<<

pdf version of the entry Feminist Political http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/feminism-political/ from the Summer 2014 Edition of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen R. Lanier Anderson Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor Editorial Board http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html

Library of Congress Catalog Data ISSN: 1095-5054

Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries, please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ .

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Copyright c 2013 by the publisher

The Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 Feminist Copyright c 2014 by the author

No¨elleMcAfee All rights reserved. Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/ Feminist Political Philosophy First published Sun Mar 1, 2009; substantive revision Tue Apr 1, 2014

Feminist political philosophy is an area of philosophy that is in part focused on understanding and critiquing the way political philosophy is usually construed—often without any attention to feminist concerns—and on articulating how political theory might be reconstructed in a way that advances feminist concerns. Feminist political philosophy is a branch of both feminist philosophy and political philosophy. As a branch of feminist philosophy, it serves as a form of critique or a of suspicion (Ricœur 1970). That is, it serves as a way of opening up or looking at the political world as it is usually understood and uncovering ways in which women and their current and historical concerns are poorly depicted, represented, and addressed. As a branch of political philosophy, feminist political philosophy serves as a field for developing new ideals, practices, and justifications for how political institutions and practices should be organized and reconstructed.

While feminist philosophy has been instrumental in critiquing and reconstructing many branches of philosophy, from to , feminist political philosophy may be the paradigmatic branch of feminist philosophy because it best exemplifies the point of , which is, to borrow a phrase from Marx, not only to understand the world but to change it (Marx and Engels 1998). And, though fields have effects that may change the world, feminist political philosophy focuses most directly on understanding ways in which collective life can be improved. This project involves understanding the ways in which power emerges and is used or misused in public life (see the entry on feminist perspectives on power). As with other kinds of feminist theory, common themes have emerged for discussion and critique, but there has been little in the way of consensus among feminist

1 Feminist Political Philosophy theorists on what is the best way to understand them. This introductory article lays out the various schools of thought and areas of concern that have occupied this vibrant field of philosophy for the past forty years. It understands feminist philosophy broadly to include work conducted by feminist theorists doing this philosophical work from other disciplines, especially political science but also anthropology, comparative literature, law, and other programs in the humanities and social sciences.

1. Historical Context and Developments 2. Contemporary Approaches and Debates 2.1 Liberal 2.2 Radical, Socialist, and Marxist 2.3 Feminisms 2.4 Diversity Feminisms 2.5 Performative Feminisms Bibliography Academic Tools Other Internet Resources Related Entries

1. Historical Context and Developments

Current feminist political philosophy is indebted to the work of earlier generations of feminist scholarship and activism, including the first wave of feminism in the English-speaking world, which took place from the 1840s to the 1920s and focused on improving the political, educational, and economic system primarily for middle-class women. Its greatest achievements were to develop a language of equal rights for women and to garner women the right to vote. It is also indebted to the second wave of feminism, which, beginning in the 1960s, drew on the language of the civil rights movements (e.g., the language of liberation) and on a new

2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee feminist consciousness that emerged through women's solidarity movements and new forms of reflection that uncovered sexist attitudes and impediments throughout the whole of society. As the entry on approaches to feminism notes, by 1970 feminism had expanded from activism to scholarship with the publication of 's The of Sex (Firestone 1971); 's (Millett 1970); and Robin Morgan's Sisterhood is Powerful (Morgan 1970).

One of the first theoretical advances of second wave feminism was to separate out biological conceptions of women's identity from socially- constructed ones in order to disprove the notion that biology was destiny and hence that women's main role was as and caregivers. Drawing on the social sciences and psychoanalytic theory, anthropologist developed an account of a “sex/ system” (Ruben 1975; Dietz 2003, 401; and the entry on feminist perspectives on sex and gender). The sex/gender distinction pointed to “a set of arrangements by which the biological raw material of human sex and procreation is shaped by human, social intervention” (Rubin 1975, 165). While biological sex was fixed, in Rubin's view, gender was a social construction that served to divide the sexes and privilege men. Because gender was mutable, the sex/gender distinction gave feminists a powerful tool to look for ways to address women's oppression.

With this socially-constructed notion of gender, early second-wave theorists sought out an understanding of as a universal subject and agent of feminist politics. Just as Marxist theory sought out a universal subject in the person of the worker, feminists theorists sought it out in a shared and common condition that afflicted women across cultures. But this notion of a universal womanhood was interrupted by other thinkers, such as , saying that it excluded non-white and non-middle-class women's and concerns. Hooks' 1981 book titled Ain't I a Woman? exposed mainstream feminism as a movement of a small group

Summer 2014 Edition 3 Feminist Political Philosophy of middle- and upper-class white women whose experience was very particular, hardly universal. The work of hooks and later Cherrie Moraga, Gloria Anzaldúa, Maria Lugones, Elizabeth Spelman, and others foregrounded the need to account for women's multiple and complex identities and . By the 1990s the debates about whether there was a coherent concept of woman that could underlie feminist politics was further challenged by non-Western women challenging the Western women's movement as caught up in Eurocentric ideals that led to the colonization and domination of “Third World” people. So what is now known as postcolonial theory further heightened the debate between feminist who wanted to identify universal feminist subject of woman (e.g. Okin, Nussbaum, and Ackerly) and those who call for recognizing multiplicity, diversity, and (e.g., Spivak, Narayan, Mahmood, and Jaggar).

The effects of this diversity movement would be felt more in the 1990s and beyond. In the meantime, in the 1970s and 1980s feminist theory began to develop in the various areas of the social sciences and humanities, and in philosophy it began to arise in what were already the different traditions and areas of research. As a branch of political philosophy, feminist political philosophy has often mirrored the various divisions at work in political philosophy more broadly. Prior to the fall of the Berlin Wall and the end of the Cold War, political philosophy was usually divided into categories such as liberal, conservative, socialist, and Marxist. Except for , for each category there were often feminists working and critiquing alongside it. Hence, as 's classic text, Feminist Politics and Human Nature, spelled out, each ideological approach drew feminist scholars who would both take their cue from and borrow the language of a particular ideology (Jaggar 1983). Jaggar's text grouped feminist political philosophy into four camps: , , , and . The first three groups followed the lines of Cold War global political

4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee divisions: American liberalism, European , and a revolutionary communism (though few in the west would embrace Soviet-style communism). Radical feminism was the most indigenous of the feminist , developing its own political vocabulary with its roots in the deep criticisms of that feminist consciousness had produced in its first and second waves. Otherwise, feminist political philosophy largely followed the lines of traditional political philosophy. But this has never been an uncritical following. As a field bent on changing the world, even liberal feminist theorists tended to criticize liberalism as much or more than they embraced it, and to embrace socialism and other more radical points of view more than to reject them. Still, on the whole, these theorists generally operated within the language and framework of their chosen approach to political philosophy.

