<<

PROPOSAL : ’s , A Critical Guide EditedbyMariskaLeunissen,TheUniversityofNorthCarolinaatChapelHill

A. Project description The importance of Aristotle’s Physics : Throughout his life, Aristotle was deeply committed to the study of natural phenomena: about one third of the surviving investigatesandexplainsthemotionsandattributesofthingsthathavea, that is, of things that have an internal principle of change and rest. The Physics – an intellectual masterpiece in itself and one of the mostlywidely readAristotelian treatises – forms Aristotle’s most fundamental treatise in his studies of natural . In this treatise,Aristotleinvestigatestheprinciplesandcausesofallnaturalthingsingeneral,and,in thecourseofdoingso,definesalargenumberofkeyconceptsofhisnaturalphilosophy, suchasmotionandchange,andtime,andform,causalexplanation,luckand spontaneity, and necessity. In addition, Aristotle specifies in the Physics the methodologicalguidelinesforhowoneshouldstudynatureifonewantstogainscientific knowledgeofit,whichincludesthefamousbutstillillunderstoodrecommendationtostart fromthingsthatare“moreknownandclearertous”and towork fromthere towhat is “moreknownandclearerbynature”.Inthisway,the Physics laysoutAristotle’sconceptual apparatus and methodological framework for all of his natural philosophy, including his psychology,biology,andotherinquiriesintothemorespecificandmorecomplexsegments ofthenaturalworldpreservedinAristotle’sremainingnaturaltreatises. The Physics isnotjustrelevantforAristotle’snaturalphilosophy,however;sincetheobjects ofdonot,forthemostpart,existindependentlyoftheobjectsofphysicsand canthusonlybestudiedthroughthose,thescienceofmetaphysicsoftenhastorelyonthe sameconcepts,definitions,andapproachesasarepresentedinthe Physics. The purpose of this volume: Becauseofthefoundationalroleofthe Physics forAristotle’s naturalphilosophyandmetaphysics,interestinthePhysics amongscholarsofAristotle(and ofancientphilosophymoregenerally)hasbeenconsistently high. Somewhat surprisingly, eventhoughthe Physics hasinspiredarichscholarlyliteratureintheformofbotharticlesand monographs,thereexistsonlyonevolumeofcollectedpapersthatfocusesexclusivelyonthe Physics :L.Judson(1991), Aristotle’s Physics, A Collection of Essays (Oxford:ClarendonPress). However, since the publication of this volume the field of Aristotlestudies has changed considerably,bothintermsofitsunderstandingofkeyconceptsinAristotle’sphilosophy and in terms of its preferred methods for gaining such understanding. It is time for a reassessment. Thepaperscommissionedforthisproposedvolumeaimtomakeoptimaluseofthesenew insightsandapproaches,andtherebytopushforwardthescholarshiponAristotle’s Physics. ThefourteenpapersonAristotle’s Physics inthisvolumeareexpectedtoengagewiththese changedperspectivesonAristotle inatleastoneofthefollowingthreeways:

