Marsilio Ficino's Commentary on Plato's Gorgias

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Marsilio Ficino's Commentary on Plato's Gorgias Marsilio Ficino’s Commentary on Plato’s Gorgias Leo Catana Abstract: Plato’s Gorgias sets out to discuss the nature translated in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, but, and aim of rhetoric. The dialogue was held in high esteem apart from the Meno, none of the dialogues conveyed among late ancient Platonists and it resurfaced in Renais- much about ancient sophists. In the Timaeus we find the sance discussions about ethics. Olympiodorus (6th cen- speaker Critias, whose relation to the speaker with the tury) produced an extensive commentary on the dialogue, same name in the Plato dialogue entitled Critias is dis- emphasising its ethical content. In 1409, Leonardo Bruni puted, but the central point is that Critias in the Timaeus (1369-1444) provided the first complete Latin translation did not convey theories under the banner of sophistry.1 In of the Gorgias with preface and annotations. Later in the Meno 93c, Meno had related that sophists (sophistai) Renaissance we find direct and indirect commentaries by promised to teach virtue (aretē), adding that he admired George of Trebizond (1395-1472/1473) and Marsilio Fi- Gorgias (probably a reference to Gorgias of Leontini), for cino (1433-1499). I argue that Ficino’s translation of, and his refusal to make such a promise; all he did was to teach commentary to, Plato’s Gorgias was a significant, but oratory. Gorgias of Leontini (485-380) was a historical perhaps also unintended, contribution to the dissemination figure, who went to Athens on a diplomatic mission in of ancient sophists in the Italian Renaissance. Ficino’s 427, and Plato’s Gorgias was clearly a reaction to his in- commentary to the Gorgias defends a legitimate and fluence on Athenian rhetoric and politics.2 In Meno 75e, philosophical use of rhetoric, including the one we find in Socrates had referred to Prodicus, but without linking his Plato’s own writings. Furthermore, Ficino treats the char- name to the sophists. In short, in the Medieval period acter Callicles – together with several other sophists in there was no Plato dialogue available in Latin in which a Plato’s dialogues – as an enemy of the Platonic- sophist featured as a speaker, incarnating and articulating Pythagorean ethical ideal, maintaining that the sophists sophistic theories and arguments in a elaborate manner. were wrong. Moreover, he treats ancient sophists as a This situation meant that little, apart from names and brief fairly homogeneous group, unlike some of the ancient assertions, were known about the ancient Greek sophists sources. in the Medieval period through the texts of Plato, the chief exponent of ancient Greek sophists. Keywords: Plato’s Gorgias, sophists, Marsilio Ficino, It should be noted, however, that even though Plato’s rhetoric, philosophy. dialogues offered the most elaborate (though biased) ac- count of ancient sophists and sophistry available to pos- terity, non-Platonic accounts of ancient sophists and soph- 1. Ficino and Renaissance sophistry istry existed in antiquity, and some of these were trans- mitted to the Latin Medieval tradition well before Fi- This article examines the Florentine humanist and phi- cino’s 1484 translation of Plato’s works. Notably, Aris- losopher Marsilio Ficino and his contribution to Renais- totle had dealt with sophistry and sophisms in his logical sance sophistry. At first sight this may appear as an un- as well as in his non-logical works, and these works had promising topic, since Ficino, an important Plato transla- been available in Latin translation for several centuries tor and Platonist, generally sided with Plato in his criti- before Ficino’s Plato translation came out.3 It should be cism of ancient sophistry: How could Ficino possibly observed, however, that Aristotle rarely referred to indi- have made a contribution to Renaissance sophistry? vidual sophists, so even though Medieval, Latin transla- The writings of ancient Greek sophists were lost in tions of Aristotle’s works proceeded Ficino’s Latin trans- antiquity, and their ideas were mainly known through re- lation of Plato’s dialogues and letters, these translations of ports made by a variety of ancient authors. Plato was one Aristotle’s works conveyed very little about the ancient of these authors, and he was the most important one, since sophists themselves, implying that to Medieval authors he portrayed several sophists and their ideas in a series of the ‘sophist’ was a virtually empty category, whereas his dialogues. As is well known, Plato did not do so in ‘sophistry’ and ‘sophism’ denoted fairly well-known order to provide a detailed and objective account of the logical categories. Albert the Great (ca. 1200-1280), for sophists’ ideas, but in order to refute their ideas. Hence instance, was familiar with the sophist name Gorgias we have good reasons for believing that his