Philosophy and Ordinary Language: the Bent and Genius of Our Tongue/Oswald Hanfling

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy and Ordinary Language: the Bent and Genius of Our Tongue/Oswald Hanfling Philosophy and Ordinary Language Oswald Hanfling has written a lucid, painstaking, thorough and comprehensive defence of a certain method in philosophy, a method used, consciously or not, by many philosophers, derided by some, and mainly associated in our century with the names of Austin and Wittgenstein. Sir Peter Strawson, Oxford University This is a timely book. Oswald Hanfling offers a clearly-written and wide-ranging defence of ‘ordinary language philosophy’. Michael Beaney, Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg This is an important and much needed book. Oswald Hanfling engages in a lively defence of ordinary language philosophy – the appeal to ‘what we say’ – while correcting some of the errors of its founders (Austin and Ryle) and rebutting both traditional and recent philosophical attacks on ordinary language. A courageous and salutary effort! Robert Arrington, Georgia State University Oswald Hanfling is Professor of Philosophy at the Open University. He is the author of several books including, Logical Positivism, The Quest for Meaning, and Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy. Routledge Studies in Twentieth-Century Philosophy 1 The Story of Analytic Philosophy Plot and heroes Edited by Anat Biletzki and Anat Matar 2 Donald Davidson Truth, meaning and knowledge Edited by Urszula M. Zeglén 3 Philosophy and Ordinary Language The bent and genius of our tongue Oswald Hanfling Philosophy and Ordinary Language The bent and genius of our tongue Oswald Hanfling London and New York First published 2000 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2001. © 2000 Oswald Hanfling All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Hanfling, Oswald. Philosophy and ordinary language: the bent and genius of our tongue/Oswald Hanfling. p. cm. – (Routledge studies in twentieth century philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Ordinary-language philosophy. I. Title. II. Series. B828.36.H36 2000 149’.94–dc21 99-39028 CIP ISBN 0-415-21779-2 (Print Edition) ISBN 0-203-00351-9 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-17480-1 (Glassbook Format) Contents Acknowledgements ix List of abbreviations x Introduction 1 PART I The philosophy of ‘what we say’: its practice and justification 13 1 Socrates and the quest for definitions 15 2 Austin: ‘at least one philosophical method’ 26 3 Wittgenstein: bringing words ‘back to their everyday use’ 38 Wittgenstein and ordinary language 38 Wittgenstein and unordinary language 41 Ordinary language and the ‘bewitchment of our understanding’ 44 The ‘arbitrariness of grammar’ 49 4 ‘What we say’: who says? 53 What we say, what I would say, and what I would be prepared to say 53 Linguistic philosophy and empirical linguistics 56 ‘What we say’ and the diversity of usage 60 ‘Language-neutral’ and ‘language-specific’ 65 vi Contents 5 What is wrong with the paradigm case argument? 74 The paradigm case argument and the ostensive teaching argument 76 Free will and the paradigm case argument 78 Inductive reasoning and the paradigm case argument 85 What we say and what philosophers say 89 6 Knowledge and the uses of ‘knowledge’ 94 Some knowledge-situations 96 Knowledge and truth 99 Knowledge and belief 101 Knowledge and justification (i) 105 Knowledge and justification (ii) 108 7 The paradox of scepticism 111 The absolute certainty requirement 113 The requirement of ‘ruling out other possibilities’ 116 The consequential knowledge requirement 118 The onus of proof and the second-order knowledge requirement 123 Scepticism and ordinary language 124 PART II The philosophy of ‘what we say’: challenge and rejection 127 8 Drawing the curtain of words 129 ‘Disputes merely verbal’ 129 ‘Ideas bare and naked’ 133 Hume and the quest for meanings 138 Popper: facts, not words 141 Language and reality in ethics 143 Ethics and ontology 146 Contents vii 9 Language remade: ancient cities and orderly towns 150 A ‘logically perfect’ language 151 ‘Logic’s ruler’: Frege on the defects of language 153 Regimented notation as ‘a source of insight’ 159 Redefining our words: what we mean and what we ought to mean 163 Truth versus ‘convenience’: the theory of descriptions 169 The craving for answers 172 