1 (1) Reassessing the key concepts of Aristotle’s . First, some of the papers will provide a challenge to existing interpretations of someof the key concepts of Aristotle’s Physics (such as nature, cause, art, chance, and motion) and argue for alternative understandings . Thesepapersdonotonlydrawfromthelatestresearchinthefield,butalso exhibitagreatersensitivitytowardstherichnessandcomplexityofAristotelianconceptsas wellastowardstheextenttowhichAristotlebuildsonandreshapeshisconceptsindifferent explanatory contexts. Instead of just studying the main concepts of Aristotle’s natural philosophy in the immediate context in which they are first introduced in the Physics and tryingtoprovideaunifiedaccountoftheirdefinitionsandroles,thepaperspresentedinthis volumealsopayattentiontosomeofthe(methodologically)laterusestowhichtheconcepts are put in other (natural) treatises, provide explanations of why these other uses require conceptual changes, and answer the metaquestion aboutwhyAristotle needs the specific understandingsof,forinstance,hisconceptsofnatureandcauseforhisnaturalphilosophy asawhole. (2) Reconstructing Aristotle’s methods for the study of nature. Second,someofthepaperswilltryto provideareconstructionofthemethodsAristotleuses and/or describes for the study of nature.ScholarsworkingonAristotlehavebecomeincreasinglyinterestedintherelationship betweenAristotle’s‘geometricstyle’theoryofscientificdemonstrationandinvestigationas presentedinthe andhispracticeinthenaturaltreatises,andalthoughmuch workhasbeendoneonthemethodologicalconnectionsbetweenthe Posterior Analytics and Aristotle’sbiology (i.e., his studyof living nature),the connectionswithhis Physics remain largelyunexploredterritory.Thepapersinthisvolumeaimtoworktowardsclosingthisgap in the existing scholarship by offering interpretations of (a) what it means according to Aristotletoinvestigatethings physikôs – i.e.,inthemannerofanaturalscientist;(b)howthis method relates to other methods available to a philosopher (such as semantic analysis or dialectic)aswellastothescientificmethodoutlinedinthe Posterior Analytics ;and(c)how methodologicalconcernsstemmingfromthe Posterior Analytics drivetheinvestigationsinthe Physics . (3) Determining the boundaries of Aristotle’s natural philosophy. Third, some papers will concern themselves with the boundaries (and the extent to which these boundaries are crossed) betweenAristotle’snaturalphilosophyandhismetaphysics.Inrecentyears,therehasbeena growing awareness among scholars of Aristotle that Aristotle’s full views can rarely be pluckedoutofsinglepassages,orevensingletreatises.Thishasledtomodificationsinhow webelieveoneshouldconductconceptualanalysisinAristotle(e.g.,astakingintoaccount the different uses to which concepts are put in differentpartsofascience,asdescribed under item number 1 above), but it has also highlighted concerning Aristotle’s division of the sciences and his requirement that principles that belong properly to one sciencecannotbeusedinthegenerationofknowledgeinanotherscience(unlessthetwo sciencesaresubordinatedtoeachother).Forthisvolume,theissueconcerningtherelation betweenthedifferentsciencesarisesmostprominentlywithregardtoAristotle’sconceptof the Unmoved (or Prime) Mover – the origin of all motion in the – which he

2 introducesin Physics VIII.SincethisUnmovedMoverisadivinebeingthatispureformand iswithoutmatter,itistechnicallyspeakingnotpartofthephysicalworld,butratherbelongs toAristotle’s‘firstphilosophy’ormetaphysics.Thepapersinthisvolumeexaminetheways in which Physics VIII divides up the science of nature and his metaphysics, and how his account in the Physics relates to a similar, but also importantly different discussion of unmovedmoversin Metaphysics XII. B. Audience Theproposedvolumeaimstobringtogethercuttingedgeresearchpapers,writtenbysome ofthebestscholarscurrentlyworkingonAristotle’snaturalscience,andtherebytoproduce avolumethatreflectstherecentdevelopmentsinthefieldbutalsoopensupnewavenuesof inquiry. The primary audience for this volume will be scholars and advanced graduate studentsinancientphilosophy.Thevolumewillbeanessentialreadingandkeyresourcefor allthoseworkingonAristotle.However,thevolumewillappealmorebroadlytoscholars workinginancientphilosophyaswellastothoseworkinginthehistoryandphilosophyof (natural)science,giventhecentralityofthenotions and methods discussed in Aristotle’s Physics for his entire philosophy and their influence on the development of natural philosophyinlaterAntiquity(includingtheNeoplatonicperiod)andintheEarlyModern period. C. Timetable The papers commissioned for this volume are all original and have not been published elsewhere. Authors will submit the first complete drafts of their papers to the editor by March15,2013,afterwhichtheywillreceivecomments.Thedraftswillberevisedduring thesummerof2013,andthecompletemanuscriptwillbesubmittedtoCUPforreviewno laterthanSeptember1 st ,2013.Themanuscriptshouldbereadyfortheproductionprocess sometimeduringthefallof2013. D. Information about the editor and the contributing authors MariskaLeunissen,theproposededitorforthisvolume,iscurrentlyassistantprofessorof philosophyattheUniversityofNorthCarolinaatChapelHill.Fromfall2007tospring2011 she was assistant professor at Washington University in St. Louis, and from fall 2010 to spring2011sheheldaresidentialfellowshipattheHarvardUniversity’sCenterforHellenic studiesinWashington,D.C.Sheistheauthorof Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature (CUP2010;oneofthreefinalistsforthe Journal of the History of Philosophy 2011book prize),coeditorof Interpreting Aristotle’s PosteriorAnalytics in Late Antiquity and Beyond (Brill, Leiden2010),andhaswrittenseveralarticlesonAristotle’stheoryofdemonstration,natural science,andcharacter.