Political philosophy began to change enormously in the late 1980s, just before the end of the Cold War, with a new invocation of an old Hegelian category: civil society, an arena of political life intermediate between the state and the household. This was the arena of associations, churches, labor unions, book clubs, choral societies and manifold other nongovernmental yet still public organizations. In the 1980s political theorists began to turn their focus from the state to this intermediate realm, which suddenly took center stage in Eastern Europe in organizations that challenged the power of the state and ultimately led to the downfall of communist regimes.

After the end of the Cold War, political philosophy along with political life radically realigned. New attention focused on civil society and the public sphere, especially with the timely translation of Jürgen Habermas's early work, the Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (Habermas 1989). Volumes soon appeared on civil society and the public sphere, focusing on the ways in which people organized themselves and developed public power rather than on the ways that the state garnered and

Summer 2014 Edition 5 Feminist Political Philosophy exerted its power. In fact, there arose a sense that the public sphere ultimately might exert more power than the state, at least in the fundamental way in which public is formed and serves to legitimate— or not—state power. In the latter respect, 's work was influential by developing a theory of that tied the legitimacy of institutions to the normative judgments that a reflective and deliberative people might make (Rawls 1971). By the early 1990s, Marxists seemed to have disappeared or at least become very circumspect (though the downfall of communist regimes needn't have had any effect on Marxist proper, which never subscribed to Leninist or Maoist thought). Socialists also retreated or transformed themselves into “radical democrats” (Mouffe 1992, 1993, 2000).

Now the old schema of liberal, radical, socialist, and Marxist feminisms were much less relevant. There were fewer debates about what kind of state organization and economic structure would be better for women and more debates about the value of the the private sphere of the household and the nongovernmental space of associations. Along with political philosophy more broadly, more feminist political philosophers began to turn to the meaning and interpretation of civil society, the public sphere, and democracy itself.

2. Contemporary Approaches and Debates

Now in the second decade of the twenty-first century, feminist theorists are doing an extraordinary variety of work on matters political and democratic, including global , human rights, disabilities studies, bioethics, climate change, and international development. (See the entry on topics in feminism.) Some of the tensions that came to the fore in previous decades are played out in any of these areas.

For example, in global ethics there is a debate over whether there are

6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee universal values of justice and freedom that should be intentionally cultivated for women in the developing world or whether cultural diversity should be prized. Feminist theorists have sought to answer this question in a number of different and compelling ways. (For some examples see Ackerly 2000, Ackerly & Okin 1999, Benhabib 2002 and 2008, Butler 2000, Gould 2004, and Zerilli 2009.)

Likewise new philosophical work on disabilities, as the entry on feminist perspectives on disability explains, is informed by a great deal of feminist theory, from standpoint philosophy to feminist phenomenology, as well as political philosophical questions of identity, difference, and diversity. (See also Carlson & Kittay, 2010.)

Ultimately, the number of approaches that can be taken on any of these issues is as high as the number of philosophers there are working on them. Nonetheless there are some general family resemblances to be found in certain groupings, not altogether unlike Jaggar's 1983 classification. The remainder of this entry will identify how the previous schema has changed and what new constellations have emerged.

2.1 Liberal Feminism

Of Jaggar's categories, liberal feminism remains a strong current in feminist political thought. Its primary concern is to protect and enhance women's personal and political autonomy, the first the freedom to live one's life as one wants and the second being the freedom to help decide the direction of the political community. This approach was invigorated with the publication of John Rawls's A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1971) and subsequently his Political Liberalism (Rawls 1993). Susan Moller Okin (Okin 1989, 1979; Okin et al. 1999) and (Kittay 1999) have used Rawls's work productively to extend his theory to attend to women's concerns. From a more critical perspective, several

Summer 2014 Edition 7 Feminist Political Philosophy feminist theorists have argued that some of the central categories of liberalism occlude women's lived concerns; for example, the central liberal private/public distinction sequesters the private sphere, and any harm that may occur there to women, away from political scrutiny (Pateman 1983). Perhaps more than any other approach, liberal feminist theory parallels developments in liberal feminist activism. While feminist activists have waged legal and political battles to criminalize, as just one example, against women (which previously, in marital relations, hadn't been considered a crime), feminist political philosophers who have engaged the liberal lexicon have shown how the distinction between private and public realms has served to uphold male domination of women by rendering power relations within the household as “natural” and immune from political regulation. Such political philosophy uncovers how seemingly innocuous and “commonsensical” categories have covert power agendas. For example, old conceptions of the sanctity of the private space of the household and the role of women primarily as child-bearers and caregivers served to protect male domination of women in the household from public scrutiny. Feminist critiques of the public/private split supported legal advances that finally led in the 1980s to the criminalization in the United States of spousal rape (Hagan and Sussman 1988).

While liberal feminism continues to flourish, it is not without its critics, especially given that it continues to treat unproblematically many of the concepts that theorists in the 1990s and since have problematized, such as “woman” as a stable and identifiable category and the unity of the self underlying self-rule or autonomy. Critics (such as Zerilli 2009) have argued that the universal values that liberals such as Okin invoked were really expanded particulars, with liberal theorists mistaking their ethnocentrically derived values as universal ones. At the same time, however, some feminist critics are showing how many of the values of liberalism could be performatively reconstituted. (See section 2.5)

8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

Nonetheless there is very important work going on in this field. For example, Carole Pateman and Charles Mills have been working within the liberal tradition to show the limits and faults of theory for women and blacks. Their jointly authored book, Contract & Domination, levels a devastating critique against systems of sexual and racial domination. This work engages and critiques some of the most dominant strains of political philosophy.

2.2 Radical, Socialist, and Marxist Feminisms

While feminist liberalism continues to flourish, the historical developments and emerging debates described in the previous sections have eclipsed or deeply transformed Jaggar's other three categories of radical, Marxist, and socialist feminism (Jaggar 1983). Also, the “grand narratives” that underlay these views, especially the latter two, have fallen out of favor (Snyder 2008). This subsection briefly covers these approach's concerns and transformations.