10 Grice: ‘true even if misleading’ 176 ‘The ordinary notion of perceiving’ 176 A note on method 181 Explaining the difference: (i) ‘cancellability’ 182 Explaining the difference: (ii) the ‘weaker/ stronger’ principle 185 Conversational implicature and truth-functional logic 188 Conversational implicature and the theory of descriptions 199 Conclusion 202 11 Quine and the unity of science 203 Philosophy and science 203 A shrouded science 208 ‘No statement is immune’ 212 12 Scientific realism: discovering what we really mean 222 Intension and extension 222 Intension and analytic truth 232 Rigid designators and ‘metaphysical necessity’ 234 Knowing what we mean 237 viii Contents Scientific realism and the meaning of ‘meaning’ 240 Philosophy and ‘intuition’ 241 13 ‘Folk psychology’ and the language of science 244 A need for replacement? 248 ‘Folk psychology’: a philosophers’ myth 250 Eliminativism and the first person 254 Explanation and justification 257 Throwing away the ladder 259 Index 262 Acknowledgements A number of people have helped me to work out my thoughts in various parts of the book. I am grateful in particular to Michael Beaney, Michael Clark, David Cockburn, Antony Flew, Laurence Goldstein, Severin Schroeder and Roger Woolhouse. To Peter Strawson I am especially grateful for comments on chapter 10. John Hyman supplied detailed and incisive comments on the penultimate draft of the book, which enabled me to make many improvements. Most of all I wish to thank Peter Hacker, who read and commented on drafts of every part of the book. His criticism and discussion over the years have greatly sharpened my understanding of the topics in question. Abbreviations Concepts CKP consequential knowledge principle OTA ostensive teaching argument PCA paradigm case argument Texts BB Blue and Brown Books (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1964) CN Conceptual Notation and Related Articles (G. Frege, transl. T. W. Bynum, OUP 1972) CTP ‘The Causal Theory of Perception’ (H. P. Grice in G. J. Warnock, The Philosophy of Perception, OUP 1967) EN ‘Epistemology Naturalized’ (W. V. Quine in Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Columbia 1969) FA The Foundations of Arithmetic (G. Frege, Blackwell 1980) ILT Introduction to Logical Theory (P. F. Strawson, Methuen 1952) LPV From a Logical Point of View (W. V. Quine, Harper 1961) MLR Mind, Language and Reality (H. Putnam, CUP 1975) MPD My Philosophical Development (B. Russell, Unwin 1959) NN Naming and Necessity (S. Kripke, Blackwell 1980) OC On Certainty (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1969) PG Philosophical Grammar (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1974) PHK Principles of Human Knowledge (G. Berkeley, Dent 1993) PI Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1958) PL Philosophy and Linguistics (C. Lyas (ed.), Macmillan 1971) PMC Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence (G. Frege, Blackwell 1980) Abbreviations xi PP Philosophical Papers (J. L. Austin, Clarendon 1961) PW Posthumous Writings (G. Frege, Blackwell 1979) RFM Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1978) SS Sense and Sensibilia (J. L. Austin, OUP 1962) WO Word and Object (W. V. Quine, MIT Press 1960) WW Studies in the Way of Words (H. P. Grice, Harvard 1989) Z Zettel (Wittgenstein, Blackwell 1967) Introduction It is impossible, even in the most rigid philosophic reasonings, so far to alter the bent and genius of the tongue we speak, as never to give a handle for cavillers to pretend difficulties and inconsistencies. (Berkeley) One can’t abuse ordinary language without paying for it. (J.L. Austin) I Philosophers often support their conclusions by reference to the use of language, pointing out that in such and such a case we might use the word A but not the word B, that we would not describe someone as X unless Y, and so on. Yet they also arrive at conclusions that are contrary to this criterion, as when they claim that knowledge is impossible or free will an illusion. When this is so, can the appeal to the ordinary use of language be set aside as a mere ‘cavil’? How important is the ‘bent and genius of the tongue we speak’ in philosophy? Are the problems of philosophy largely about language, and to be settled by reference to the ordinary uses of words? ‘Ordinary language’ is an expression that is often viewed with suspicion by philosophers nowadays. One reason for