3 Thescholarswhohaveagreedtocontributetothisvolumewereallselectedonthebasisof theirindividualexpertiseinthefieldofAristotle’snaturalscience.All–includingthemore juniorscholars–havepublishedpreviouslyonAristotle’snaturalscience,eitherintheform ofarticlesbutalsoofmonographsoreditedvolumes.Asagroup,theyrepresentthecurrent diversity in Aristotelian scholarship in terms of their distribution in gender, geographical locationoftheirhomeinstitution,nationality,andrank. Thisisthefulllistofcontributorstothevolume: James Allen isProfessorofAncientGreekandRomanPhilosophyattheUniversityof Pittsburgh,U.S.A.

Robert Bolton isProfessorofPhilosophyatRutgers–TheStateUniversityofNewJersey, U.S.A

David Charles isColinPrestigeFellowandResearchProfessorinPhilosophyatOriel College,OxfordUniversity,U.K.

Ursula Coope isProfessorofAncientPhilosophyandFellowofCorpusChristiCollege, OxfordUniversity,U.K.

Andrea Falcon isAssociateProfessorofPhilosophyatConcordiaUniversity,Canada

Devin Henry isAssistantProfessorofPhilosophyatTheUniversityofWesternOntario, Canada

Sean Kelsey isAssociateProfessorofPhilosophyattheUniversityofNotreDame,U.S.A.

James G. Lennox isProfessorofHistoryandPhilosophyofScienceattheUniversityof Pittsburgh,U.S.A.

Jacob Rosen isJuniorResearcherinPhilosophy(TOPOIExcellencecluster)atthe HumboldtUniversity,Berlin.

Diana Quarantotto isProfessoreAggregatoattheUniversityofRome,Italy

Margaret Scharle isAssociateProfessorofPhilosophyatReedCollege,U.S.A.

Stasinos Stavrianeas isAssistantProfessorattheUniversityofPatras,Greece

Charlotte Witt isProfessorofPhilosophyattheUniversityofNewHampshire,U.S.A.

4 E. Chapter titles and abstracts Therewillbefourteenchapters,plusanintroduction.Eachpaper,withtheexceptionofthe introduction, will be maximally 8500 words long. The complete manuscript will be maximally125000wordslong.

Introduction Author: MariskaLeunissen(TheUniversityofNorthCarolinaatChapelHill,U.S.A.) Chapter : The Method of the Natural Scientist Author: JamesG.Lennox(UniversityofPittsburgh,U.S.A.) Abstract: Thispaperdiscusseswhatitmeans,precisely,tocarryouta methodos physikôs , i.e.inthemannerofanaturalscientist.Thepapertakesofffrompassagesin Physics I1, I1,and Metaphysics VI1thatdiscussthenaturalmethodofinquiryandthewayin whichthemathematiciandiffersinhismethodfromthestudentofnature(althoughboth studythesameobjects,thefirststudiestheirattributesasseparablefromthoseobjectsbyan effortofabstractionandasunchangeable,whereasthelatterstudiesthemasenmatteredand as subjected to change). I shall explain what is meant by the ‘teleological integration’ of matterandformofnaturalobjects(buildingontheintroductionofthisconceptinLennox 2008), and show what the methodological consequences are of taking such a position towardsnaturalobjectsforthestudentofnature.Inthenextpartofthepaper,Irange aroundinthevariousnaturaltreatisestoshowwhatsuchamethodlookslikeinpractice.

Chapter 2 The Role of Semantics in Author: DianaQuarantotto(UniversityofRome,Italy) Abstract: In Physics bookIAristotlebeginshisinvestigation“aboutnature”( peri physeos ) –aninvestigationwhosestatusandpossibilitywereconsideredcontroversial,atleastfrom theperspectiveoftheEleaticclaimthatbeingisoneandimmovable.Thebeginningofthis investigationisforusparticularlydifficulttounderstand.ItisunclearhowexactlyAristotle understood the problem of becoming and being as presented by his predecessors, and thereforewhatAristotle’sownsolutionamountsto.Moreover,itisunclearwhatthefield andtheobjectsoftheinvestigationthemselvesare,thatis,whethertheyactuallybelongto thescienceofnature,giventhatAristotlepaysconsiderableattentiontolanguageandmakes frequent use of linguistic analysis. On these issues, several interpretations have been proposed:forinstance,thatAristotleconfusestherealmsoflanguageandthoughtandthe realmofreality;orthatAristotleisarealistandthinksthatlanguagemirrorsrealitydirectly andperfectly;oreventhatAristotleisan ante-litteram phenomenologist.Thispapertackles this issue heads on by means of an analysis of Physics I 23 where this problem is most glaring. I shall argue that Aristotle’s critique of the Eleatic thesis that being is one and unchangeableiscarriedoutfromasemanticandpropositionalpointofview:itisthrough thegenerationofsemanticmeaningandtheuseofpropositional structures thatAristotle demonstratestheimpossibilityforbeingtobeoneinthesenseproposedbytheEleatics.In