account was through Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations (183b37), biased. where Aristotle had criticised Gorgias for not conveying To the Medieval Latin tradition, Plato’s works were the art (technē) of rhetoric itself to his pupils, only its re- inaccessible with the exception of his Timaeus (up till sults; Albert’s knowledge about Gorgias did not transcend 53b), which was available in Latin throughout the Medi- these and other scattered notes found in Aristotle’s work.4 eval period. His Meno, Phaedo and his Parmenides were There is, however, another important source to an- University of Copenhagen Philosophical Readings XI.2 (2019), pp. 68-75. Copenhagen, Danmark DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.2554108 email: [email protected] MARSILIO FICINO’S COMMENTARY ON PLATO’S GORGIAS cient sophists that pre-dated Ficino’s Latin translation of authors, including Ficino, the tag ‘sophist’ denoted a bat- 1484, namely ancient doxographer Diogenes Laertius. In tle field rather than a well-defined profession. For this 1433, the Florentine humanist Ambrogio Traversari com- reason my second question — were ancient sophists a pleted a Latin translation of Laertius’ Lives, which subse- unified group – becomes even harder to answer, and I quently circulated in manuscript form before it was shall leave it open. printed in Rome in 1472. In general, this work became a The present article is on Ficino’s commentary on major source of information of ancient Greek philosophy Plato’s Gorgias. Was the protagonist Gorgias regarded as in the Renaissance, but it was almost silent as regards the a sophist by Plato and Ficino? Let me first turn to Plato. ancient sophists. In 9.50-56, Laertius presented a short In his Gorgias, the character Gorgias presents himself not entry on the life of one prominent ancient sophists, as a ‘sophist’ but as an orator (rhētōr) (449a6) mastering namely Protagoras. In 8.58, in the section on Empedo- rhetoric (rhētorikē), whose status as a craft (technē) is cles, he made a brief note on another ancient sophist, subsequently contested by Socrates. The fact that Plato Gorgias of Leontini: Laertius claimed that Gorgias was a has Gorgias presenting himself as an “orator” (rhētōr) pupil (mathētēs) of Empedocles, an accomplished orator, does not exclude, of course, that he is regarded as a soph- and the author of a manual on the art of rhetoric.5 ist in other of Plato’s dialogues. Besides, the orator and In 1484 Ficino published the collected works of Plato, the sophist may well co-exist in one person. This possi- containing a number of dialogues portraying some of the bility is affirmed in some of Plato’s other dialogues. In most influential ancient sophists. Given the restricted the Apology 19e, Socrates groups Gorgias of Leontini to- knowledge about sophists in the medieval period, this was gether with other sophists (sophistai) like Prodicus of a major event. We normally think of Ficino as the one Ceos and Hippias of Elis: They were itinerant teachers of who transmitted Plato’s ideas to the Latin tradition, but young people. In the Meno 95c, Meno asserts that Gorgias we should reckon that by doing so Ficino also played an differs from (other) sophists by not promising his pupils important role in the transmission of ancient sophistry. that he can teach virtue; he only teaches rhetoric. In Ficino did so by providing Latin translations of Plato’s (pseudo-)Plato’s Greater Hippias 282b4-5, Gorgias of dialogues discussing sophists and by writing commen- Leontini is spoken of as “Gorgias of Leontini, the famous taries to these dialogues — commentaries, that were sophist” (Gorgias te gar houtos ho Leontinos sophistēs). printed together with the dialogues themselves in the Now let me turn to Ficino: Did he regard Gorgias as a 1484 publication and in many subsequent publications of sophist? Plato’s collected works. Even though Ficino by and large Ficino, in his Gorgias commentary, describes soph- sided with Plato in his rejection of the sophists, he inad- ists as those who, under the guise of truth, divert men to- vertently promoted their ideas in the Renaissance. For this wards what is false.8 Gorgias of Leontini, the portrayed reason I think Ficino’s translations of, and especially his speaker in Plato’s Gorgias, did not aim at truth and jus- commentaries to, Plato’s dialogues on the sophists is a tice, but conformed with popular opinion, which prefers promising topic, if we want to understand the uses of the what has the appearance of truth and likelihood, Ficino ancient sophists in the Renaissance. It may be useful to says.9 In his Phaedrus, Ficino continues, Plato criticised clarify the historiographical concept of sophists before I Lysias, in the Gorgias he criticised Gorgias of Leontini.10 examine Ficino’s discussion of ancient sophists. Ficino affirms in his Protagoras commentary that Plato has Socrates criticising the “sophists” in the dialogue Gorgias, though in an elegant manner.11 The sophists re- 2.
