Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship polis, The Journal for Ancient Greek Political Thought 35 (2018) 478-498 brill.com/polis Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship Christopher Paone Western Connecticut State University, 181 White St, Danbury, CT 06810, USA / Sacred Heart University, 5151 Park Ave, Fairfield, CT 06825, USA [email protected] / paonec@ sacredheart.edu Abstract Against the traditional reading of Cynic cosmopolitanism, this essay advances the thesis that Diogenes’ world citizenship is a positive claim supported by philosophi- cal argument and philosophical example. Evidence in favor of this thesis is a new interpretation of Diogenes’ syllogistic argument concerning law (nomos) (D.L. 6.72). Important to the argument are an understanding of Diogenes’ philanthropic character and his moral imperative to ‘re-stamp the currency’. Whereas Socrates understands his care as attached specially to Athens, Diogenes’ philosophical mission and form of care attach not to his native Sinope but to all humanity. An important result is that Diogenes’ Cynicism provides an ancient example of cosmopolitanism that is philan- thropic, minimalistic, experimental, and utopian. Keywords Diogenes of Sinope – Cynicism – cosmopolitanism – law – citizenship 1 When Diogenes of Sinope (hereafter Diogenes) was asked where he was from, he replied that he was a citizen of the world (kosmopolitēs) (D.L. 6.63, 6.72).1 But what does ‘citizen of the world’ mean for the Cynic philosopher infamous for his biting wit and contempt for convention? Are there substantive philo- sophical commitments or argumentation supporting his self-identification 1 D.L. = R. D. Hicks (ed. and trans.), Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1925), [book number].[section number]. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi:10.1163/20512996-12340176Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 06:03:16PM via free access Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship 479 as world citizen? Or, is this one of his barbs aimed at mocking traditional Greek life? This essay advances the thesis that Diogenes’ world citizenship is a posi- tive claim supported by philosophical argument and philosophical example. Evidence in favor of this thesis includes a new interpretation of the controver- sial syllogistic argument concerning law (nomos) reported by Diogenes Laërtius (hereafter D.L.) and a consideration of Diogenes’ way of life as portrayed in the Cynic anecdotal tradition (D.L. 6.72). Important for both aspects of my argu- ment are an understanding of Diogenes’ philanthropic character and his moral imperative to ‘re-stamp the currency’, that is, the Cynic practice of ridding soci- ety of moral and political counterfeits (D.L. 6.20-1, 6.70-1).2 Briefly, I argue that Diogenes’ syllogistic argument shows an inconsistency in the ancient Greek understanding of law. The traditional ancient Greek view is that one becomes virtuous by living according to law (nomos) and its prescriptions, but the tradi- tionally ineluctably local understanding of law, according to Diogenes, draws one further from true law, namely, a Cynic life of virtue in accordance with nature, to which he exhorts everyone.3 Hence, Diogenes, in Cynic fashion, intends to re-stamp law: Law is not conventional but natural, not local but universal. The true citizen belongs not to any one city but to the cosmos. So whereas Socrates, in whose footsteps Diogenes follows, understands his philo- sophical mission and form of care as attached specially to Athens, Diogenes’ philosophical mission and form of care attach not to his native Sinope but to all humanity.4 If my argument is correct, then Diogenes’ Cynicism provides an ancient example of cosmopolitan practice that is, as I will conclude by attend- ing to his philosophic way of life, philanthropic, minimalistic, experimental, and utopian in character. In the following sections of the essay I will briefly 2 On the philanthropic character of Cynicism, see J. Moles, ‘“Honestius Quam Ambitiosius”? An Exploration of the Cynic’s Attitude to Moral Corruption in His Fellow Men’ in The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 103 (1983), pp. 103-123, esp. pp. 113-6. On re-stamping the currency see R. B. Branham and M.-O. Goulet-Cazé (eds.), The Cynics: The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1996), pp. 8-9, 24-5 and W. Desmond, The Greek Praise of Poverty: Origins of Ancient Cynicism (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006), pp. 16-7, p. 179n51. 