5 addition, I shall offer some considerations of what role semantics plays according to Aristotleinthemethodofinvestigationintothescienceofnature.

Chapter 3 Aristotle’s Account of Substantial Change in Physics I 58 Author: DevinHenry(UniversityofWesternOntario,Canada) Abstract: ThispaperwillexploreAristotle’saccountofcomingtobein Physics I58. Aristotle’saccountcanbedividedintotwoparts.Thefirstpart( Physics I57)developsthe basic theory according to which all comingtobe involves three principles, an underlying subjectandapairofcontraries(formandprivation)whichrepresentthetwo‘poles’ofthe change.Thesecondpart( Physics I8)defendsthisaccountagainsttheEleatics,whoargued thatcomingtobeisimpossiblebecauseitrequirestheexistenceofnonbeing.Inthispaper I shall explore two controversial aspects of this theory. First, I will challenge the long standingassumptionthatAristotlethinksthatallchangerequiresanunderlyingsubjectthat endurestheprocessandremainsasaconstituentofthefinishedproduct.Specifically,Ishall argue that Physics I 7 does not commit Aristotle to the view that substantial generation requiresapersistentsubject.Second,IshallshowhowAristotle’sresponsetotheEleatics defends the account of nonbeing from ’s Sophist using the conceptual machinery developedinthe Analytics .Thisissomethingthathasnotbeennoticedbyscholars.

Chapter 4 Aristotle’s Definition of Nature as a SecondLevel Potentiality Author: StasinosStavrianeas(UniversityofPatras,Greece) Abstract: ThispaperoffersanewinterpretationofAristotle’sdefinitionofnaturein Physics bookIIbyexamininghowtheclaimsthatprecedethisdefinitionpavethewayforit andbyaddressingcertainconcernsrelatingtothenecessityandsufficiencyofthecriterion proposed in this definition. I argue that Aristotle’s description of the substratum as ‘an ungeneratedpotentiality’thatisessentiallyrelatedtowhatwillbetheresultofthechange leadstoanunderstandingofnaturenotasanefficientcause,but(followinganinterpretation proposed already by Simplicius) as a secondlevel potentiality responsive to principled processesthatconstitutecompleteactivities.Theargumentproceedsinthreesteps.First,I turn tothe analysis of the nature of elemental bodies in order to show that their passive principle of motion qualifies as being a nature.This means that their movement must be conceivedasacompleteactivity,giventhattheelementsareactiveprinciplesoftheirmutual transformations and not in need of a further active principle determining their respective motions.Ithenarguethatananalysisofartisticprocesses–whichareincompleteactivities– leadsnecessarilytoaseparationoftheprincipleofchangeandofthethingchanged.Finally, Iturntolivingbeingsandshowthatsuchaseparationofagentandpatientofchangedoes notapplytothem.Consequently,bothAristotle’sargumentsinthe Physics andhisaccountof generationinthe allowlivingbeingstobepatientsaswellaspossessors oftheirownprincipleofchangeandrest.

