<<

Ling 107

Syntax - The Study of Sentence Structure

All human languages use sentences as minimal units of propositional expression, but the forms sentences can take in any language are infinitely varied. The study of sentence structure exposes the way in which human creativity is constrained by structure.

Compare the possibilities for creation in the lexicon and with sentences:

What is the longest word you know? / The longest sentence?

Can you make up a new word? / A new sentence?

Both questions reveal a level of creativity available at the sentence level, but not at the lexical level of a language. is the linguist’s attempt to understand this creativity and its limits.

We know there are limits on the sentences we produce just as there are limits on the forms of words in any language. Any speaker of English would agree that “* Take me out game the ball” is not an acceptable sentence. (Linguists use asterisks to mark unacceptable sentences.) How can we produce an infinite number of original sentences on one hand, and recognize that an infinite number of sentences are unacceptable on the other?

Chomsky (1965) observed that the creativity we observe in sentence construction raises an interesting problem for . Do children learn how to create sentences?

One hypothesis would be that children learn a language by simply imitating the sentences that other speakers produce. Imitation does not explain children’s ability to produce new sentences, or accept sentences that they have never heard other speakers produce.

A second hypothesis would be that children produce new sentences by combining words together in novel ways. Random generation would predict that children would also produce lots of unacceptable sentences before they learn the correct structure for sentences.

A third hypothesis is that children produce new sentences based on analogy with the sentences they hear other speakers produce. Analogy predicts children would also produce false analogies, e.g., *Are the girls who ____ good are getting cake? from Are the girls getting cake?

The solution to the acquisition problem lies in recognizing sentence structure and role it plays in organizing words. Sentence Structure

An account of sentence structure has to explain two basic features of sentences: 1. The linear order of the words in the sentence. A cat is on the mat =/ The mat is on the cat.

2. The grouping of words into constituents.

Constituent structure is another fundamental aspect of our grammatical knowledge. Not only can we recognize the difference between acceptable and unacceptable sentences, we can parse any acceptable sentence into smaller phrases or constituents, e.g.,

[Any speaker of English] [can split this sentence into two main constituents]

We can take this process further:

[Any] [speaker of English] [can] [split this sentence into two main constituents]

And even further if we want to.

Linguists use constituency tests as evidence to back up their intuitions about sentence components. Ideally the different constituency tests produce the same results, but they can also produce different results. It takes some practice with the tests to learn how to use them properly and interpret their results.

1. Semantic Intuition Test—decide if the words can be grouped together semantically.

Your intuitions about the semantic relations between the words in a sentence provide a basic insight into a sentence’s constituent structure. The phrase ‘into two main constituents’ specifies a result and is therefore a candidate constituent.

2. Substitution Test—see if a pro-form can be substituted for the proposed constituent.

Pronouns are an example of a pro-form, a form that can be substituted for a constituent of a specific type: substitute for determiner phrases do substitutes for verb phrases one substitutes for noun phrases there substitutes for prepositional phrases auxiliaries substitute for auxiliary phrases 3. Stand Alone Test—see if the proposed constituent can stand by itself.

It helps to imagine using the constituent by itself in response to a question: Who can split this sentence into two main constituents? Any speaker of English.

How can any speaker of English split this sentence? Into two main constituents.

4. Movement Test—see if the proposed constituent can be moved.

The movement test has more limitations than the other tests and is correspondingly more difficult to apply. One trick is to use a pseudocleft construction: [Two main constituents] is what [any speaker of English can split this sentence into].

as compared with

? Two main constituents any speaker of English can split this sentence into.

You should learn how to use the constituency tests to show that a set of words is NOT a constituent as well as to show that it is, e.g.,

1. Semantic Intuition ‘this sentence into two main constituents’ does not make sense.

2. Substitution Any speaker of English can split this =/ Any speaker of English can split this sentence into two main constituents

3. Stand Alone What can any speaker of English split? *This sentence into two main constituents

4. Movement *This sentence into two main constituents is how any speaker of English can split.

Constituent Properties

Once we agree on the existence of sentence constituents, we can explore how they are used to construct sentences.

We can identify different types of constituents, or phrases, e.g., Noun phrases: any speaker of English, this sentence, two main constituents Verb phrases: split this sentence into two main constituents Prepositional phrases: into two main constituents

The different types of phrases have some basic similarities.

One word, the head, is central to every type of phrase.