this was expressed by Bertrand Russell in his intellectual autobiography, where he criticized those who are ‘persuaded that common speech is good enough, not only for daily life, but also for philosophy’. ‘I, on contrary’, he continued, 2 Introduction am persuaded that common speech is full of vagueness and inaccuracy . .. Everybody admits that physics and chemistry and medicine each require a language which is not that of everyday life. I fail to see why philosophy, alone, should be forbidden to make a similar approach towards precision and accuracy.1 Now it is true that the language of everyday life would not be adequate for the sciences mentioned by Russell, but is that because it is vague and inaccurate? What a person says in ordinary language is sometimes vague or inaccurate, but then the fault does not lie in the language: it lies in his or her use of it, and here too lies the remedy.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 5. Language: Private, Public, Solitary, Shared on the Received
    Chapter 5. Language: private, public, solitary, shared On the received reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations1, the book contains an argument purporting to show the impossibility of a private language. There has been a lively debate, however, on how the relevant notion of a private language is to be understood, and what considerations should be taken to rule it out. Some have understood Wittgenstein to mean that a language must be something that several speakers actually share, while others take him to mean that a language must be something that they could, in principle, share. Or, slightly differently put, on one view, speaking a language presupposes the actual existence of a linguistic community upholding certain shared standards of meaning and correctness, while on the other view, it only presupposes that such a community might have existed. These views have come to be known as the ‘community view’ and the ‘solitary speaker’ view, respectively.2 Furthermore, supporters of the community view tend to think that the discussion about privacy holds a central place in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, whereas those who support the solitary speaker view usually see its bearings as limited to the issue of the privacy of experience. 1 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958). References to this work will be indicated with the abbreviation PI followed by paragraph number. 2 Rather than two monolithic positions, what we have here is a spectrum of views ranging between two extremes. To mention but a few examples: the best-known formulations of the community view are to be found in Norman Malcolm, “Following a Rule” in his book Nothing is Hidden (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), as well as in his essay “Wittgenstein on Language and Rules” in Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays 1978-1989 (ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior
    Incapacity Incapacity Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior Spencer Golub northwestern university press evanston, illinois Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Copyright © 2014 by Spencer Golub. Published 2014 by Northwestern University Press. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Golub, Spencer, author. Incapacity : Wittgenstein, anxiety, and performance behavior / Spencer Golub. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8101-2992-4 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889–1951. 2. Language and languages—Philosophy. 3. Performance—Philosophy. 4. Literature, Modern—20th century—History and criticism. 5. Literature—Philosophy. I. Title. B3376.W564G655 2014 121.68—dc23 2014011601 Except where otherwise noted, this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. In all cases attribution should include the following information: Golub, Spencer. Incapacity: Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2014. For permissions beyond the scope of this license, visit http://www.nupress .northwestern.edu/. An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high-quality books open access for the public good. More information about the initiative and links to the open-access version can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org. For my mother We go towards the thing we mean. —Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §455 .