6 Chapter 5 “The Representation of Nature” Author: SeanKelsey(UniversityofNotreDame,U.S.A.) Abstract: ElsewhereIconsiderthecontentofAristotle’sdefinitionofnature(first half of Physics II1);hereIproposetoconsideritsfunction.Why does Aristotle think it importantto“define”nature(tosay“what”nature“is”)?Whatmileagedoeshehopetoget fromtheparticulardefinitionheoffers?Whatusedoesheputitto?Thesequestionsarise becausewhenAristotleappealstothedefinition—whichhedoesnotoftendoin Physics II— it is usually to remark that certain things fall outside the purview of natural science (e.g. 198a35b1).Butthedefinitioncanhardlyfunctionmerelytosettletheextensionofτὰφύσει ὄντα;onthecontrary,itiselicitedfromthisextension(192b8ff.).Moreover,Aristotledoes not appeal to the definition—at leastnotexplicitly—in thosecontexts inwhichwewould mostexpecthimtodoso,namely,whenexplaininganddefendingthemostcharacteristic anddistinctiveaspectsofhisconceptionofnatureandnaturalscience:e.g.inthesecondhalf of Physics II1(formandmatterarebothnature—exceptionsare193a2930andb34,where itisvirtuallyidle),in Physics II2(thescienceofnaturemusttreatofbothformandmatter), and in Physics II 8 (nature is a final cause—an exception being a snatch of reasoning at 199b1325,thatdoesadverttothedefinition,albeitbriefly).Inaword,thedefinitionappears lessfoundationalthanweexpect.Thissuggeststhatsomethingisamiss(perhapswiththe appearance, perhaps with the expectation); the idea of the paper is to try to getto the bottomofthis. Chapter 6 Aristotle’s Conception of Author: RobertBolton(RutgersUniversity,U.S.A.) Abstract: MuchworkhasbeendoneonAristotle’sunderstandingofhistheoryoffour causes,especiallyregardingtheirontologicalstatus–thatis,whetherthesecausesconstitute ‘real causes’ or should ratherbe considered as mere ‘epistemic reasons why’. This paper examinesAristotle’stheoryofthefourcausesfromamorepragmaticperspective,namely: Why does Aristotle need four causes? What conception – or conceptions – of a cause is Aristotleworkingwithandwhatinterrelationsamongthecausesdoesheintroduceinorder tomakethisnotion(whichatleastfirstseemsratherforeigntous)intelligible?

Chapter 7 Chance as a Byproduct of Natural Teleology Author: JamesAllen(UniversityofPittsburgh,U.S.A.) Abstract: Chance, which Aristotle sometimes divides into two species, luck ( tyche ), operativeintherealmofhumanagency,anditscounterpartinthebroadernaturalworld,the automaticorspontaneous,figuresprominentlyinhisdefenseofnaturalteleology.Hisown positionissomethingofabalancingact.Accordingtoaviewwidespreadatthetime,lucky events are the result of divine intervention in the natural order. Tyche or Fortuna was worshipedasagoddesswhoactsonbehalfofherfavorites.Thoughthedivineexistsandis acauseinAristotle’suniverse,thereisnoplaceinitfordivinemeddlingby‘supernatural’ agentsofthiskind.Againstthisview,Aristotleisconcernedtoshowthatchance,ifthereis suchathing,mustbepartofthenaturalorderandexplicablewithintheframeworkofthe four causes. Of more pressing concern to him, however, are the views of some of his

7 philosophicalpredecessors,whoseethecosmicorderandthebeneficialarrangementsthat are everywhere in evidence within it as products of chance, above all members of the biological species,which are organic unities inwhich mutually dependent functional parts contributetothegoodofthewhole.Theseare,ofcourse,preciselytheitemsthatcanonly, according to Aristotle, be understood teleologically, with the aid of final causes. Chance, then, is the alternative tofinal causal explanation,whichAristotleisdeterminedtoreject. Thisisnot,however,becauseheagreeswithotherswhomaintainthatnothingoccursby chance because everything has a cause of some sort. Instead, on the interpretation of Aristotle’sownaccountofchanceasacausebydefendedhere,itisaninevitable byproduct of final causation and unintelligible apart from it. If Aristotle is right, chance events are a marginal exception to the teleological rule that prevails in nature, and at the sametimeaproofofit.

Chapter 8 The Ontology of Artifacts in Aristotle’s Physics Author: CharlotteWitt(UniversityofNewHampshire,U.S.A.) Abstract: Inthe Physics Aristotledistinguishesartifactsfromnaturalbeings,notingthat thelatterhaveaninternaloriginofmotionandrest,whichartifactslack.Still,itisstriking that artifacts are frequently used as examples in the passages of the Physics that introduce importantideaslikematterandform,whichsuggeststhattheyareontologicallysimilarto natural substances at least in some respects. However, most commentators agree that artifacts do not count as substances, although there are significant differences in the explanations given. Some argue that artifacts lack the unity of true substances (Kosman), others think that it is an artifacts inability to reproduce that is key (Katayama), and still othersthinkitisthefactthatartifactsarenotselfregulating(Shields).InthispaperIfocus on the context of Aristotle’s discussion of artifacts in the Physics to show how truly problematic the idea is that artifacts are not substances at all and to try to develop a compromiseinterpretation.Beingasubstancecomesindegrees,andartifactsaresubstances toadegree.