Those who continue to work in radical feminism remain committed to getting at the root of male domination by understanding the source of power differentials, which some radical feminists, including Catharine MacKinnon, trace back to male sexuality and the notion that heterosexual intercourse enacts male domination over women. “Women and men are divided by gender, made into the sexes as we know them, by the requirements of its dominant form, heterosexuality, which institutionalizes male sexual dominance and female sexual submission. If this is true, sexuality is the linchpin of ” (MacKinnon 1989,113). Radical feminists of the 1980s tended to see power as running one-way, from those with power over those who are being oppressed. As Amy Allen puts it, “Unlike liberal feminists, who view power as a positive social resource that ought to be fairly distributed, and feminist phenomenologists, who understand domination in terms of a tension

Summer 2014 Edition 9 Feminist Political Philosophy between transcendence and immanence, radical feminists tend to understand power in terms of dyadic relations of dominance/subordination, often understood on analogy with the relationship between master and slave.” (See the section on radical feminist approaches in the entry on feminist perspectives on power.) Unlike the more reformist politics of liberal feminism, radical feminists of the 1980s largely sought to reject the prevailing order altogether, sometimes advocating separatism (Daly 1985, 1990). But a new generation of radical feminist theorists shares some of the commitments of the postmodern feminists discussed below, e.g., skepticism about any fixed gender identity or gender binaries and a more fluid and performative approach to sexuality and politics (Snyder 2008).

Through much of the twentieth century, many political theorists in Europe, the United States, and Latin America drew on socialist and Marxist texts to develop theories of social change attentive to issues of class relations and exploitation in modern capitalist economies. After learning of the horrors of Stalinism, most Western Marxists and socialists were extremely critical of the communist systems in the Soviet Union and later in China. Western, mostly anti-communist, Marxist thought flourished in Italy (with Antonio Gramsci's work), England (with Stuart Hall and Raymond Williams' work), France (with the Socialisme ou Barbarie group), and the United States (but less so there after McCarthyism yet renewed somewhat in the 1960s with the New Left). Jaggar's 1983 book summed up well the way feminists were using socialist and Marxist ideas to understand the way women were exploited and their laboring and reproductive work devalued and unpaid though necessary for capitalism to function. In the entry on feminist perspectives on class and work, the authors point to much of the work that was going on in this field up through the mid- 1990s.

But since then, the authors note, various postmodern, postcolonial,

10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee poststructuralist, and deconstructive theories have criticized the bases for socialist and Marxist thought, including the “grand narrative” of economic and the reduction of everything to economic and material relations. At the same time, Marxist analyses are important parts of other contemporary feminist philosophers' work. (See Dean 2009, Fraser 2009, Spivak 1988.) So while the categories of socialist and Marxist feminisms are less relevant today, many feminist philosophers still take seriously the need to attend to the material conditions of life and engage in the hermeneutics of suspicion that Marxist analysis calls for.

2.3 Difference Feminisms

A major set of fault lines in feminist thought since the 1990s is over the questions of the subject of “woman.” According to Mary Dietz's 2003 article laying out the field, there are two large groups here. One champions the category of woman (in the singular and universal), arguing that the specificity of women's identity, their sexual difference from men, should be appreciated and revalued. (The other is discussed in the next subsection.) This “” includes two distinct groups: (i) those who look at how gendered sexual difference is socially constituted and (ii) those who look at how sexual difference is constructed symbolically and psychoanalytically. The first, social difference feminism, includes theories that revalue mothering and caring and has been developed largely in the Anglo-American context. (See for example Tronto 1993 and Held 1995.) The second, symbolic difference feminism, is that of what are often referred to as the French Feminists, including Irigaray, Cixous, and Kristeva. They belong in this group to the extent that they value and distinguish women's specific sexual difference from men's. Irigaray's focus on sexual difference is emblematic of this. Social- difference and symbolic-difference feminisms have very little to do with each other but, Dietz argues, they share the notion that a feminist politics requires a category woman that has a determinate meaning (Dietz 2003,

Summer 2014 Edition 11 Feminist Political Philosophy

403; Nicholson 1994, 100).

Social Difference Feministm: The new generation of radical feminists briefly described above could be considered a part of social difference feminism, at least to the extent that these theorists take seriously the category of woman and want to develop an ethics and politics upon it. Another good example of social-difference feminism is care ethics, which was originally developed as an alternative to mainstream ethical theory, has been harnessed to counter liberal political theory (Gilligan 1982; Held 1995). (See the discussion in the entry on .) Drawing on feminist research in moral psychology (Gilligan 1982; Held 1995), this field explores the ways in which the that society and mothering cultivate in women can provide an alternative to the traditional emphases in moral and political philosophy on universality, reason, and justice. Some care ethicists have sought to take the virtues that had long been relegated to the private realm, such as paying particular attention to those who are vulnerable or taking into consideration circumstances and not just abstract principles, and use them as well in the public realm. This approach has led to intense debates between liberals who advocated universal ideals of justice and care ethicists who advocated attention to the particular, to relationships, to care. By the 1990s, though, many care ethicists had revised their views. Rather than seeing care and justice as mutually exclusive alternatives, they began to recognize that attention to care should be accompanied by attention to fairness (justice) in order to attend to the plight of those with whom we have no immediate relation (Koggel 1998).

The care ethics approach raises the question of whether and, if so, how women-as-care-givers have distinct virtues. Feminists as a whole have long distanced themselves from ideas that women have any particular essence, choosing instead to see and its accompanying virtues as social constructs, dispositions that result from culture and conditioning,

12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee certainly not biological givens. So for care ethicists to champion the virtues that have inculcated femininity seems also to champion a patriarchal system that relegates one gender to the role of caretaker. The care ethicists' answer to this problem has largely been to flip the hierarchy, to claim that the work of the household is more meaningful and sustaining than the work of the polis. But critics, such as Drucilla Cornell, Mary Dietz, and Chantal Mouffe, argue that such a revaluation keeps intact the dichotomy between the private and the public and the old association of women's work with childcare. (Butler and Scott 1992; Phillips and NetLibrary Inc 1998, pp. 386-389)