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Haydn on Understanding Music
    Contemporary Aesthetics (Journal Archive) Volume 4 Volume 4 (2006) Article 15 2006 Wittgenstein and Haydn on Understanding Music Yael Kaduri Bezalel Academy of Art and Design, Jerusalem, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.risd.edu/liberalarts_contempaesthetics Part of the Aesthetics Commons Recommended Citation Kaduri, Yael (2006) "Wittgenstein and Haydn on Understanding Music," Contemporary Aesthetics (Journal Archive): Vol. 4 , Article 15. Available at: https://digitalcommons.risd.edu/liberalarts_contempaesthetics/vol4/iss1/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Liberal Arts Division at DigitalCommons@RISD. It has been accepted for inclusion in Contemporary Aesthetics (Journal Archive) by an authorized editor of DigitalCommons@RISD. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Wittgenstein and Haydn on Understanding Music Yael Kaduri About CA Abstract Journal Wittgenstein's remarks about music have motivated philosophers to build a comprehensive picture of his philosophy of music, concentrating on the central Contact CA issues of musical meaning. It is often claimed that, according to Wittgenstein, understanding music consist in grasping the internal relationships between Links musical events. Musical practice, however, is naturally saturated with what philosophers often call extra-musical meanings. The present study, by Submissions considering a musical issue in Haydn's instrumental music, attempts to show that musical language games in the Wittgensteinian sense involve explanations Search Journal of music that enhance the listener's ability to understand music by broadening his musical competence. Nevertheless, constituting understanding of music, these explanations might use professional musical terms as well as non-musical terms, comparisons, gestures and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Ebook-Mumford-Laws-In-Nature.Pdf
    Laws in Nature What are the laws of nature? Do they control the actions and movements of the other things that exist in our world? Is there a sense in which such laws are real things? Both scientists and philosophers have been attracted by the view that the world contains laws of nature. It is such laws that dictate the behaviour of particulars, rather than any of those things’ intrinsic or internal forces. In this book Stephen Mumford argues against this popular view. He shows that no adequate account has been produced of what such laws in nature would be, or how they would perform the work that has been required of them. In their place, he argues that there are other necessary connections in nature that can do all the work for which we thought laws were needed. This book offers a holistic and connected account of reality in which the world’s elements do not need to be activated or controlled by laws. It is not possible that these elements behave other than they do. The world is more of a jigsaw than a mosaic: its pieces can form only one picture, and laws are no part of it. Stephen Mumford is Reader in Metaphysics in the Department of Philo- sophy at the University of Nottingham. He is the author of Dispositions (1998) and various papers in metaphysics. He is editor of Russell on Meta- physics (2003) and Powers by the late George Molnar (2003). Routledge studies in twentieth-century philosophy 1 The Story of Analytic Philosophy Plot and heroes Edited by Anat Biletzki and Anat Matar 2 Donald Davidson Truth, meaning and knowledge Edited by Urszula M.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reformed Natural Theology?
    A REFORMED NATURAL THEOLOGY? SEBASTIAN REHNMAN University of Stavanger Abstract: This paper aims to counter the recent opinion that there is a peculiar epistemology in the reformed Church which made it negative to natural theology. First it is shown that there was an early and unanimous adoption of natural theology as the culmination of physics and the beginning of metaphysics by sixteenth and seventeenth century philosophers of good standing in the reformed Church. Second it is argued that natural theology cannot be based on revelation, should not assume a peculiar analysis of knowledge and must not pass over demonstration. INTRODUCTION The title of this paper admittedly contains some confusion. But recently a notion of an allegedly pessimistic natural theology based on (purportedly) revealed principles of the reformed Church has been circulating among philosophers.1 This notion is