3 On nomos, its meanings, and its subsequent opposition to phusis, see W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1971), p. 55ff. 4 See, for example, Plato’s Apology, Crito or the Theaetetus with R. Kraut, Socrates and the State (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984); G. Vlastos, ‘The Historical Socrates and Athenian Democracy’ in M. Burnyeat (ed.), Socratic Studies (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1994); and T. C. Brickhouse and N. D. Smith, Plato’s Socrates (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1994). But see also E. Brown, ‘Socrates the Cosmopolitan’, Stanford Agora: An Online Journal of Legal Perspectives, 1 (2000), pp. 74-87. Polis, The Journal for Ancient Greek Political ThoughtDownloaded from35 (2018) Brill.com10/01/2021 478-498 06:03:16PM via free access 480 Paone sketch some of the interpretative difficulties that face arguments concern- ing Cynicism and the meanings of cosmopolitanism (Section 2). Then, I will offer a new interpretation of Diogenes’ syllogistic argument in the context of Diogenes’ philosophic way of life (Section 3). Finally, I draw out several philo- sophical consequences of this new interpretation (Section 4). 2 As with nearly all the ancient Greek Cynic philosophers, the central diffi- culty for answering these questions is the dearth of reliable evidence. None of the writings attributed to Diogenes is extant. Like Socrates, he has become a literary figure, besides an historical one, and the two traditions, literary and historical, are thoroughly intermingled. The largest body of evidence for Diogenes is D.L.’s Lives of Eminent Philosophers, dating to the early half of the third century CE, over 500 years after Diogenes’ death (D.L. 6.20-81). D.L. offers many stories and sayings drawn from an anecdotal tradition, but it is not always clear how the sources, from which D.L. is working, intend to represent Diogenes. For example, some scholars argue that D.L.’s sources intend to show the Cynics as an important link in the succession from Socrates to the Stoics.5 If this evaluation is correct, then the most extensive source for the historical Diogenes may already be too contaminated with Stoicism to catch sight of an accurate picture of what thinking and arguments, if any, Diogenes himself would have offered in favor of his claim to be a world citizen. There are also several other sources for the Cynics earlier than D.L., but these face similar difficulties. These sources are either Stoic philosophers (Musonius and Epictetus) and their students (Dio Chrysostom) or satirists intending to mock the Cynics of their own time (Lucian). Additionally, there are fifty-one pseudepigraphical letters attributed to Diogenes, some of which date to the late first century BCE, others as late as the second century CE. These letters would represent our earliest extant writings of the Cynics in their own words. Scholars have shown, however, that the letters are the product of mul- tiple authors, probably written at different times, and later collected together.6 Moreover, the letters attributed to Diogenes are accompanied by other letters 5 See P. A. Vander Waerdt, The Socratic Movement (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994), p. 241ff. 6 See in particular the introduction to Malherbe’s edition and collection, including bibliogra- phy, in A. J. Malherbe (ed.), The Cynic Epistles: A Study Edition (Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press, 1977), pp. 1-5, 14-21. Polis, The Journal for Ancient Greek Political ThoughtDownloaded from35 (2018) Brill.com10/01/2021 478-498 06:03:16PM via free access Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship 481 attributed to philosophers not typically considered Cynics but who articulate views sympathetic to Cynicism. Because of the uncertain origin and dating of these letters, it may be difficult to discern what thought may be authen- tic. Nevertheless, the letters at least adhere to the spirit of Diogenes and his Cynicism, if not to the letter. On the questions of Diogenes’ use of kosmopolitēs and the status of his world citizenship there are generally two scholarly fronts. On the first front, the scholarship is concerned with whether Diogenes’ world citizenship is negative or positive.7 In other words, ‘negative’ means that world citizenship is intended to deny or reject the usual obligations Greek citizens of the same city-state may have to one another, whereas ‘positive’ means that world citizenship has some additional content all of its own, whatever that content may be. If his world citizenship is negative, then his self-identification is a rejection of life in the typical ancient Greek city, and of the social and political duties attached to it, and nothing more than this rejection of traditional values. In other words, Diogenes is simply saying, ‘I am not one of you’. If his world citizenship is positive, then the rejection of the typical ancient Greek city may also imply the character of a life that bears with it other kinds of duties, perhaps even of the universalist character that some modern conceptions of cosmopolitan- ism advocate. 7 The typical negative interpretation is clearly paraphrased by P. Kleingeld and E. Brown, ‘Cosmopolitanism’ in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2014), http:// plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/ cosmopolitanism, §1.1: [T]he first philosopher in the West to give perfectly explicit expression to cosmopolitan- ism was the Socratically inspired Cynic Diogenes in the fourth century BCE….
