservedinAristotle’sremainingnaturaltreatises. The Physics isnotjustrelevantforAristotle’snaturalphilosophy,however;sincetheobjects
    [Show full text]
  • From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category Is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected]
    REDESCRIPTIONS Sandford, Stella. 2019. “From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”?” Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory 22(1): 4–17. DOI: https://doi.org/10.33134/rds.314 RESEARCH From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected] This paper examines the nature of the categories of ‘male’ and ‘female’ as ­classificatory­groupings,­via­an­examination­of­this­question­in­Aristotle’s­zoology­ and­metaphysics.­Tracing­the­use­of­Aristotle’s­logical­categories­of­‘genus’­and­ ‘species’­in­his­zoological­works­and­contrasting­this­with­the­use­of­the­terms­ in­contemporary­taxonomy,­the­paper­demonstrates­that­‘male’­and­‘female’­are,­ in­a­significant­sense,­unclassifiable.­Although­Aristotle­has­no­generic­concept­of­ ‘sex’­at­his­disposal,­the­paper­shows­how­many­English­translations­of­his­works­ introduce­‘sex’­as­if­in­answer­to­the­question­of­the­nature­of­the­categories­of­ male­and­female.­The­paper­then­argues­that­the­generic­concept­of­sex­covers­ over­the­problem­of­the­classification­of­male­and­female­in­both­Aristotle­and­ contemporary­biology­(including­botany,­mycology­and­bacteriology),­by­introduc- ing­a­classificatory­genus­(‘sex’)­that­does­not­in­fact­explain­anything­but­rather­ (in­its­trans-species­generality)­needs­explaining. Keywords:­Sex;­male/female;­Aristotle;­biology;­taxonomy;­classification All living organisms that have been scientifically recorded or studied are named according to the relevant international code for nomenclature. Naming and denoting a taxonomical clas- sification are two sides of the same coin.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE and the IMPORTANCE of VIRTUE in the CONTEXT of the POLITICS and the NICOMACHEAN ETHICS and ITS RELATION to TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University
    Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses 2010 ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Anthony, Kyle Brandon, "ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY" (2010). Honors Theses. 21. https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses/21 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses at Bucknell Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Bucknell Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter 1 What does it mean to live a good life? 7 The virtuous life 8 Ethical virtue 13 Bravery as an ethical virtue 20 Justice 22 Chapter 2 The Politics and the ideal polis 28 Development of a polis 29 Features of an ideal polis 32 What does it mean to be a citizen of a polis? 40 Aristotle’s views on education 42 Social groups in a polis who are not recognized as citizens 45 Non-ideal political systems 51 Chapter 3 Connections between the Politics and the Ethics 57 Chapter 4 Difficulties in applying Aristotle’s theories to a modern setting 68 Conclusion Where do we go from here? 87 Bibliography 89 iv Acknowledgements First off, I have to thank God, as He helped me endure this project and gave me the courage to press on when I became frustrated, angry, and ready to quit.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works
    UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works Title The anthropology of incommensurability Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3vx742f4 Journal Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 21(2) ISSN 0039-3681 Author Biagioli, M Publication Date 1990 DOI 10.1016/0039-3681(90)90022-Z Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California MARIO BIAGIOLP’ THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF INCOMMENSURABILITY I. Incommensurability and Sterility SINCE IT entered the discourse of history and philosophy of science with Feyerabend’s “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism” and Kuhn’s The Structure of Scient$c Revolutions, the notion of incommensurability has problematized the debate on processes of theory-choice.’ According to Kuhn, two scientific paradigms competing for the explanation of roughly the same set of natural phenomena may not share a global linguistic common denominator. As a result, the possibility of scientific communication and dialogue cannot be taken for granted and the process of theory choice can no longer be reduced to the simple picture presented, for example, by the logical empiricists. By analyzing the dialogue (or rather the lack of it) between Galileo and the Tuscan Aristotelians during the debate on buoyancy in 1611-1613, I want to argue that incommensurability between competing paradigms is not just an unfortunate problem of linguistic communication, but it plays an important role in the process of scientific change and paradigm-speciation. The breakdown of communication during the