Recommended publications
  • A History of Cynicism
    A HISTORY OF CYNICISM Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com A HISTORY OF CYNICISM From Diogenes to the 6th Century A.D. by DONALD R. DUDLEY F,llow of St. John's College, Cambrid1e Htmy Fellow at Yale University firl mll METHUEN & CO. LTD. LONDON 36 Essex Street, Strand, W.C.2 Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com First published in 1937 PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com PREFACE THE research of which this book is the outcome was mainly carried out at St. John's College, Cambridge, Yale University, and Edinburgh University. In the help so generously given to my work I have been no less fortunate than in the scenes in which it was pursued. I am much indebted for criticism and advice to Professor M. Rostovtseff and Professor E. R. Goodonough of Yale, to Professor A. E. Taylor of Edinburgh, to Professor F. M. Cornford of Cambridge, to Professor J. L. Stocks of Liverpool, and to Dr. W. H. Semple of Reading. I should also like to thank the electors of the Henry Fund for enabling me to visit the United States, and the College Council of St. John's for electing me to a Research Fellowship. Finally, to• the unfailing interest, advice and encouragement of Mr. M. P. Charlesworth of St. John's I owe an especial debt which I can hardly hope to repay. These acknowledgements do not exhaust the list of my obligations ; but I hope that other kindnesses have been acknowledged either in the text or privately.
    [Show full text]
  • DIOGENES of SINOPE Diogenes of Sinope (C
    DIOGENES OF SINOPE Diogenes of Sinope (c. 412‐323 BC), a contemporary of Plato and Aristotle, is considered the founder of the philosophical school of Cynicism. Concerned more with action than with words, he left no writings. What we know of his thought is what has been related to us by contempo‐ raries and later scholars. The most extensive account is from Diogenes Laertes, writing almost 500 years after Diogenes lived. LIFE OF DIOGENES OF SINOPE, THE CYNIC (404‐323 BC) RD BY DIOGENES LAERTIUS (3 CENTURY AD) Diogenes was a native of Sinope, son of Hicesius, a banker. Diocles relates that he went into exile because his father was entrusted with the money of the state and adulterated the coin‐ age. But Eubulides in his book on Diogenes says that Diogenes himself did this and was forced to leave home along with his father. Moreover Diogenes himself actually confesses in his Porde‐ lus that he adulterated the coinage. Some say that having been appointed to superintend the workmen he was persuaded by them, and that he went to Delphi or to the Delian oracle in his own city and inquired of Apollo whether he should do what he was urged to do. When the god gave him permission to alter the political currency, not understanding what this meant, he adulterated the state coinage, and when he was detected, according to some he was banished, while according to others he voluntarily quitted the city for fear of consequences. One version is that his father entrusted him with the money and that he debased it, in consequence of which the father was imprisoned and died, while the son fled, came to Delphi, and inquired, not whether he should falsify the coinage, but what he should do to gain the greatest reputation; and that then it was that he received the oracle.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dream of Reason: a History of Western Philosophy from The