Chapter 9 On processes Author: DavidCharles(OxfordUniversity,U.K.) Abstract : Myaimistosetoutandengagewiththeongoingdebateonthenatureof processes, considering the views held by Kosman, Broadie, and Coope on one side and Ross,Heinaman,andmeontheother.Ishallfocusonprocessesascontinuants,understood asunfoldingsthroughtime,andcomparethemwithothercontinuants(suchassubstances andactivities).Inadditionto Physics III1,Ishallalsoconsiderpartsof Metaphysics Theta.

8 Chapter 0 and the topology of change: Physics V–VI

Author: JacobRosen(HumboldtUniversity,Berlin) Abstract: In Physics V–VI,Aristotleattemptstoprovideatheoryofcontinua:boththe temporallyextendedsort(changes)andthespatiallyextendedsort(bodies,lines,etc.).The treatise was historically influential, but its mathematical basis has been superseded by differential calculus and set theory; nowadays it is famous for its testimony about Zeno's paradoxesofmotion,butreceiveslittlesystematicattentioninitsownright.Itrytoattainan overview of the treatise from two angles. First, its deductive structure. The text shows ambitions of being a mathematical treatise with definitions, axioms and theorems; but its actualorganizationisnotsoneat(forexample,severalclaimsarearguedforintwodifferent waysintwodifferentchapters)anditissometimeshardtodeterminewhatissupposedtobe derivedfromwhat.Itrytoproducesomeorder.Second,itsconnectionswiththerestofthe corpus. In some ways the treatise makes an isolated impression, offering distinctions and claimswhichdonotevidentlyserveanylargerpurposeinAristotle'sphilosophy.Yetonthe other hand, it promises to provide an important link between mathematical and (meta)physicalissuesasAristotletellsusin GC I2,itmakesagreatdifferencetoone's theoryofgeneration,perishing,andalterationwhetherornotoneisanatomist,and Physics V–VI is his most sustained argument for, and elaboration of, an antiatomist picture. I consider where the treatise is implicitly or explicitly relied on in other works, as well as lookingtoseewhereitsresultsareoverlookedorcontradicted.

Chapter Aristotle’s Account of Change and Virtues in Physics VII 3 Author: MariskaLeunissen(TheUniversityofChapelHill,U.S.A.) Abstract: In Physics VII3,Aristotlearguesthatqualitativechange,whichisoneofthe fourstandardmodesofchangehedistinguishes,onlybelongstothingsthatareaffectedin and by themselves by perceptible things. Somewhat surprisingly, he also claims that ‘conditions’ – such as thevirtues ofthe bodyor soul – do notbelong tothe categoryof ‘quality’ and do not come to be as a result of qualitativechange,butthattheyarerather ‘somekindofperfections’( Ph VII3,246a13)that‘existinvirtueofaparticularrelation’( Ph VII 3, 246b8), thereby seemingly introducing a fifth type of change. In this paper, I will analyzeAristotle’saccountofthevirtuesinthe Physics andshowhowitoffersaphysiological andnaturalisticexplanationforhisaccountofhabituationinthe . Inthis treatise, it is argued that, even though human beings are by nature able to receive moral virtues, those virtues do not come to be by nature, but are ‘made perfect’ through habituation( NE II1,1103a2326),andthatthechangethattakesplaceduringhabituationis different from the one involved in the realization of natural capacities (which constitute qualitativechanges)aswellasfromtheoneinvolvedinlearningaskill(whichdonotrequire thedevelopmentoftherightmotivations,astheacquisitionofvirtuedoes;see NE II14). Only in the Physics, however, do we learn what kind of change is involved in moral development.