confused, since if the principles of natural theology are supernatural, then either it is not natural theology or it is circular. There may be a natural theology by philosophers in the reformed Church, but not a natural theology based on the doctrines of the reformed Church. It is moreover confused to characterise such a natural theology as pessimistic in contrast to an allegedly optimistic mediaeval one. For thinkers such as Anselm, Aquinas, Scotus and Suarez did not maintain the sufficiency of natural theology for Christian faith. For all the important Catholic mediaeval thinkers held to the conviction that divine revelation is absolutely necessary for us to flourish as human EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION 4/1 (SPRING 2012), PP. 151-175 152 SEBASTIAN REHNMAN beings and that, as far as ultimate metaphysical and moral questions are concerned, we remain in an utterly perilous state of ignorance without it.2 It is simply misleading to characterise natural theology in the reformed tradition in contrast with natural theology in the mediaeval tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam
    111 Hilary Putnam 011 111 A beautiful statement of almost all the ideas that I take to be of lasting value and vital importance Hilary Putnam Hilary Putnam is one of the most famous and influential living philosophers. In Hilary Putnam: Pragmatism and Realism, Putnam responds to ten new papers exam- ining his central ideas, written by highly respected Putnam scholars especially 0111 for this volume. Putnam’s work touches on almost every area of interest in contemporary Anglo- American philosophy. His ideas have had repercussions in the philosophy of language and the philosophy of mind, as well as countless areas of metaphysics. Many of Putnam’s most influential ideas can be traced back to his two key commit- ments: to pragmatism and to realism. In this book, well-known top scholars examine these two fundamental positions and their place in Putnam’s work. In addition to responding to each paper, there is a new essay by Putnam himself on pragmatism and nonscientific knowledge. The insight into Putnam’s work provided by the contributions to his work, 0111 combined with Putnam’s extensive and detailed responses, make this essential reading for anyone with an interest in the ideas and influence of Hilary Putnam. Contributors: Ruth Anna Putnam, Hilary Putnam, Richard Warner, Robert Brandom, Nicholas Rescher, John Haldane, Tadeusz Szubka, John Heil, Wolfgang Künne, Gary Ebbs and Charles Travis. James Conant is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Chicago. He is the editor of Putnam’s collected papers. Urszula M. Z˙eglen´ is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Turon´, Poland.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein. La 'Reorientación De La Filosofía'
    WITTGENSTEIN Reorientación de la filosofía por CARLA CORDUA Nº de Inscripción: 99.844 © Carla Cordua Derechos reservados para todos los países ISBN 956-201-322-7 A Roberto Sumario Prefacio................................................................ 5 I Filosofía y ciencia como teoría.................... 7 II La teoría: perspectivas críticas..................... 22 III La filosofía y la vida común y corriente....... 40 IV El fenómeno de la lógica............................. 60 V Necesidad................................................. 73 VI El contexto de la necesidad......................... 89 VII Claridad.................................................... 103 VIII Explicación con ejemplos........................... 122 IX Análogos del lenguaje................................ 140 X El lenguaje y los juegos.............................. 152 APÉNDICES I Torturas y enfermedades............................ 170 II Crítica de la teoría..................................... 172 III Polémicas o el arte de lanzar huevos........... 176 IV Diferentes diferencias................................ 179 V Wittgenstein en inglés............................... 182 VI ¿Qué forma parte de la lógica?................... 186 VII El filósofo y las imágenes........................... 194 VIII Contextos............................................... 200 IX ¿Teoría, investigación o qué?..................... 202 Bibliografía........................................................... 207 Prefacio El asunto de este libro es lo que se podría llamar el talante