    Contents Introduction Acknowledgements PART ONE 1 The Archetypes: the Milesians 2 The Harmony of the World: the Pythagoreans 3 The Man Who Searched for Himself: Heraclitus 4 The Truth about Nothing: Parmenides 5 The Ways of Paradox: Zeno 6 Love and Strife: Empedocles 7 Mind and Matter: Anaxagoras 8 He Who Laughs Last: Democritus 9 Opening Pandora’s Box: the Sophists PART TWO 10 Philosophy’s Martyr: Socrates and the Socratics 11 The Republic of Reason: Plato 12 The Master of Those Who Know: Aristotle PART THREE 13 Three Roads to Tranquillity: Epicureans, Stoics and Sceptics 14 The Haven of Piety: From Late Antiquity to the Renaissance Notes Index Introduction The last thing I expected to find when I began work on this book, more than ten years ago, is that there is no such thing as philosophy. Yet that, more or less, is what I did find, and it explained a lot. Determined to forget what I thought I knew, I set out to look at the writings of those from the past 2,600 years who are regarded as the great philosophers of the West. My aim (politely described by friends as ‘ambitious’ when they often meant ‘mad’) was to approach the story of philosophy as a journalist ought to: to rely only on primary sources, wherever they still existed; to question everything that had become conventional wisdom; and, above all, to try and explain it all as clearly as I could. As I ploughed through the diverse cast of characters from the fifth and sixth centuries BC who are traditionally lumped together as philosophers, through Socrates, Plato, Aristotle (often bracketed as a trio, but were there ever three more different men?), on to the intellectual therapists of Hellenistic times, through the mystics and occultists of late antiquity, to the first Christian thinkers, the logic-obsessed monks of the early Middle Ages, medieval scientists and theologians, Renaissance magicians, visionaries, grammarians and engineers and on to the beginnings of modern times, the fabric of ‘philosophy’ – supposedly the oldest of subjects – unravelled before my eyes.
    [Show full text]
  • Full Library Catalog
    Call Number Title Author Edition ISBN-13 ISBN-10 Publisher # Copies Keywords Other Locations Mythologies, Myths, Fabrications, AC25 .B36 Mythologies: The Complete Edition in a New Translation Barthes, R. 9780374532345 0374532346 Hill and Wang Deciphered, Debunked Here only AZ101 .F6913 1972 The Archaeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language Foucault, M. 9780394711065 0394711068 Vintage 2 Knowledge, Thinkers, Ideologies, Interests Willis, 3rd Floor Philosophy, History, Classics, Historical B29.C537 2003 The Classics of Western Philosophy Gracia, J. 9780631219064 0631219064 Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Texts Willis, 3rd Floor University of Minnesota Alain Badiou, Aristotle, Anaphora, B105.C46 A4313 1993 The Coming Community Agamben, G. 9780816622351 0816622353 Press Homonyms Human, Russell's Paradox Here only B105.M65 .M37 2002 Parables for the Virtual Massumi, B. 9780822328970 1822328828 Duke University Press Autonomy, body image, belonging Willis, 3rd Floor Communities, Past, Identities, History, B105.P53 .P59 2010 Places of Public Memory: The Rhetoric of Museums and Memorials Dickinson, G.; Blair, C.; Ott, B. L. 9780817356132 0817356134 University of Alabama Press Architecture Here only Guiguzi, China's First Treatise on Rhetoric: A Critical Translation and B128.K8372 .E54 2016 Commentary Wu, H. 9780809335268 0809335263 Southern Illinois Univ. Press Rhetoric, Chinese rhetorical tradition Here only Archaeology of consciousness, physis, University of South Carolina kosmos, logos, Sophistical wisdom, Socratic B187.L6 J635 2009 Listening to the Logos:Speech and the Coming of Wisdom in Ancient Greece Johnstone, C. L. 9781570038549 X00164YAQ5 Press wisdom, and the political life Here only University of South Carolina Protagoras, Xeniades, Gorgias, Prodicus, B288 .A4813 2001 The Older Sophists: A Complete Translation Sprague, R.