The head can take a complement phrase that provides an for the head, e.g.,

NP VP PP ru ru ru speaker of English split this sentence into two main constituents

Each phrase can take a that makes the referent more explicit, e.g.,

NP VP PP ru ru ru any speaker of English can split only into two

Abstracting away from the specifics, we can construct a template for ALL phrases:

Phrase u Intermediate ru Specifier Head Complement

Linguists commonly borrow terms from algebra to refer to the different parts of phrase structure:

XP u X’ ru Specifier X Complement

Just substitute any lexical type for X and you have an X phrase or XP!

An important aspect the so-called X-bar phrase structure is that both the specifier and complement are phrases in their own right. This feature produces the property of recursion that allows a rule to be repeated indefinitely. For example, noun phrases have prepositional phrase complements, and prepositional phrases take complements, which creates structures like: NP ru Spec N’ ru N PP ru P NP ru N PP | etc.

e.g., the height of the lettering on the top of the page

Recursion also allows us to add an indefinite number of adjectives to modify a noun:

NP eo Spec N’ qp AdjP N’ ty ep Spec Adj AdjP N’ ty t Spec Adj AdjP ty Spec Adj N

e.g., a very large, very black, rather undignified bulldog

Phrase Structure Grammar

I have been using tree structures to display the syntactic relations between constituents. Linguists also use phrase structure rules to describe the same relations. A phrase structure rule looks like the phonological rules we wrote earlier. It contains a symbol on the left side of an arrow that indicates the upper or mother node in the tree structure, and one or more symbols on the right side of the arrow that indicate the lower or daughter nodes in the tree structure.

Phrase structure rules and tree diagrams are equivalent notational devices. You can convert one into the other.

We can start by writing phrase structure rules that generate our first example sentence: Any speaker of English can split this sentence into two main constituents.

The sentence has two main constituents, a and predicate, so we will need a phrase structure rule like:

S ® NP AuxP

We can use X-bar theory to help us devise a phrase structure rule for the subject. We will need a specifier and a complement phrase:

NP ® Spec N’ N’ ® N PP

Note that I am assuming the prepositional phrase serves as a complement to the head of the noun phrase. The other constituent phrases can be divided into heads, specifiers and complements as follows:

AuxP ® Aux VP VP ® V NP PP PP ® P NP

These rules constitute a for (a fragment of) English. The rules describe the constituent structure of our sentence, and also provide a recipe for generating that sentence and many more. In theory, we should be able to add new rules to our grammar until we obtained a complete description of the language. Such a grammar would generate every possible sentence in the language, and would not generate any unacceptable sentences. Despite 50 years of serious grammar writing, linguists still haven’t produced such a grammar. We do not yet know if this problem can be solved.

You may have noticed some problems with the phrase structure rules I wrote to generate our first sentence. As written, the rules do not generate the last noun phrase ‘two main constituents’. How would we need to change the rule for noun phrases to generate this phrase?

Another problem with the rules is that they do not allow for the option of not generating some constituent. Three of the noun phrases in our sentence have specifiers, but one does not. One of the noun phrases has a complement, but three do not. Linguists use parentheses in phrase structure rules to capture this feature of optionality. We can rewrite the noun phrase rules to allow for optional specifiers and complements.

NP ® (Spec) N’ N’ ® N (PP)

The option of adding a modifier to the noun phrase raises the need for another type of option if we add a rule for adjectival modifiers as N’ ® AdjP N’

Linguists uses curly braces in phrase structure rules to capture this option.

N’ ® N (PP) 9 AdjP N’ A

We face two additional problems that X-bar theory creates. The phrase structure rules to generate an X-bar phrase would be:

XP ® (Spec) X’ X’ ® X (Comp)

Our new set of rules for noun phrases provide a good example of the X-bar template. Our rule for the is another story. Our verb phrase deviates from the X-bar template in that the verb has two complements rather than the single complement predicted by X-bar theory. We face a direct challenge to the theory and have to decide whether we want to keep the theory and find some way to shoehorn the verb phrase into the X-bar template, or change the X-bar template to allow multiple complements.

The second problem X-bar theory creates is seen in our first phrase structure rule.

S ® NP AuxP

How does this rule violate X-bar theory, and how can we change the rule to avoid such a violation?

Lexical Categories

Our phrase structure grammar still lacks one final rule for generating our sample sentence. We need a way to translate the terminal strings of our rules into actual words. The solution is simple enough; assume another rule translates the terminal strings into words of the proper lexical category.