Symbolic Difference Feminism: Notable among the French Feminists for having a political philosophy is , who has written several books on the new rights that should be afforded to and women. Irigaray's early work (1985a and 1985b) made the case that in the history of philosophy women have been denied their own essence or identity. Rather they have been positioned as men's mirror negation. So that to be a man is to not be a woman, and hence that woman equals only not-man. Her strategy in response to this is to speak back from the margins to which women have been relegated and to claim some kind of “essence” for women, and along with that a set of rights that are specifically for girls and women (Irigaray 1994 and 1996). Criticisms of her views have been heated, including among feminists themselves, especially those who are wary of any kind of essentialist and biological conflation of women's identity. To the extent that Irigaray is an essentialist, her view would indeed be relegated to the approach outlined here as symbolic difference feminism, as Dietz 2003 does. But there are compelling arguments that Irigaray is wielding essentialism strategically or metaphorically, that she isn't claiming that women really do have some kind of irreducible essence that the the history of metaphysics has denied them (Fuss 1989). This other reading would put Irigaray more in the performative group described below. The same kind of argument could be made for the work of Julia

Summer 2014 Edition 13 Feminist Political Philosophy

Kristeva, that her metaphors of the female chora, for example, are describing the western imaginary, not any kind of womanly . So whether French feminist thought should be grouped as difference feminism or performative feminism is still very much open to debate.

To the extent that the above two types of feminist theory are pinpointing some kind of specific difference between the sexes, difference feminisms have raised concerns about essentialism or identifying distinct values that women have as women. Such concerns are part of a larger set of criticisms that have run through feminist theorizing since the 1970s, with non-white, non-middle-class, and non-western women questioning the very category of “woman” and the notion that this title could be a boundary-spanning category that could unite women of various walks of life. (See the entries on identity politics and feminist perspectives on sex and gender.) Criticisms of a unitary identity of “woman” have been motivated by worries that much feminist theory has originated from the standpoint of a particular class of women who mistake their own particular standpoint for a universal one. In her 1981 book, Ain't I a Woman?: Black women and feminism, bell hooks notes that the pretends to speak for all women but was made up of primarily white, middle class women who, because of their narrow perspective, did not represent the needs of poor women and women of color and ended up reinforcing class stereotypes (hooks 1981). What is so damning about this kind of critique is that it mirrors the one that feminists have leveled against mainstream political theorists who have taken the particular category of men to be a universal category of mankind, a schema that does not in fact include women under the category of mankind but marks them as other (Lloyd 1993).

2.4 Diversity Feminisms

Hence, one of the most vexing issues facing feminist theory in general and

14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee feminist political philosophy in particular is the matter of identity (see the entry on identity politics). Identity politics in general is a political practice of mobilizing for change on the basis of a political identity (women, black, chicana, etc.). The philosophical debate is whether such identities are based on some real difference or history of oppression, and also whether people should embrace identities that have historically been used to oppress them. Identity politics in feminist practice is fraught along at least two axes: whether there is any real essence or identity of woman in general and even if so whether the category of woman could be used to represent all women. People at the intersection of multiple marginalized identities (e.g, black women) have raised questions about which identity is foremost or whether either identity is apt. Such questions play out with the question of political representation—what aspects of identity are politically salient and truly representative, whether race, class, or gender (Phillips 1995; Young 1997, 2000). The ontological question of women's identity gets played out on the political stage when it comes to matters of political representation, group rights, and affirmative action. The 2008 U.S. Democratic Party primary battle between Senators Barack Obama and Hillary Clinton turned this philosophical question into a very real and heated one from black women throughout the United States. Was a black woman who supported Clinton a traitor to her race, or a black woman who supported Obama a traitor to her sex? Or did it make any sense to talk about identity in a way that would lead to charges of treason? Of the approaches discussed above, radical and seem particularly wedded to feminist identity politics.

The other large group of contemporary feminist philosophers that Dietz (2003) describes disagrees entirely with the idea that there is or needs to be a single and universal category of “woman.” Dietz refers to this group as diversity feminism, which began with what I described earlier: women of color and others pointing out that the presuppositions of mainstream feminism were based on their very particular race and class. In the 1980s

Summer 2014 Edition 15 Feminist Political Philosophy and 1990s philosophy along with the rest of Western culture started grappling with demands for multicultural perspectives. Shortly thereafter postcolonial theory raised the need to become aware of multiple global perspectives. As Sharon Krause describes it, “this development involved the ‘world diversification’ of feminism to a more global, comparative, and differentiated body of work” (Krause 2011, 106). This diversification, Krause notes, is also due to new literature on intersectionality, that is, the ways in which the intersections of our multiple identities (race, gender, orientation, ethnicity, etc.) all need to be attended to in talking about political change (Krause 2011, 107). Intersectionality also links up with discussions of “hybridity” in postcolonial literature, of religion and globalization, and of the experiences of LGBTQ people. “The result is an explosion of about the lived experience of differently placed and multiply-positioned women” (Krause 2011, 107).

2.5 Performative Feminisms

If the diversity feminists, from multiculuturalists to postcolonial and intersectional thinkers, are right, then there is no reliable category of woman on which to base feminist politics. By the end of the 1990s some saw this as a radical danger of , and the field seemed to be at an impasse. But then another approach began to emerge. As Mary Dietz writes in her 2003 essay on current controversies in feminist theory,

In recent years, political theorists have been engaged in debates about what it might mean to conceptualize a feminist political praxis that is aligned with democracy but does not begin from the binary of gender. Along these lines, Mouffe (1992, pp. 376, 378; 1993), for example, proposes a feminist conception of democratic citizenship that would render sexual difference “effectively nonpertinent.” Perhaps the salient feature of such conceptions is the turn toward plurality, which posits democratic society as a field

16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

of interaction where multiple axes of difference, identity, and subordination politicize and intersect (e.g., Phelan 1994, Young 1990, 1997b, 2000; Benhabib 1992; Honig 1992; Ferguson 1993; Phillips 1993, 1995; Mouffe 1993; Yeatman 1994, 1998; Bickford 1996; Dean 1996; Fraser 1997; Nash 1998; Heyes 2000; McAfee 2000). (Dietz 2003, 419)

Following up on what has happened in feminist political theory since Dietz's article, Sharon Krause writes that this work is “contesting the old assumption that equals autonomy” and makes room “within agency for forms of subjectivity and action that are nonsovereign but nevertheless potent” (Krause 2011, citing Allen 2007, Beltrán 2010, Butler 2004, Hirschman 2002, and Zerilli 2005.) “For some theorists,” Krause writes, “this shift involves thinking of agency and freedom in more collective ways, which emphasize solidarity, relationality, and constitutive intersubjectivity” (Krause 2011, 108, citing Butler 2004, Cornell 2007, Mohanty 2003, and Nedelsky 2005).