    [Show full text]
  • S.Y. Luria Democritus Texts Translation Investigations
    S.Y. LURIA DEMOCRITUS TEXTS TRANSLATION INVESTIGATIONS English translation by C.C.W. TAYLOR NAUKA PUBLISHERS Leningrad 1970 Copyright Note I have tried unsuccessfully to identify the present holder or holders of the copyright in Luria’s book, in order to seek permission for the publication of this translation. Enquiries made of the publisher in Moscow and St Petersburg and of the Society of Russian Authors in St Petersburg have failed to elicit the information sought. CCWT CONTENTS Translator’s preface Editors’ preface Abbreviations Texts Variant readings Concordance Luria – DK Index locorum Translation of texts Commentary Works of S.Y Luria relating to Democritus TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE In this volume I present a translation into English of S.Y. Luria’s edition of the fragments of Democritus and of the testimonia relating to him. The work has the sole aim of making Luria’s work available to students in the English-speaking world and in other countries worldwide who are familiar with English but not with Russian. A valuable Italian translation of Luria’s work (Democrito, Raccolta dei frammenti, interpretazione e commentario di Salomon Luria, ed. G. Girgenti et al., Edizione Bompioni, Milan) appeared in 2007, but my impression of the current level of comprehension of Italian, even among students of ancient philosophy, convinces me that, regrettably, only an English translation can expect to reach a truly worldwide audience. Our author’s full name, spelled in the Cyrillic alphabet, is Соломон Яковлевич Лурье, to which the closest approximation in the Roman alphabet is ‘Solomon Yakovlevich Lurye’. However, in publications in languages using the Roman alphabet.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias on Thought and Its Objects *
    r Chapter 16 Gorgias on Thought and its Objects * Victor Caston Und es ist kein Geschwiitz, wie man sunst wuhl glaubt; seine Dialektik is' objektiv. - Hegel, 1833, p. 37 Gorgias' 011 Not Being is the Charybdis of Presocratic philosophy. If taken at face value, it undermines the foundations of philosophy and life itself, by arguing, first, that there isn't anything; second, that even if there were something, it could not be known; third, that even if something could be known, no one could inform anyone else of it. Yet there is at least one thing, a treatise, that contains demonstrations for various conclusions, written in order to inform us, thus undercutting all three claims. How are we to construe a text charitably whose arguments are so obviously self-refuting in this way? This question alone makes it implausible to think that Gorgias endorses a particularly dark form of nihilism, the result (as some would have it) of philosophical despair and world­ weariness. 1 Gorgias would have to be not merely disconsolate, but quite dull-witted, to have missed the conflict between his presentation and its content. Similar considerations put in doubt any attempt to take Gorgias as a kind of relativisl.2 The self-undermining character of * It is a special pleasure to dedicate this essay to Alex Moure\atos, who has been a model teacher, a caring mentor, and a true friend. This piece is a very small return for all that I have gained and learned from him. I The classic statement of this position can be found in Diels, 1884, who argues that after a period of pursuing Empcdoc\ean physics, Gorgias entered a 'period of doubt, or rather despair,' during which Eleatic dialectic led him to reject natural science and write On Not Being; but unable to sustain this 'barren Nihilism,' in which 'the world of bcing had dissolved into empty appearance,' he turned to rhetoric, in an effort to turn 'appearance into reality in the beliefs of his audience' (pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Academic Questions by M