9 Chapter 2 Aristotle on the Boundary between Physics and Metaphysics Author: MargaretScharle(ReedCollege,U.S.A.) Abstract: Posterior Analytics I28maintainsthatasinglescienceisascienceofonekind (87a3840),sothestrictnessoftheboundarybetweenonescienceandanotherdependson the strictness of the boundarybetween one kind and another.Physics VIII argues for the distinction between two kinds of substances—natural substance and immovable substance—that mark off the boundary between physics and metaphysics. Physics II.2 characterizesthedistinctionbetweenphysicsandmetaphysicsbythefactthattheformeris concernedwithcompositesofmatterandform,whilethelatterconcernsseparableform(s). Physics II’sdistinctionrestsongroundsanalogoustothosefoundintheargumentof Physics VIII. I argue that Physics II’s conception of the distinction between composites and separableform(s)dependsontheimpossibilityofsomething’sbeingitsownnature.That would be tantamount to something’s being in itself primarily, which would require somethingtobecontainerandcontainedwithrespect to the same contents ( Physics IV.3 210b823). Likewise, Physics VIII’s distinction between natural and immovable substance restsontheimpossibilityofsomething’sbeingbothagentandpatientwithrespecttothe same motion. I thereby argue that there is a philosophically rich a priori issue at stake in Aristotle’s distinction between science and metaphysics, and I show how this issue distinguishedAristotlefromhisforemostpredecessors,Platoand.

Chapter 3 Aristotle’s Account of SelfMotion in Physics VIII Author : UrsulaCoope(OxfordUniversity,UK) Abstract: In Physics VIII5,Aristotlesetshimselfthequestion:ifathingmovesitself,in whatwaydoesitdoso?Hearguesthatwhenathingmovesitself,thereisonepartofitthat isthemoverandanotherpartofitthatismoved(257a1213).Inmypaper,Ishallexamine, indetail,Aristotle’sargumentsforthisclaimand shalldiscusssomequestionsabouttheir largersignificance.Inparticular,shallexaminethefollowingthreequestions:(i)Theextent towhichAristotle’sviewsaboutselfmotiondepartfromorareconsistentwithPlato’s.(For instance,accordingtoonelater,neoplatonistview,Aristotle’sargumentsdependonthefact thatthekindofmotionheisconsideringisthemotionofa bodily thing–somethingthatis infinitelydivisible–soAristotlecouldagreewithPlatothatasoulmightbeabletoacton itselfasawhole.)(ii)WhetherAristotle’sargumentfortheexistenceofselfmotiondepends onaparticularaccountofmotionorchange(andifso,whataccountitpresupposes).And (iii) whether Aristotle’s argument provides any resources for distinguishing between a genuineselfmoverandapairofthings:anexternalunmovedmoverandthemovedthing whosemotionitcauses.

Chapter 4 A Scientific Study of Eternal Motion in Physics VIII Author: AndreaFalcon(ConcordiaUniversity,Canada) Abstract: Thestandardinterpretationisthat Physics VIIIisanargumentintwostages from the eternity of motion to the existence of a prime mover which is eternal and unmoved.Interestinglyenough,thisisnotquitewhatwearetoldintheopeninglinesofthe De Motu Animalium. There,Aristotle makes contact with Physics VIII. He tells us that the

10 investigationconductedin Physics VIIIunfoldsintwostages.Butthetwostageshehasin mindarenotthosepresentedinthestandardinterpretation.Rather,theyarethoseoutlined attheoutsetofthesecondbookofthe Posterior Analytics . More directly, his investigation beginswiththequestion ei esti (isthereeternalmotion?).Onceitisestablishedthatthereis eternalmotion,thisinvestigationcontinueswiththequestion ti esti (whatiseternalmotion?). Atthissecondstage,Aristotlelooksforascientificdefinitionofeternalmotionbyengaging insearchforitscauses.Anditisinthiscontextthatafirstprincipleofmotionthatisnot itselfsubjecttomotionisintroduced.Thelatterenterstheexplanationofeternalmotionas thefirstunmovedmover.Thatin Physics VIIIAristotleis,atleastinprinciple,committedto the method outlined in the Posterior Analytics is not sufficiently appreciated. Many, if not most,scholarsstillagreewithG.E.L.Owen,whoopenedhisimmenselyinfluentialarticle “TithenaitaPhainomena”(1961) 1withthefollowingstatement:“thereseemstobeasharp discrepancybetweenthemethodofscientificreasoningrecommendedinthe Analytics and those actually followed in the Physics. ” I propose a close textual study of the argument advancedin Physics VIIIItoestablishtowhatextentitreflectsthetheoryofscienceoutlined inthe Posterior Analytics.

1 Owen,G.E.L.(1961),‘TithenaitaPhainomena’,in:S.Mansion(ed.), Aristote et les problèmes de méthode. Papers of the Second Symposium Aristotelicum .Louvain,1961,83103.

11