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review Special Issue 2015 • Wittgenstein and Forms of Life Danièle Moyal-Sharrock d.moyal-sharrock @ herts.ac.uk Wittgenstein on Forms of Life, Patterns of Life, and Ways of Living Abstract This paper aims to distinguish Wittgenstein’s concept of ‘form of life’ from other concepts or expressions that have been confused or conflated with it, such as ‘language-game’, ‘certainty’, ‘patterns of life’, ‘ways of living’ and ‘facts of living’. Competing interpretations of Wittgenstein’s ‘form(s) of life’ are reviewed (Baker & Hacker, Cavell, Conway, Garver), and it is concluded that Wittgenstein intended both a singular and a plural use of the concept; with, where the human is concerned, a single human form of life characterized by innumerable forms of human life. Introduction This paper aims to demarcate Wittgenstein’s concept of ‘form(s) of life’ from other concepts or expressions that have been confused or conflated with it, such as, ‘language-game’, ‘certainty’, ‘patterns of life’, ‘ways of living’ and ‘facts of living’. The tendency to merge these concepts may in part be due to their all being what we might call framework concepts: concepts featuring basicness or ungrounded- ness. Wittgenstein’s reputation as a therapeutic philosopher who refrains from interventionist or constructive philosophical activity 21 Danièle Moyal-Sharrock CC-BY is unjustified.1 Particularly when we think of him as pushing his way through a lot of muddied and muddled philosophical water to emerge with many a brilliant ‘redeeming word’ (erlösende Wort) or concept – such as ‘form of life’ or ‘language game’. These concepts result from Wittgenstein’s attempts to present the familiar unseen – what is always before our eyes but is unnoticed because of its familiarity2 – in such a way that it becomes perspicuous.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE Professor Dr. Hans-Johann GLOCK
    CV_0421_Glock: 06.04.2021:06.04.21 13:04 CURRICULUM VITAE Professor Dr. Hans-Johann GLOCK A. General Name: Professor Hans-Johann Glock (M.A., D.phil.) married, two daughters (*1993 & 1995) Present Appointments: Professor für Philosophie (Ordinarius), Lehrstuhl für Theoretische Philosophie II, Philosophisches Seminar, Universität Zürich (since 01.09.2006) Visiting Professor School of Humanities, University of Reading Date of Birth: 12 February 1960 Nationality: German National Service: Conscientious objector, nursing (1980-81) E-mail: [email protected] Website: http://www.philosophie.uzh.ch/institut/lehrstuehle/theoretische2/team/glock ORCID: 0000-0001-6176-909X Areas of Specialization Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Animal Minds, Analytic Philosophy, Metaphilosophy, Wittgenstein Areas of Competence Theory of action, Philosophy of Biology Epistemology, Metaphysics, Kant. Education and Qualifications Obtained • Kepler Gymnasium, Freudenstadt (Abitur) '71–'79 • University of Tübingen: '81–'83 Prelims (Philosophy, German, Mathematics) June '83 • St. Anne's College, Oxford: '83–'84 Visiting Student • Free University of Berlin: '84–'86 M.A. (Philosophy, Linguistics) Double First Sept. '86 • Balliol College, Oxford '86–'87 • St. John's College, Oxford: '87–'90 D.Phil (Philosophy) June '90 Scholarships • German National Scholarship Foundation (Studienstiftung) '81–'86 • German Academic Exchange Service (DAAD) '83–'84 • German National Scholarship Foundation Ph.D. Scholarship '86–'89 • North Senior Scholarship, St. John's College, Oxford '87–'90 1 CV_0421_Glock: 06.04.2021:06.04.21 13:04 Previous Appointments • Course Tutor for Open University 01.01.87– 31.01.88 • Stipendiary Lecturer at St. Catherine’s College, Oxford 01.10.88– 30.09.91 • Junior Research Fellow at St.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics As The
    新進研究者 Research Note Secondary Meaning in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics Kumpei YAMAMURO Abstract This paper presents the possibility of interpreting the two uses of the words “same”, “analogous” and “similar” that are discussed in Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics as the primary and secondary meanings he discusses in Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology and Philosophy of Psychology — A Fragment. Although the hitherto overlooked significance of the concept of “secondary meaning” has been pointed out by a number of commentators, to the best of my knowledge, little research has been done on its potential significance in Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics. This paper is positioned as a preparatory work to discuss the significance. (1) Research Topic This paper proposes to interpret