    The Project Gutenberg EBook of The Academic Questions by M. T. Cicero This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at http://www.gutenberg.org/license Title: The Academic Questions Author: M. T. Cicero Release Date: June 26, 2009 [Ebook 29247] Language: English ***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE ACADEMIC QUESTIONS*** The Academic Questions, Treatise De Finibus. and Tusculan Disputations Of M. T. Cicero With A Sketch of the Greek Philosophers Mentioned by Cicero. Literally Translated by C. D. Yonge, B.A. London: George Bell and Sons York Street Covent Garden Printed by William Clowes and Sons, Stamford Street and Charing Cross. 1875 Contents A Sketch of the Greek Philosophers Mentioned by Cicero.2 Introduction. 35 First Book Of The Academic Questions. 39 Second Book Of The Academic Questions. 59 A Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 142 First Book Of The Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 144 Second Book Of The Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 178 Third Book Of The Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 239 Fourth Book Of The Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 274 Fifth Book Of The Treatise On The Chief Good And Evil. 311 The Tusculan Disputations. 359 Introduction. 359 Book I. On The Contempt Of Death. 360 Book II. On Bearing Pain. 422 Book III. On Grief Of Mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Academica, 152, 157 Aporia, 139 Caelo, 81-89; De Caelo and De Anima, Nichomachean Ethics, 100- 101 ; on Generation and Corrupti
    Index Academic skepticism. See skepticism Arab civilization, 170 Academica, 152, 157 Arcesilaus, 141-144; leader of Academic Academy, 106, 118, 161 , 165; Old, 119, skeptics, 137, 140, 141; Montaigne and 139; Plato, xix, 51 , 61 , 63 , 105, 107, epoche, 171 ; Plato's Academy, I 06; 111 , 119, 159; Third, 144----145 Strata, friendship with, 112 Aenesidemus, 141 , 144 Archelaus, 53 Aetius, xviii Aristotle, 63-102; acroamata, xix, 65; afterlife, l 0, I 32 anima, 93 , 96; atoms, 88, 91 , 116; Age of Pericles, 49, 172 belief, 98; binary combinations, doubts, agnosticism. See Cicero 109; body and thought, 96, 97; Bruno, Agrippa, 139 use of Aristotle's materialism, 171; air. See elements Christian interpolations, 70---71; Alcmaeon, 13 compared with Plato, 66-69; cycles, Alexander the Great, 63 , 65 94----95, 95, 96; De Anima, 93-100; De Alexandria, I 05 , 169; scientists, 117 Caelo, 81-89; De Caelo and De Anima, Anaxagoras, 29-34; atomism, 58; links between, 109; Democritus, Democritus, 45; homoemeria, 129; influence, 46; first mover, 76; gravity or mentioned by Aristotle, 99; mind, 33, weight, 113, 160; imagination, 97-98; 54; spiritual transcendence, 56, 84, 158; left Academy, 61 ; life, 96; logic, trial, 50, 52 Aristotlean, 147; mass in motion, 85 ; Anaximander, 4----5 ; basic matter of materialism of pre-Socratics, 55; universe, 4; cycles, 4; globe, 5; heat and Melissus, criticism of, 25, 84----85, 86; cold, 5, I 09; universe, eternal history, Metaphysics, 77- 80; motion and force, 155 31; motion of living bodies, 160; Anaximenes, 6; air, 35; change and stasis, Nichomachean Ethics, 100- 101 ; On 31 ; cycles of elements, 20; death, 132 Generation and Corruption, 89-93; Andronicus of Rhodes, 77 oral doctrine.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and the Age of Pericles
    Chapter Two Plato and the Age of Pericles Radical doubt was fashionable among a generation of Sophists during the so- called Age of Pericles, which lasted roughly from 495-429 BC. The obvious absurdity of Greek mythology had finally provoked both outspoken skepti- cism and unrestrained secular speculation by many of the pre-Socratic phi- losophers. Disbelief came into vogue, and relevant to almost every issue the question boiled down to, "How can this assumption to be valid?" Or more to the point: "To what extent does it withstand sustained criticism?" Credible answers were formulated on a sustained basis to determine why or how any particular concept was worthy of consideration. Vigorous debate became commonplace as well as an enlarged emphasis on analytic skill that allowed more articulate and/or better-informed advocates to prevail at the expense of others. This pursuit of rhetorical advantage was perhaps best illustrated by an episode reported in Plato's dialogue Protagoras, when as a young dialecti- cian Socrates fell into argument with Protagoras, the first and most success- ful proponent of Sophism. Supposedly their purpose was to explain the basic difference between virtue and knowledge. Much was said, and no decisive explanation finally prevailed. More important, however, the standoff con- firmed that Socrates was a genuine contender quite aside from the seasoned capabilities of Protagoras. I. SOPHISTS It was almost inevitable that Sophism arose as a systematic commitment to disbelief. Sophists, however, took skepticism to excess, and it soon became almost a parody of itself. For example Gorgias, by many accounts the most eminent Sophist after Protagoras and Socrates, went so far as to insist that nothing exists, that if it did it would be unknowable, and if it were knowable 49 50 Chapter 2 it could not be communicated.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Philosophy