Recommended publications
  • The Cynicism of Diogenes
    DON‟T SHOOT THE MESSENGER! RETHINKING CYNICISM AND THE VALUE OF POLITICAL CRITIQUE by Suvi Maaria Irvine A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland December 2014 ©2014 Suvi Irvine All Rights Reserved Abstract: That Americans have become cynical about politics is often taken for granted in both popular and scholarly discourse. But what does it mean to be cynical? The answer to this question is far from simple and requires an investigation into the concept‟s origins, which reside in the ancient Greek philosophy known as classical Cynicism. Diogenes of Sinope, who remains the paradigmatic Cynic, was an abrasive figure in ancient Athens whose sneers and sarcasm where essential to his commitment to „living according to nature.‟ And for Diogenes, this meant living in accordance with the truth. He distrusted the social and political motivations of his fellow Athenians, and he called them out on their hypocrisy in ways that both amused and aggravated them. But what Diogenes did, above all, was demand room for honesty and the truth in the public sphere. I propose that his example is valuable in the context of contemporary American political culture, where honesty is rare and the truth is regularly disregarded. This dissertation presents an analysis of what cynicism can do for American political culture. I first address the question of what it means to be cynical and assess how much cynicism has changed since the days of Diogenes. While it may not mirror the original in all of its aspects, I argue that at root what it means to be cynical has not changed significantly, and that we can still identify cynics in our midst through their commitment to seeking and sarcastically speaking the truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine on Knowledge
    Augustine on Knowledge Divine Illumination as an Argument Against Scepticism ANITA VAN DER BOS RMA: RELIGION & CULTURE Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Research Master Thesis s2217473, April 2017 FIRST SUPERVISOR: dr. M. Van Dijk SECOND SUPERVISOR: dr. dr. F.L. Roig Lanzillotta 1 2 Content Augustine on Knowledge ........................................................................................................................ 1 Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................................ 4 Preface .................................................................................................................................................... 5 Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 7 The life of Saint Augustine ................................................................................................................... 9 The influence of the Contra Academicos .......................................................................................... 13 Note on the quotations ........................................................................................................................ 14 1. Scepticism ........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1986 The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five Michael Sollenberger Mount St. Mary's University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Sollenberger, Michael, "The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum, Book Five" (1986). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 129. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/129 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. f\îc|*zx,e| lîâ& The Lives of the Peripatetics: Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosoohorum Book Five The biographies of six early Peripatetic philosophers are con­ tained in the fifth book of Diogenes Laertius* Vitae philosoohorum: the lives of the first four heads of the sect - Aristotle, Theophras­ tus, Strato, and Lyco - and those of two outstanding members of the school - Demetrius of Phalerum and Heraclides of Pontus, For the history of two rival schools, the Academy and the Stoa, we are for­ tunate in having not only Diogenes' versions in 3ooks Four and Seven, but also the Index Academicorum and the Index Stoicorum preserved among the papyri from Herculaneum, But for the Peripatos there-is no such second source.