N ® speaker, sentence, constituents V ® split Aux ® can Spec ® any, this, two P ® of, into Adj ® main

We can combine all of these rules into a single rule

X ® lexemex Here, lexeme points to a word in the lexicon that belongs to the lexical category X. This rule captures the idea that each word belongs to a part of speech that selects the appropriate specifier and complement phrases.

We can use several types of evidence to detect lexical categories in a language.

Notional categories

We can use word meaning to divide words into various notional categories.

Noun - the name of a person, place or thing Verb - the name of an action or state Adjective - the name of a quality Preposition - the name of a path or location

The problem with such notional categories is that they are rather imprecise. For example is an action a thing or an action?

Inflectional categories

We can use lexical inflection as evidence for separating words into different lexical categories.

Noun - inflect for plural, possession Verb - inflect for tense, aspect, voice, mood, Adjective - inflect for comparative, superlative

The problem with inflectional evidence is that it is not available for every category, and some words lack an overt inflection.

Syntactic categories

We can also use syntactic frames as evidence for grouping words into lexical categories. Words are used in specific syntactic contexts, which aid in analyzing the lexical categories.

Noun Det ______, Det Adj ______Verb Aux ______, Please ______Adjective ______N, Adverb ______Preposition ______NP, right ______Auxiliary ______V, ______not

Other Languages

Our lexical category tests do not apply to other languages. We cannot use inflectional evidence in languages that lack inflection–analytic languages. Likewise, we cannot use the presence of determiners as evidence for a noun category if the language does not require determiners in its noun phrases. We can divide words in any language into notional categories, but then we have no basis for constructing syntactic rules from notional categories.

We can determine what lexical categories exist in other languages and then try to decide the extent to which we find the ‘same’ lexical categories in different languages.

One would think that all languages would at least contain the lexical categories of noun and verb. The Salish languages of the Northwest challenge this assumption.

Kinkade (1983) Lingua, ‘Salish evidence against the universality of ‘noun’ and ‘verb’’

Upper Chehalis only has two lexical classes: predicates and particles

s-q’wct’-w-n continuative-burn-intrans-3sing ‘fire’ or ‘it is burning’

s-x/ cp-w-n continuative-dry-intrans-3sing ‘it is drying’

s-º§aláš ‘deer’ or ‘it is a deer’

§it-q’walán’- completive-ear-2sing ‘you are all ears’

Columbian Salish

s-q’á§-xn continuative-wedge_in-foot ‘shoe’ or ‘it is a shoe’

The category of adjectives also varies across languages. Quechua does not distinguish between adjectives and nouns:

chay runa hatun (kaykan) chay runa alkalde (kaykan) that man big is that man mayor is ‘That man is big’ ‘That man is mayor’

chay hatun runa chay alkalde runa ‘That big man’ ‘That mayor man’ (that man who is mayor)

K’iche’ expresses some adjectival notions as verbs:

x-in-war-ik x-in-kos-ik comp-1sing-sleep-status comp-1sing-tire-status ‘I slept’ ‘I was tired’

x-in-noj-ik x-in-kikot-ik comp-1sing-full-status comp-1sing-happy-status ‘I was full’ ‘I was happy’

Some languages (Jakaltek) lack prepositions.

Some languages have lexical categories that are not found in English. Mayan languages distinguish a category of positionals from other lexical types:

k-in-tak’-e§-ik k-in-paq-e§-ik

incomp-1sing-stand-POSITIONAL-status incomp-1sing-climb-POSITIONAL-status ‘I am standing’ ‘I am climbing’

We have the following categories in languages

Nootka (N, V) Jakaltek (N, V, A) Korean (N, V, P) English (N, V, A, P)

Linear Order

The linear order of heads, specifiers and complement phrases also varies across languages. We can describe these differences easily by means of phrase structure rules.

Korean (Head Last)

S ® NP VP VP ® (PP) (NP) V Chun ku chayk poata NP ® (Spec) N Chun that book see PP ® NP P ‘Chun saw that book’

Selayarese (Head First)

S ® VP NP VP ® V (NP) (PP) la§allei doe§ iñjo ri lamari iñjo i Baso NP ® N (Spec) take money the in cupboard the Baso PP ® P NP ‘Baso took the money in the cupboard’

Subcategories We often need to make finer distinctions between the words in a lexical category. Transitive verbs allow an object complement, but intransitive verbs do not. Ditransitive verbs take two complement phrases. There are also verbs that take adjective and sentence complements.