the two uses of the words “same”, “analogous” and “similar” that Wittgenstein discusses in LFM as the primary and secondary meaning, respectively. (2) Background and Previous Research At §276 of Philosophy of Psychology — A Fragment, Wittgenstein distinguishes between the primary and secondary meaning of a word. In order to see what the distinction is like, we must look at the preceding section: Given the two concepts ‘fat’ and ‘lean’, would you be inclined to say that Wednesday was fat and Tuesday lean, or the other way round? (I am strongly inclined towards the former.) Now have “fat” and “lean” some different meaning here from their usual one? — They have a different use. — So ought I really to have used different words? Certainly not. — I want to use these words (with their familiar meanings) here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quest for Meaning, 0631153330, 9780631153337, 225 Pages, Oswald Hanfling
    The Quest for Meaning, 0631153330, 9780631153337, 225 pages, Oswald Hanfling DOWNLOAD http://bit.ly/1nWvHIi http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?search=The+Quest+for+Meaning Most discussions of medical and practical ethics have avoided direct confrontation with the query: what is the value and meaning of human life? The book addresses these issues directly, examining the variety of philosophical questions in the area, their meaningfulness and the paradoxes suggested by answers to those questions. Each chapter is an attempt to identify and correct the biases and confusions in such discussions. DOWNLOAD http://is.gd/ZPXzTe http://bit.ly/1tfV5JD The meaning of life in the world religions , Joseph Runzo, 2000, Philosophy, 330 pages. This volume brings together some of the most distinguished thinkers in theield of theology to consider the question of the meaning of life in thearious global religions.. Knowledge and scepticism , Douglas Odegard, 1982, Philosophy, 170 pages. The Coherence of Theism , Richard Swinburne, 1977, Language Arts & Disciplines, 302 pages. God is often defined as a spirit who is present everywhere, knows everything, is able to do anything, is the creator of the world, is perfectly free, perfectly good, eternal. Does Life Have a Meaning? , Milton Karl Munitz, 1993, Philosophy, 114 pages. In pursuit of this goal, Munitz contends that we must recognize a basic distinction between two important dimensions of Reality: (1) the observable universe - the domain of. Philosophical Investigations , Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1968, Analysis (Philosophy), 250 pages. The Comic Element of Montaigne's Style , ZoГ© Samaras, 1970, French language, 253 pages. Philosophy of Language Meaning and Use in Wittgenstein's Blue and Brown Books, Oswald Hanfling, 1973, Language and languages, .
    [Show full text]
  • C©, Un 22307 Alexandria, VA
    -_-=1_ _ --.-_ . _ :i=T-:=j-5= :.-rT-I--I-:-i--i::- :i _i ,-` -ghooro Bulk Mail U.S. Postage o/,08ofalkunk%%X JB. PAID Permit No'. 5659 c©, un 22307 Alexandria, VA MR. DENNIS J. DARLAND /9999 1965 WINDING HILLS RD. (1304) DAVENPORT IA 52807 THE BERTRAND RUssl£LL SOCIETY THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIHTY 8UAR7ERIy 38{)2 North Kcnncui Avcnuc, New.sleller o the Berlrand Russell Sociel Chicago,11. 6()f4l -2814, U.S.A. February, 1998 No. 97 The Bertrand Russell Society was fountlcd in I t)74 lo I.oster a better understanding FROM TIIE EI)lTOR of Russcll's work and to promoLc idc:rs zin(I c{iuscs hc thought important. Tl`c `John Shosky Sociely's motto is Russell's statcmcnt, "Tlic g(}(){1 lil`c is one juspircd by love and guided by knowledge." FROM TIIE BRS I'RESIDENT: TILE ANNUAL MEETING .John I.enz The Bertrand Russell Society Quarterly is publi``hc(I in February, May, August, and November. Letters and manuscripts should bc iiddrcsscd to: PRELIMINARY PROGRAM FOR TIIE ANNUAL MEETING Papers, Panels, Workshops, Videos, and More 7 John Shosky BRS RUSSELL NEWS 1806 Rollins Drive Talking Points on Russell 11 Alexandria, Vlrginia 22307 ANTONY FLEW: PIIILOSOPHICAL HUMANIST oFFICHRs oF TIIE I}nRTRANI) Russnl,L socllITy John Shosky 13 Chair Michael Rockler BooK RnvlEw: RussELL.s powER President John Len7, F.van Selinger 16 Vice President Jan Eisler Vice PresidenVlnformation Emeritus Lee Eisler I}00K REVIEW: J/V7ERJIACES Secietary Ken Blackwell Robert Barnard 19 Treasurer Dennis Darland I}00K RF.VII]W: COLLECTED PAPERE, VOLUME 10 Tiln nl3RTRANn RussELL socllITy ON TIIR NIIT John Shosky 21 The Berlrantl Russet( Society Home Page vlDEO TIE.NiTrw.
    [Show full text]