    [Show full text]
  • Simon the Shoemaker
    SIMON THE SHOEMAKER John Sellars 1399 3RD AVENUE -MANHATTAN- SIMON SHOE REPAIR -1- The name “Simon the Shoemaker” is not one im- mediately familiar to specialists in ancient philoso- 1 phy, let alone to students of philosophy in general. This may well be due, in part, to the tendency of many scholars both past and present to deny his historical reality altogether. Ancient sources refer to a Simon who, it is said, was an associate of Socrates and who ran a shoe shop on the edge of the Athenian agora where Socrates used to come to engage in philosophical discussions with Simon while he worked.2 However, the fact that neither Plato nor Xenophon mentions Simon has often been cited as an argument against his very existence. Moreover, it is reported that the Socratic philosopher Phaedo wrote a dialogue entitled Simon, and thus it has been sug- gested that the later “Simon legend” derived ultimately from a literary character created by Phaedo.3 The situation has somewhat changed since the discovery of the remains of a shop near the Tholos on the southwestern edge of the agora, the floor scattered with hobnails, containing a base from a pot with the word “Simon’s” inscribed upon it.4 Ar- chaeologists commenting upon this discovery have been keen to identify its owner with the Simon mentioned in the literary sources as a companion of Socrates, but scholars primarily concerned with ancient philosophy have tended to remain doubtful.5 Simon’s reputation relies principally upon the claim made by Diogenes Laertius that Simon was the first to write “Socratic dialogues.”6 Diogenes reports that these were also known as “shoemaker’s dialogues” or simply “shoemaker’s.” These, Diogenes says, were notes of actual conversations that Simon had had with Socrates rather than literary compositions.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Cynicism
    A HISTORY OF CYNICISM Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com A HISTORY OF CYNICISM From Diogenes to the 6th Century A.D. by DONALD R. DUDLEY F,llow of St. John's College, Cambrid1e Htmy Fellow at Yale University firl mll METHUEN & CO. LTD. LONDON 36 Essex Street, Strand, W.C.2 Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com First published in 1937 PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN Downloaded from https://www.holybooks.com PREFACE THE research of which this book is the outcome was mainly carried out at St. John's College, Cambridge, Yale University, and Edinburgh University. In the help so generously given to my work I have been no less fortunate than in the scenes in which it was pursued. I am much indebted for criticism and advice to Professor M. Rostovtseff and Professor E. R. Goodonough of Yale, to Professor A. E. Taylor of Edinburgh, to Professor F. M. Cornford of Cambridge, to Professor J. L. Stocks of Liverpool, and to Dr. W. H. Semple of Reading. I should also like to thank the electors of the Henry Fund for enabling me to visit the United States, and the College Council of St. John's for electing me to a Research Fellowship. Finally, to• the unfailing interest, advice and encouragement of Mr. M. P. Charlesworth of St. John's I owe an especial debt which I can hardly hope to repay. These acknowledgements do not exhaust the list of my obligations ; but I hope that other kindnesses have been acknowledged either in the text or privately.
    [Show full text]
  • The Recollections of Encolpius
    The Recollections of Encolpius ANCIENT NARRATIVE Supplementum 2 Editorial Board Maaike Zimmerman, University of Groningen Gareth Schmeling, University of Florida, Gainesville Heinz Hofmann, Universität Tübingen Stephen Harrison, Corpus Christi College, Oxford Costas Panayotakis (review editor), University of Glasgow Advisory Board Jean Alvares, Montclair State University Alain Billault, Université Jean Moulin, Lyon III Ewen Bowie, Corpus Christi College, Oxford Jan Bremmer, University of Groningen Ken Dowden, University of Birmingham Ben Hijmans, Emeritus of Classics, University of Groningen Ronald Hock, University of Southern California, Los Angeles Niklas Holzberg, Universität München Irene de Jong, University of Amsterdam Bernhard Kytzler, University of Natal, Durban John Morgan, University of Wales, Swansea Ruurd Nauta, University of Groningen Rudi van der Paardt, University of Leiden Costas Panayotakis, University of Glasgow Stelios Panayotakis, University of Groningen Judith Perkins, Saint Joseph College, West Hartford Bryan Reardon, Professor Emeritus of Classics, University of California, Irvine James Tatum, Dartmouth College, Hanover, New Hampshire Alfons Wouters, University of Leuven Subscriptions Barkhuis Publishing Zuurstukken 37 9761 KP Eelde the Netherlands Tel. +31 50 3080936 Fax +31 50 3080934 [email protected] www.ancientnarrative.com The Recollections of Encolpius The Satyrica of Petronius as Milesian Fiction Gottskálk Jensson BARKHUIS PUBLISHING & GRONINGEN UNIVERSITY LIBRARY GRONINGEN 2004 Bókin er tileinkuð