Intransitive verbs (Vi) fall, sleep, sneeze, jog Transitive verbs (Vt) throw, cut, acknowledge, seek Ditransitive verbs (Vdt) give, show, put Adjective complement verbs be, become Sentence complement verbs want, promise, say

Other parts of speech have similar restrictions on the types of complements they take.

Nouns

None car, electricity

PPto presentation, pledge

PPabout argument, discussion

Adjectives

None tall, smart

PPabout curious, glad

PPto apparent, obvious

In addition to complement types there are other types of subcategory distinctions. Singular count nouns require a determiner, but singular mass nouns do not.

Count nouns table, boy, wind, mesa Mass nouns water, gold, furniture

Trying to force all words into a specific lexical subcategory creates problems. Large classes of verbs regularly alternate between specific subcategories. The verbs break, tear and drop as well as the verbs eat, drink and see can appear as both transitive and intransitive verbs. English speakers differ over whether the noun data is mass or count. Linguists are currently attempting to describe and account for a wide range of phenomena associated with lexical subcategories.

Transformations

In addition to describing the internal structure of sentences syntax also looks at the relations between sentences. For example, we can transform a declarative sentence in English into a simple question by moving the to the beginning of the sentence. Any speaker of English can split this sentence into two main constituents.

becomes

Can any speaker of English split this sentence into two main constituents?

If we maintain that these two sentences are related in some fashion, then we can try to account for the relation. We could propose a movement rule, or transformation, to account for the relation. Such a rule raises a number of issues.

First Guess

Inversion Transformation X Aux Y ® Aux X Y

One problem with this version of the rule is that it is overly general. Think of an unacceptable sentence that this rule generates.

Another problem with this rule is that it doesn’t explain why we move the auxiliary to the beginning of the sentence. A subpart to this problem is that the rule does not tell where to put the auxiliary once we move it.

We can solve both problems by assuming the Auxiliary moves to a position that distinguishes the illocutionary force of a question from that of a declarative sentence. We can call the node that heads this position the Question node, which projects a Question phrase. I am assuming the process of forming a question includes creating a Question phrase which then attracts the auxiliary verb. We can make a further assumption that the auxiliary verb lands at the head of the Question phrase. Our revised inversion rule would then be:

Second Guess

Inversion Transformation Question X Aux Y ® Question-Aux X Y

The variable X in this formulation is still too general. We can tighten the rule further by specifying that X always refers to a subject.

Third Guess

Inversion Transformation Question NP Aux Y ® Question-Aux NP Y

This version of the rule asserts that the first auxiliary after the first noun phrase at the beginning of the sentence is the word that moves to the Question Phrase.

Other Languages Looking at other languages we find some interesting differences in their inversion rules.

French allows an auxiliary or main verb to move to the Question node.

Vois tu ___ le livre? see you ___ the book? ‘Do you see the book?’

As tu ___ essayé? have you ___ tried? ‘Have you tried?’

French only allows a verb or auxiliary to move across pronominal subjects. Movement across non-pronominal subjects is not acceptable.

*Sait Jean? ‘Knows John?’

*A Jean essayé? ‘Has John tried?’

French speakers resort to one of the following constructions to form such questions.

Est-ce que Jean sait? ‘Is it that John knows?’

Jean sait-il? ‘John knows-he?’

Spanish moves the main verb to the Question node, but not auxiliary verbs. The rule applies regardless of whether or not the subject is a .

Partió Juan ___ ? Partió él? leave John ___ ? ‘Left he?’ ‘Did John leave?’

*Ha Juan ___ partido? *Ha él partido? has John ___ left? ‘Has he left?’ ‘Has John left?’

K’iche’ simply introduces a particle to mark questions.

A xel lee a Waan? Q left the familiar John? ‘Did John leave?’ The K’iche’ rule resembles what happens in English when the underlying sentence does not contain an auxiliary verb. English introduces the auxiliary do is such situations, giving rise to a rule known as Do-Support. The French est-ce que construction suggests the language is moving in the direction of K’iche’.

The English Inversion rule changed during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Before this time English speakers could invert the main verb.

Speak they the truth?

Cross-linguistic comparison reveals several parameters are necessary to account for inversion across languages. All of these languages mark yes-no questions by marking a question feature at the left periphery of the sentence. The parametric variation for inversion includes:

1. Whether or not a particle is added to mark the question. 2. Whether or not the main verb moves. 3. Whether or not the auxiliary moves. 4. Whether or not the verb can move across non-pronominal subjects.