    A. C. Grayling T H E H I S T O RY O F P H I L O S O P H Y Contents Preface Acknowledgements Introduction PART I Ancient Philosophy Philosophy before Plato The Presocratic Philosophers Thales Anaximander Anaximenes Pythagoras Xenophanes Heraclitus Parmenides Zeno of Elea Empedocles Anaxagoras Leucippus and Democritus The Sophists Socrates Plato Aristotle Greek and Roman Philosophy after Aristotle Cynicism Epicureanism Stoicism Scepticism Neoplatonism PART II Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy Philosophy in Medieval Times Augustine Boethius Anselm Abelard Aquinas Roger Bacon Duns Scotus William of Ockham Philosophy in the Renaissance Renaissance Platonism Renaissance Humanism Renaissance Political Thought PART III Modern Philosophy The Rise of Modern Thought Francis Bacon Descartes Hobbes Spinoza Locke Berkeley Leibniz Hume Rousseau Kant The Eighteenth-Century Enlightenment Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century Bentham Hegel Schopenhauer Positivism Mill Marx Nietzsche Idealism Pragmatism PART IV Philosophy in the Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy Russell Frege Moore Wittgenstein: The Early Philosophy Logical Positivism Carnap Quine Popper Wittgenstein: The Later Philosophy Ordinary Language Philosophy Ryle Austin Strawson Philosophy of Language Davidson Dummett Kripke Philosophy of Mind Ethics Stevenson Hare Mackie Virtue Ethics Political Philosophy Rawls Nozick Feminist Philosophy Continental Philosophy Husserl Heidegger Merleau-Ponty Sartre Gadamer Ricoeur Deleuze Derrida Continental Thought: Un Salon des Refusés PART V Indian, Chinese,
    [Show full text]
  • Aristophanes and the Sophists
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1940 Aristophanes and the Sophists Joseph O. Schell Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons Recommended Citation Schell, Joseph O., "Aristophanes and the Sophists" (1940). Master's Theses. 359. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/359 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1940 Joseph O. Schell IC:: Aristophanes and the Sophists Joseph o. Schell, s. J. August 1940 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Loyola University. Vita Auctoris Joseph Otis Schell, s. J., was born in Port Huron, Michigan on May 30, 1914. He attended elementary school at St. James in Lakewood, Ohio. Graduated ~rom Lakewood High School in 1931, he entered Mil~ord Novitiate o~ the Society of Jesus in the same year. In 1935 he transferred to West Baden College o~ Loyola University where he received his degree of Bachelor of Arts in 1936. He attended the University of Toronto during the year 1938-39, and during the years, 1939-41, he taught at Saint Ignatius High School in Chicago. Table of Contents Chapter Title Page Chapter I Aristophanes' Criticism 1-23 of the Sophists.
    [Show full text]
  • The Greek Sophists : Teachers of Virtue David Dwyer Corey Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2002 The Greek sophists : teachers of virtue David Dwyer Corey Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Corey, David Dwyer, "The Greek sophists : teachers of virtue" (2002). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 270. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/270 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. THE GREEK SOPHISTS: TEACHERS OF VIRTUE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by David Dwyer Corey B.A., Oberlin College, 1992 B.Mus., Oberlin Conservatory, 1992 M.A., Louisiana State University, 1999 May, 2002 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation has had many sources of inspiration and support, and I have long looked forward to the opportunity to thank those who have been involved. Professor William F. Campbell and his wife, Helen (my father- and mother-in-law) accepted me into their family as a wayward stockbroker and through intellectual stimulation, love and ample quantities of food and wine produced a budding academic. Judy Petrie at First Presbyterian Church, Baton Rouge, encouraged me to go to graduate school and supported me generously through my first couple of years.
    [Show full text]