This constellation of thinkers could be working in what we could call performative political philosophy, performative in several senses: in theorizing how agency is constituted, how political judgments can be made in the absence of known rules (Honig 2009, 309), how new universals can be created and new communities constituted. Performative feminist politics doesn't worry about whether it is possible to come up with a single definition of “woman” or any other political identity; it sees identity as something that is performatively created. “How we assume these identitites,” Drucilla Cornell writes, “is never something ‘out there’ that effectively determines who we can be as men and women—gay, lesbian, straight, queer, transsexual, transgender, or otherwise” (Cornell 2003, 144). It is something that is shaped as we live and externalize identities. From a performative feminist perspective, feminism is a project of anticipating and creating better political futures in the absence of

Summer 2014 Edition 17 Feminist Political Philosophy foundations. As Linda Zerilli writes, “politics is about making claims and judgments—and having the courage to do so—in the absence of the objective criteria or rules that could provide certain knowledge and the guarantee that speaking in women's name will be accepted or taken up by others” (Zerilli 2005, 179). Drawing largely on Arendt and Butler, Zerilli calls for a “freedom-centered feminism” that “would strive to bring about transformation in normative conceptions of gender without returning to the classical notion of freedom as sovereignty” that feminists have long criticized but found difficult to resist (ibid.).

In its feminist incarnations, this view also takes its cue from 's performative account of gender as well as Hannah Arendt's observation that human rights are created politically, as well as other thinkers' ideas, to describe an anticipatory ideal of politics. Linda Zerilli describes this kind of feminist politics as “the contingently based public practice of soliciting the agreement of others to what each of us claims to be universal” (Zerilli 2005, p. 173). From a performatve perspective, normative political claims appeal to other people, not to supposed or foundations.

This view recuperates many of the ideals of the Enlightenment—such as freedom, autonomy, and justice—but in a way that drops the Enlightenment's metaphysical assumptions about reason, progress, and human nature. Instead of seeing these ideals as grounded in some metaphysical facts, this new view sees them as ideals that people hold and try to instantiate through practice and imagination. Where many ancient and modern ideals of politics were based on suppositions about the nature of reality or of human , contemporary political philosophies generally operate without supposing that there are any universal or eternal truths. Some might see this situation as ripe for , arbitrariness, or the exercise of brute power. The performative alternative is to imagine and try to create a better world by anticipating, claiming, and appealing to

18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee others that it should be so. Even if there is no metaphysical that human beings have dignity and infinite worth, people can act as if it were true in order to create a world in which it is seen to be so.

Peformative feminist political philosophy shares liberal feminism's appreciation for Enlightenment ideals but in a way that is skeptical about foundations. Just as Zerilli performatively reconstitutes the concept of freedom, Drucilla Cornell recuperates ideas of autonomy, dignity, and personhood, in a new performative capacity, as ideals that people aspire to rather than as moral facts waiting to be discovered, applied, or realized.

Despite the shared post-foundational theorizing among performative feminists, when it comes to thinking about democratic politics, there are sharp divergences, namely on the question of “what it means to actualize public spaces and enact democratic politics” (Dietz 2003, 419). On this questions, theorists tend to diverge into two groups: associational and agonistic. Associational theorists (e.g., Benhabib 1992, 1996; Benhabib and Cornell 1987; Fraser 1989; Young 1990, 1997, 2000) gravitate more toward deliberative democratic theory, while agonistic theorists (e.g., Mouffe 1992, 1993, 1999, 2000; Honig 1995; Ziarek 2001) worry that democratic theories that focus on consensus can silence debate and thus they focus more on plurality, dissensus, and the ceaseless contestation within politics.

The differences spring from, or perhaps lead to, different readings of who has most inspired performative political theory: Hannah Arendt, namely Arendt's ideas of speech and action in the public sphere, of the meaning of plurality, of the ways in which human beings can distinguish themselves. As Bonnie Honig, a champion of the agonistic model writes,

Political theorists and feminists, in particular, have long criticized

Summer 2014 Edition 19 Feminist Political Philosophy

Arendt for the agonistic dimensions of her politics, charging that agonism is a masculinist, heroic, violent, competitive, (merely) aesthetic, or necessarily individualistic practice. For these theorists, the notion of an agonistic feminism would be, at best, a contradiction in terms and, at worst, a muddled and, perhaps, dangerous idea. Their perspective is effectively endorsed by who, in a recent series of powerful essays, tries to rescue Arendt for feminism by excising agonism from her thought. (Honig 1995, 156)

Associational theorists tends to look for ways, amidst all the differences and questions about the lack of foundations, it is possible to come to agreement on matters of common concern. This is seen in feminist democratic theory, perhaps best known through the works of Seyla Benhabib (Benhabib 1992, 1996), greatly inspired by her non-agonistic reading of Arendt and of the work of the German critical theorist, Jürgen Habermas. Benhabib's work engages democratic theorists quite broadly, not just feminist theorists. This passage of hers helps to clarify what she takes to be the best aim of a political philosophy: a state of affairs to which all affected would assent. As she writes,

Only those norms (i.e., general rules of action and institutional arrangements) can be said to be valid (i.e., morally binding), which would be agreed to by all those affected by their consequences, if such agreement were reached as a consequence of a process of deliberation that had the following features: 1) participation in such deliberation is governed by norms of equality and symmetry; all have the same chances to initiate speech acts, to question, to interrogate, and to open debate; 2) all have the right to question the assigned topics of conversation; and 3) all have the right to initiate reflexive arguments about the very rules of the discourse procedure and the way in which they are applied or carried out. (Benhabib

20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

1996, 70)

Following Habermas, Benhabib contends that certain conditions need to be in place in order for members of a political community to arrive at democratic outcomes, namely the proceedings need to be deliberative. Some take deliberation to be a matter of reasoned argumentation; others see it as less about reason or argumentation but more about an open process of working through choices. (McAfee 2004.)