    [Show full text]
  • IS GOD in HEAVEN? John Morreall Religion Department the College of William and Mary
    IS GOD IN HEAVEN? John Morreall Religion Department The College of William and Mary 1. Introduction t first glance, this question may seem as silly as the quip “Is the Pope Catholic?” For in the Biblical traditions what Ais older and more accepted than the idea that God is in heaven? In his prayer dedicating the temple, Solomon says over and over, “Hear in heaven your dwelling place (I Kings 8:30, 32, 34, 36, 39, 43, 45, 49), and many Jewish prayers are addressed to God in heaven. The central prayer of Christians, composed by Jesus, begins, “Our Father, who art in heaven.” Both the Apostles’ Creed and the Nicene Creed say that Jesus ascended into heaven, where he is now “seated at the right hand of the Father.” What I will show, however, is that, far from being an obvious truth, the claim that God is in heaven is logically incoherent, and so necessarily false. I will begin by presenting four features of the traditional concept of heaven, two from the Hebrew Bible, and two from the New Testament and early Christianity. All of these features were developed at a time when God was thought of as a physical being. But, I will then argue, once Christians thought of God as nonphysical, the traditional concept of heaven was no longer acceptable. My argument is that: 1. Heaven is a place. 2. Only what is physical is located in a place. 3. God is not physical. 4. So God is not located in a place. 5. So God is not located in heaven.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being
    Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Author: Mark Sentesy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/2926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2012 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy ARISTOTLE: MOVEMENT AND THE STRUCTURE OF BEING a dissertation by MARK SENTESY submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2012 © copyright by MARK SENTESY 2012 Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Mark Sentesy Abstract: This project sets out to answer the following question: what does movement contribute to or change about being according to Aristotle? The first part works through the argument for the existence of movement in the Physics. This argument includes distinctive innovations in the structure of being, notably the simultaneous unity and manyness of being: while material and form are one thing, they are two in being. This makes it possible for Aristotle to argue that movement is not intrinsically related to what is not: what comes to be does not emerge from non‐being, it comes from something that is in a different sense. The second part turns to the Metaphysics to show that and how the lineage of potency and activity the inquiry into movement. A central problem is that activity or actuality, energeia, does not at first seem to be intrinsically related to a completeness or end, telos. With the unity of different senses of being at stake, Aristotle establishes that it is by showing that activity or actuality is movement most of all, and that movement has and is a complete end.
    [Show full text]
  • Luck and Good Fortune in the Eudemian Ethics
    Luck and Good Fortune in the EudemianEthics Kent Johnson Recentlythere has beensome discussion of Aristotle's treatmentof good for- tune(£\m>x;{a) in the penultimatechapter of the EudemianEthics. I Thereare two claims about this chapterI wish to challenge.One maintainsthat the use of the word tUXll (usuallytranslated as 'luck' or 'chance')in the EE is 'quite different' from Aristotle's theoretical discussion of luck, found in the Physics (Woods 1992,67). The other claim is that good fortune is a subspeciesof luck (Kenny 1992,ch. 5, esp.71 and 75). In challengingthese two views,I hopeto developan accountof Aristotle's true intent in this chapter.In the first part of this article I considerthe notion of luck asit is presentedin the Physicsand then argue that the discussionof luck in the EE accordswith this. In the secondpart I arguethat by the end of his discussionof good fortune in the EE, Aristotle doesnot consider good fortune to be any kind of luck at all. I. TuX1lin the Physicsand the EudemianEthics Woods 1992,166 denies that the useof 'luck' (tuX1l)in the EE agreeswith its usein the Physics,because in the PhysicstUX1l is usedin sucha way that 'to say that somethingoccurred by chancewill not be to give an explanation,but to deny that a general explanation is available'. Thus, there is 'no incompatibility betweensomething's occurring by chanceand its being caused',since chance is not a cause distinct from the four real causes(Woods 1992, 167). Instead, 'chanceoccurrences have the featurethat they fall underno law that holds uni- versallyor for the most part under the descriptionunder which theyare correctly said to occur by chance,though they will havesome explanation under another description'(166).
    [Show full text]