    [Show full text]
  • DIOGENES of SINOPE Diogenes of Sinope (C
    DIOGENES OF SINOPE Diogenes of Sinope (c. 412‐323 BC), a contemporary of Plato and Aristotle, is considered the founder of the philosophical school of Cynicism. Concerned more with action than with words, he left no writings. What we know of his thought is what has been related to us by contempo‐ raries and later scholars. The most extensive account is from Diogenes Laertes, writing almost 500 years after Diogenes lived. LIFE OF DIOGENES OF SINOPE, THE CYNIC (404‐323 BC) RD BY DIOGENES LAERTIUS (3 CENTURY AD) Diogenes was a native of Sinope, son of Hicesius, a banker. Diocles relates that he went into exile because his father was entrusted with the money of the state and adulterated the coin‐ age. But Eubulides in his book on Diogenes says that Diogenes himself did this and was forced to leave home along with his father. Moreover Diogenes himself actually confesses in his Porde‐ lus that he adulterated the coinage. Some say that having been appointed to superintend the workmen he was persuaded by them, and that he went to Delphi or to the Delian oracle in his own city and inquired of Apollo whether he should do what he was urged to do. When the god gave him permission to alter the political currency, not understanding what this meant, he adulterated the state coinage, and when he was detected, according to some he was banished, while according to others he voluntarily quitted the city for fear of consequences. One version is that his father entrusted him with the money and that he debased it, in consequence of which the father was imprisoned and died, while the son fled, came to Delphi, and inquired, not whether he should falsify the coinage, but what he should do to gain the greatest reputation; and that then it was that he received the oracle.
    [Show full text]
  • Traces of Cynic Monotheism in the Early Roman Empire*
    ACTA CIASSICA LI (2008) 1-20 ISSN 0065-1141 ARTICLES • ARTIKELS TRACES OF CYNIC MONOTHEISM IN THE EARLY ROMAN EMPIRE* P.R. Bosman Univel sity of South Africa ABSTRACT The ancient Cynics rejected traditional religion, themselves on first appearances endorsing either atheism or agnosticism. But their criticism may also have stemmed from a radical monotheism as voiced by Antisthenes. After briefly discussing imperial Cynics and their views on religion, the article argues that the 4th letter of Pseudo-Heraclitus and the Geneva Papyrus inv. 271, Cynic texts from the Early Empire, are not contrary to the essentials of the philosophy and may represent late Hellenistic forms of the Antisthenic tradition in portraying Cynic-type sages mediating between humankind and the God of nature. Introduction Cynic philosophy's roots go back to the 4th century BC, but it experienced a revival approximately simultaneous with the dramatic rise of Christianity. The two movements had much in common, not least their shared criticism of traditional Greco-Roman religion. 1 Two fundamental forces driving early Christian rejection of popular religion were belief in the one God of Judaism and a close association of his will with the rules for righteous living. It may be asked whether anything similar can be found in the Cynicism of that era. Some sources indeed suggest that the Cynics - traditionally focussing exclusively on ethics - were prepared to link their way of life to belief in a single God who provides or communicates the principles of correct conduct to the Cynic sage.2 * I wish to thank the referees of Acta Classica for valuable comments and corrections to this text.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • The Happiness Philosophers
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. Introduction A philosophy is the expression of a man’s intimate character. — William James But even as we as a nation have embraced education as critical to economic growth and opportunity, we should remember that colleges and universities are about a great deal more than measurable utility. Unlike perhaps any other institutions in the world, they embrace the long view and nurture the kind of critical perspectives that look far beyond the present. — dreW Gilpin faUsT, presidenT of harvard UniversiTy The Word “UTiliTarian” is not apt to strike the right chord in the world’s moral consciousness. Today, as in the nineteenth century, it can all too easily conjure up visions of soulless