Not all theorists who tend toward the associational model embrace deliberative theory so readily. Iris Young's pioneering book, Justice and the Politics of Difference and several of her subsequent works have been very influential and have led to a good deal of hesitance in feminist theoretical communities about the claims of deliberative theory. Where Benhabib is confident that conditions can be such that all who are affected can have a voice in deliberations, Young points out that those who have been historically silenced have a difficult time having their views heard or heeded. Young is skeptical of the claims of mainstream democratic theory that democratic deliberative processes could lead to outcomes that would be acceptable to all (Young 1990, 1997). Young, along with (Fraser 1989) and others, worried that in the process of trying to reach consensus, the untrained voices of women and others who have been marginalized would be left out of the final tally. Young's criticisms were very persuasive, leading a generation of feminist political philosophers to be wary of deliberative democratic theory. Instead of deliberative democracy, in the mid 1990s Young proposed a theory of communicative democracy, hoping to make way for a deliberative conception that was open to means of expression beyond the rational expression of mainstream deliberative democratic theory. Young worried that deliberation as defined by Habermas is too reason-based and leaves out forms of communication that women and people of color tend to use, such as greeting, rhetoric, and storytelling. Young argued that these alternative modes of communication,

Summer 2014 Edition 21 Feminist Political Philosophy modes that women and people of color and other marginalized people tended to use, could provide the basis of a more democratic, communicative theory. In her last major book, Inclusion and Democracy (Young 2000), Young had clearly moved to embrace deliberative theory itself, seeing the ways in which it could be constructed to give voice to those who had been otherwise marginalized. More recent feminist democratic theory has engaged deliberative theory more positively. (See McAfee and Snyder 2007.)

Where liberal feminists inspired by John Rawls and democratic feminists inspired by Jürgen Habermas and/or John Dewey hold out the hope that democratic deliberations might lead to democratic agreements, agonistic feminists are wary of consensus as inherently undemocratic. Agonistic feminist political philosophy comes out of poststructural continental feminist and philosophical traditions. It takes from Marxism the hope for a more radically egalitarian society. It takes from contemporary notions of subjectivity and solidarity as malleable and constructed. Along with postmodern thought, it repudiates any notion of pre-existing moral or political truths or foundations (Ziarek 2001). Its central claim is that feminist struggle, like other struggles for social justice, is engaged in politics as ceaseless contestation. Agonistic views see the nature of politics as inherently conflictual, with battles over power and hegemony being the central tasks of democratic struggle. Advocates of agonistic politics worry that the kind of consensus sought by democratic theorists (discussed above) will lead to some kind of oppression or injustice by silencing new struggles. As Chantal Mouffe puts it, “We have to accept that every consensus exists as a temporary result of a provisional hegemony, as a stabilization of power, and that it always entails some form of exclusion” (Mouffe 2000, 104).

Where associational theorists seek out ways that people can overcome systematically distorted communication and deliberation, Dietz notes that

22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee agonists eschew this project because they understand politics as “essentially a practice of creation, reproduction, transformation and articulation.... Simply put, associational feminists scrutinize the conditions of exclusion in order to theorize the emancipation of the subject in the public sphere of communicative interaction; agonistic feminists deconstruct emancipatory procedures to disclose how the subject is both produced through political exclusions and positioned against them” (Dietz 2003, 422).

New work in democratic theory and new readings of Arendt's philosophy offer hope of moving beyond the associational/agonistic divide in performative feminist politics (Barker et al. 2012). Benhabib's proceduralism is being surpassed with more affect-laden accounts of deliberation (Krause 2008). Instead of the rational back-and-forth of reasoned argumentation, theorists are beginning to see deliberative talk as forms of constituting the subject, judging without pre-conceived truths, and performatively creating new political projects.

In sum, feminist political philosophy is a still evolving field of thought that has much to offer mainstream political philosophy. In the past two decades it has come to exert a stronger influence over mainstream political theorizing, raising objections that mainstream philosophers have had to address, though not always very convincingly. And in its newest developments it promises to go even further.

Bibliography

Abbey, Ruth. 2011. The Return of Feminist Liberalism, Durham, UK: Acumen Publishing. Ackerly, Brooke. 2000. Political Theory and Feminist Social Criticism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ackerly, Brooke, and Susan Okin. 1999. “Feminist Social Criticism and

Summer 2014 Edition 23 Feminist Political Philosophy

the International Movement for Women's Rights as Human Rights,” in Democracy's Edges, ed. I. Shapiro, C. Hacker-Cordon, pp. 134-62. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Alcoff, Linda M. 2006. Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Alexander, M. Jacqui. 2005. Pedagogies of Crossing: Meditations on Feminism, Sexual Politics, Memory, and the Sacred, Durham: Duke University Press. Allen, Amy. 2007. The Politics of Our Selves: Power, Autonomy, and Gender in Contemporary , New York: Columbia University Press. Anzaldúa, Gloria. 1987. Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza, San Francisco: Aunt Lute Foundation Books. Barker, Derek, David McIver, and Noëlle McAfee, (eds.), 2012. Democratizing Deliberation: A Political Theory Anthology, Dayton: Kettering Foundation Press. Beltrán, Cristina. 2010. The Trouble with Unity: Latino Politics and the Creation of Identity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics, New York: Routledge. –––. 1996. Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2002. The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2008. Another Cosmopolitanism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Benhabib, Seyla, Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell, and Nancy Fraser. 1995. Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange, New York: Routledge. Benhabib, Seyla, and Drucilla Cornell. 1987. Feminism as Critique: On the Politics of Gender, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Brown, Wendy. 1988. Manhood and Politics: A feminist Reading in

24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

Political Theory, Totowa: Rowman & Allenheld. –––. 1995. States of Injury, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 1997. “The Impossibility of Women's Studies,” Differences, 9: 79- 101. –––. 2000, “Rights as Paradoxes,” Constellations, 7: 230-41. –––. 2005. Edgework: Critical Essays on Knowledge and Politics, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Butler, Judith. 1990. : Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, New York: Routledge. –––. 1993. Bodies That Matter: on the Discursive Limits of “Sex,” New York: Routledge. –––. 1995. “Contingent foundations: feminism and the question of ‘postmodernism’,” in Benhabib et al. 1995, pp. 35-58. –––. 1997a. The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection, Stanford: Stanford University Press. –––. 1997b. Excitable Speech: a Politics of the Performative, New York: Routledge. –––. 2000. “Restaging the Universal: Hegemony and the Limits of Formalism,” in Contingency, Hegemony, Universality: Contemporary Dialogues on the Left, J. Butler, E. LaClau, S. Žižek (eds.), pp. 11-43. London: Verso. Butler, Judith, and Joan Wallach Scott. 1992. Feminists Theorize the Political, New York: Routledge. Butler, Judith, and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. 2007. Who Sings the Nation State? Language, Politics, Belonging, Calcutta: Seagull Books. Carlson, Licia. 2010. The Faces of Intellectual Disability: Philosophical Reflections, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Carlson, Licia, and Eva Kittay. 2010. Cognitive Disability and Its challenge to Moral Philosophy, Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell. Cornell, Drucilla. 1998. At the Heart of Freedom: Feminism, Sex, and