manager drones addicted to “efficient” adminis- tration in the least imaginative and most dehumanizing sense, or of those who would destroy a many-sided liberal education in the name of the immediately practical, useful, and vocational. The defenders of the humanities, including the presidents of Harvard and Columbia and their peers, have tended to define themselves by their opposition to instrumental or “utilitarian” approaches to education, which, it is implied, will prioritize “economic growth and opportu- nity” and miss the big issue: how over the long haul to cultivate individuals who can think critically, empathize with others, imagine better worlds, and actively engage in meaningful democratic citizenship. These, in their view, are the invaluable intangibles that cost-bene fit-minded, bean-counting, Dicken- sian utilitarian functionaries cannot even conceptualize much less defend.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Aristotelianism, Epicureanism, Cynicism, and Stoicism on Human Life in the Early Church
    Theological Research ■ volume 3 (2015) number 1 ■ p. 25–42 doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.15633/thr.1680 Arkadiusz Baron The Pontifical University of John Paul II in Krakow, Poland The Influence of Aristotelianism, Epicureanism, Cynicism, and Stoicism on Human Life in the Early Church Abstract: This article deals with the issue of ancient Greek models of life proposed by Aristotle, Epicurus and the Stoics. The author tries to describe how and which of these models were assimilated by Christian society during the first centu- ries and which were rejected. The purpose of this article is to show how im- portant Aristotle’s, the Stoics and Epicurus’ philosophy was for Christians in the advancement of the Christian lifestyle among the Greek societies. Un- derstanding the development of theology in the early Greek Church requires knowledge of the ideals and values that shaped the thinking and behavior of people before they heard about the Gospel of Jesus. Keywords Aristotle, Stoics, Epicurus, Plato, ancient Greek and Christian models of hu- man life 26 Arkadiusz Baron Introduction In the article Greek Models of Life up to Plato’s Philosophy and its Influ- ence on the Christian Life in the Early Church I presented a brief account of the ancient Greek models of life up to the time of Plato’s philoso- phy as well as their importance for the lifestyle of the first Christian generations. In the present article, I will search Aristotle’s, Epicurus’ and the Stoic’s writings to find the ideals they contained regarding the human person and I will attempt to show their influence on Christian writings in the firsts centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian-Stoicism
    Sacred Heart University DigitalCommons@SHU Master of Arts in Religious Studies (M.A.R.S. Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies Theses) 5-2016 Christian-Stoicism: Exploring the Relationship between Christianity and Stoicism and Constructing a Manual of Christian-Stoic Wisdom Trevor Kelly Sacred Heart University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.sacredheart.edu/rel_theses Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons, Christianity Commons, Comparative Methodologies and Theories Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Kelly, Trevor, "Christian-Stoicism: Exploring the Relationship between Christianity and Stoicism and Constructing a Manual of Christian-Stoic Wisdom" (2016). Master of Arts in Religious Studies (M.A.R.S. Theses). 28. http://digitalcommons.sacredheart.edu/rel_theses/28 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@SHU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master of Arts in Religious Studies (M.A.R.S. Theses) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@SHU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CHRISTIAN-STOICISM: EXPLORING THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN CHRISTIANITY AND STOICISM AND CONSTRUCTING A MANUAL OF CHRISTIAN-STOIC WISDOM Master’s Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Theology and Religious Studies at Sacred Heart University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in Religious Studies Trevor Kelly May, 2015 This thesis is accepted in partial fulfullment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Religious Studies. ______________________________ Brian Stiltner, Ph.D., Associate Professor of Theology and Religious Studies ___________________ 6/13/16 2 Permission for photcopying or electronic cataloging of “State the title of your study here” for the purpose of individual scholarly consultation or reference is hereby granted by the a uthor.
    [Show full text]