Summer 2014 Edition 25 Feminist Political Philosophy

Equality, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2003. “Autonomy Re-Imagined” in Journal for the Psychoanalysis of Culture and Society, 8(1): 144-149. –––. 2007. Moral Images of Freedom, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Crenshaw, Kimberle. 1989. “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex,” University of Chicago Legal Forum, pp. 139-167. Critchley, Simon, and Chantal Mouffe. 1996. and , London ; New York: Routledge. Cudd, Ann E. 2006. Analyzing Oppression, Oxford: Oxford University Press. –––. 2012. “Resistance is (Not) Futile: Feminism's Contribution to Political Philosophy,” in Out from the Shadows, Anita Superson and Sharon Crasnow (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 15-31. Daly, Mary. 1985. Beyond God the Father : Toward a Philosophy of Women's Liberation, Boston: Beacon Press. –––. 1990. Gyn/ecology: The Metaethics of Radical Feminism, Boston: Beacon Press. Dean, Jodi. 2009. Democracy and Other Neoliberal Fantasies: Communicative Capitalism and Left Politics, Durham: Duke University Press. Dietz, Mary G. 1985. “Citizenship with a Feminist Face: The Problem with Maternal Thinking,” Political Theory, 13: 19-38. –––. 1987. “Context is All: Feminism and Theories of Citizenship,” Daedalus, 116: 1-24. –––. 2002. Turning Operations: Feminism, Arendt, and Politics, New York: Routledge. –––. 2003. “Current controversies in feminist theory,” Annual Review of Political Science, 6: 399-431. Firestone, Shulamith. 1971. : The Case for Feminist Revolution, rev. ed., New York: Bantam Books.

26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

Fraser, Nancy. 1989. Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary Social Theory, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. –––. 2009. Scales of Justice: Reimagining Political Space in a Globalizing World, New York: Columbia University Press. Fuss, Diana. 1989. Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature & Difference, New York: Routledge. Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gould, Carol C. 2004. Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Grewal, Inderpal. 2005. Transnational America: Feminism, Diasporas, Neoliberalism, Durham: Duke University Press. Habermas, Jürgen. 1975. Legitimation Crisis, Boston: Beacon Press. –––. 1989. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society, Studies in contemporary German social thought, Cambridge: MIT Press. Hagan, Frank E., and Marvin B. Sussman. 1988. Deviance and the Family, Marriage & Family Review (Volume 12, No. 1/2), New York: Haworth Press. Hall, Cheryl. 2005. The Trouble with Passion: Political Theory Beyond the Reign of Reason, New York: Routledge. Held, Virginia. 1995. Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics, Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. Hill-Collins, Patricia. 2005. Black Sexual Politics: African Americans, Gender, and the New Racism, New York: Routledge. Hirschmann, Nancy J. 2002. The Subject of Liberty: Toward a Feminist Theory of Freedom, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2008. Gender, Class, and Freedom in Modern Political Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Honig, Bonnie. 1993. Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics,

Summer 2014 Edition 27 Feminist Political Philosophy

Ithaca: Cornell University Press. –––. 1995. Feminist Interpretations of Hannah Arendt, University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. –––. 2001. Democracy and the Foreigner, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2009. Emergency Politics: Paradox, Law, Democracy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2011. “Ismene's Forced Choice: Sacrifice and Sorority in Sophocles' Antigone” in Arethusa, 44(1): 29-68. Honig, Bonnie, and David Mapel. 2002. Skepticism, Individuality, and Freedom: The Reluctant Liberalism of Richard Flathman, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. hooks, bell. 1981. Ain't I a Woman : Black Women and Feminism, Boston: South End Press. Hull, Gloria T., Patricia Bell Scott, and Barbara Smith. 1982. All the Women Are White, All the Blacks Are Men, But Some of Us Are Brave: Black Women's Studies, New York: The Feminist Press at the City University of New York. Irigaray, Luce. 1985a. Speculum of the Other Woman, G. Gill (trans.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press. –––. 1985b. This Sex Which Is Not One, C. Porter (trans.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press. –––. 1993. An Ethics of Sexual Difference, G. Gill, C. Burke (trans.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press. –––. 1994. Thinking the Difference: for a Peaceful Revolution, K. Montin (trans.), New York: Routledge. –––. 1996. I Love to You: Sketch of a Possible Felicity in History, A. Martin (trans.), New York: Routledge. Jaggar, Alison M. 1983. Feminist politics and human nature,Philosophy and society, Totowa: Rowman & Allanheld. –––. 2005. “‘Saving Amina’: for Women and Intercultural

28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

Dialogue,” Ethics & International Affairs, 19(3): 55-75. Khader, Serene J. 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love's Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency New York: Routledge. Koggel, Christine M. 1998. Perspectives on Equality: Constructing a Relational Theory, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. Krause, Sharon. 2008. Civil Passions: Moral Sentiment and Democratic Deliberation, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2011. “Contested Questions, Current Trajectories: Feminism in Political Theory Today,” Politics & Gender, 7(1): 105-111. Kristeva, Julia. 1980. Desire in Language: a Semiotic Approach to Art and Literature, L. Roudiez (trans.), New York: Columbia University Press. –––. 1982. Powers of Horror: an Essay on Abjection, L. Roudiez (trans.), New York: Columbia University Press. –––. 1984. Revolution in Poetic Language, M. Waller (trans.), New York: Columbia University Press. –––. 1986. “Women's Time,” in The Kristeva Reader, ed. T Moi, pp. 187- 213. New York: Columbia University Press. Lloyd, Genevieve. 1993. The Man of Reason: ‘Male’ and ‘Female’ in , New York: Routledge; first published in 1984 by Methuen & Company Limited. Love, Heather. 2007. Feeling Backward: Loss and the Politics of Queer History, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Laclau, Ernesto, and Chantal Mouffe. 1985. Hegemony & Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics, London: Verso. Lugones, Maria C. and Elizabeth Spelman, 1986. “Have We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism and the Demand for 'The Woman's Voice',” in Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy, Marilyn Pearsall (ed.), Belmont, Calif.:

Summer 2014 Edition 29 Feminist Political Philosophy

Wadsworth Publishing Company, pp. 19-31. Lugones, Maria, 1995. “Playfulness, ‘World’-Traveling, and Loving Perception,” in Free Spirits: Feminist Philosophers on Culture, Kate Mehuron and Gary Percesepe (ed.) Engleweood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice- Hall, pp. 121-128. MacKinnon, Catharine A. 1989. Toward a Feminist Theory of the State, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Mahmood, Saba. 2005. Politics of Piety: The Islamic Revival and the Feminist Subject, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Malabou, Catherine, and Ewa P. Ziarek. 2012. “Negativity, Unhappiness, or Felicity: On Irigaray's Dialectical Culture of Sexual Difference,” L'Esprit Créateur, 52(3): 11-25. Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1998. The German Ideology: Including Theses on Feuerbach and Introduction to The Critique of Political EconomyAmherst: Prometheus Books. McAfee, Noëlle. 2004. “Three Models of Democratic Deliberation” in Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Special Issue on Pragmatism and Deliberative Democracy, 18(1): 44-59. –––. 2008. Democracy and the Political Unconscious, New York: Columbia University Press. McAfee, Noëlle and R. Claire Snyder. 2007. “Democratic Theory” in : A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 22(4): vii-x. Millett, Kate. 1970. Sexual Politics, 1st ed., Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. Mohanty, Chandra Talpade. 1991. “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses,” in Mohanty et al. 1991, pp. 51-80. –––. 2003. Feminism without Borders: Decolonizing Theory, Practicing Solidarity, Durham: Duke University Press. Mohanty, Chandra Talpade, A. Russo, and L. Torres. 1991. Third World Women and the Politics of Feminims, Bloomington: Indiana

30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

University Press. Moraga, Cherrie and Gloria Anzaldúa (eds.). 1983. This Bridge Called My Back: Writings by Radical Women of Color, New York: Kitchen Table: Women of Color Press. Morgan, Robin. 1970. Sisterhood is powerful; an anthology of writings from the women's liberation movement, 1st ed., New York: Random House. Mouffe, Chantal. 1979. Gramsci and Marxist theory, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. –––. 1992. Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community, London: Verso. –––. 1993. The Return of the Political, London: Verso. –––. 1999. The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, London: Verso. –––. 2000. The Democratic Paradox, London: Verso. –––. 2005. On the Political, Thinking in action, New York: Routledge. Nurayan Uma, and , eds. 2000. Decentering the Center: Philosophy for a Multicultural, Postcolonial, and Feminist World, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Nussbaum, Martha C. 1995. “Human capabilities, Female Human Beings,” in Women, Culture, and Development: a Study of Human Capabilities, ed. M. Nussbaum, J. Glover, pp. 61-104. Oxford, UK: Clarendon. –––. 1999a. Sex and Social Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press. –––. 1999b. “The Professor of Parody,” New Republic, 2(22): 37-45. –––. 2000. Women and Human Development: the Capabilities Approach, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Okin, Susan Moller. 1979. Women in Western political thought, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 1989. Justice, Gender, and the Family, New York: Basic Books. Okin, Susan Moller, Joshua Cohen, Matthew Howard, and Martha Craven Nussbaum. 1999. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton:

Summer 2014 Edition 31 Feminist Political Philosophy

Princeton University Press. Pateman, Carole. 1988. The Sexual Contract, Oxford: Polity. –––. 1989. The Disorder of Women: Democracy, Feminism and Political Theory, Stanford: Stanford University Press. Pateman, Carole, and Charles W. Mills. 2007. Contract and Domination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Phillips, Anne. 1995. The Politics of Presence, Oxford: Clarendon Press. –––. 2009. Multiculturalism without Culture, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Phillips, Anne. 1998. Feminism and Politics, New York: Oxford University Press. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. –––. 1993. Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press. Ricœur, Paul. 1970. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation, The Terry lectures, New Haven: Yale University Press. Rubin, Gayle. 1975. “The Traffic in Women: Notes on the ‘Political Economy’ of Sex,” in Toward an Anthropology of Women, ed. R. Reiter, pp. 157-210. New York: Monthly Review. Scott, Joan. 1988a. “Gender: A Useful Category of Historical Analysis,” in Gender and the Politics of History, ed. J. Scott, pp. 28-52. New York: Columbia University Press. –––. 1988b. “Deconstructing Equality-versus-Difference: Or the Uses of Poststructuralist Theory for Feminism,” Feminist Studies, 14: 33-50. –––. 1992. “Experience,” in Butler & Scott 1992, pp. 22-40. –––. 2007. The Politics of the Veil, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2011. The Fantasy of , Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Snyder, R. Claire. 2008. “What is Third-Wave Feminism? A New Directions Essay,” , 34(1): 175-196. Song, Sarah. 2007. Justice, Gender, and the Politics of Multiculturalism,

32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Noelle¨ McAfee

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spivak, Gayatri C. 1988. In Other Worlds: Essays in Cultural Politics, New York: Routledge. Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral Boundaries: a Political Argument for an Ethic of Care, New York/London: Routledge. –––. 2013. Caring Democracy: Markets, Equality, and Justice, New York: NYU Press. Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 1997. Intersecting Voices: Dilemmas of Gender, Political Philosophy, and Policy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. –––. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy, Oxford political theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zerilli, Linda M. G. 2005. Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. –––. 2009. “Towards a Feminist Theory of Judgment,” Signs, 34(2): 295- 317. –––. 2012. “Value pluralism and the problem of judgment: farewell to public reason,” Political Theory 40(1):6-32. Ziarek, Ewa P. 2001. An Ethics of Dissensus: Postmodernity, Feminism, and the Politics of Radical Democracy, Stanford: Stanford University Press. –––. 2012. and the Politics of , New York: Columbia University Press.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy

Summer 2014 Edition 33 Feminist Political Philosophy

Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries affirmative action | democracy | Dewey, John: political philosophy | equality | exploitation | feminism, approaches to | feminist (interventions): ethics | feminist (interventions): history of philosophy | feminist (topics) | feminist (topics): perspectives on autonomy | feminist (topics): perspectives on power | feminist (topics): perspectives on the self | globalization | Habermas, Jürgen | homosexuality | identity politics | legal rights | liberalism | representation, political

Acknowledgments

For their helpful advice for this entry, I wish to thank Mary G. Dietz, Ann Garry, Bonnie Honig, Eva Kittay, Carole Pateman, R. Claire Snyder-Hall, Shay Welch, and Ewa Ziarek.

Copyright © 2014 by the author Noëlle McAfee

34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy