Modeling Affirmative and Negated Action Processing in the Brain With

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Modeling Affirmative and Negated Action Processing in the Brain With Modeling affirmative and negated action processing in the brain with lexical and compositional semantic models Vesna G. Djokic♠ Jean Maillard| Luana Bulat| Ekaterina Shutova} ♠Department of Neuroscience, University of Southern California, USA |Dept. of Computer Science & Technology, University of Cambridge, United Kingdom }ILLC, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands [email protected], [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] Abstract ability of DSMs to predict fMRI patterns of sen- tential meanings (Pereira et al., 2018) and larger Recent work shows that distributional seman- narrative text passages (Wehbe et al., 2014; Huth tic models can be used to decode patterns of brain activity associated with individual words et al., 2016). They have shown that encoding mod- and sentence meanings. However, it is yet un- els based on word embeddings are able to capture clear to what extent such models can be used subtle aspects of sentence meaning in the brain, to study and decode fMRI patterns associated even when these models are oblivious of word or- with specific aspects of semantic composition der and syntactic structure. While promising, none such as the negation function. In this paper, of this research has so far systematically investi- we apply lexical and compositional seman- gated specific semantic composition phenomena tic models to decode fMRI patterns associated and processing at the syntax-semantic interface, with negated and affirmative sentences con- taining hand-action verbs. Our results show such as that of the negation function. reduced decoding (correlation) of sentences Negation is a fundamental abstraction necessary where the verb is in the negated context, as for efficient reasoning and communication (Horn, compared to the affirmative one, within brain 1989). Although it is typically marked syntac- regions implicated in action-semantic process- tically, the semantics of negation in natural lan- ing. This supports behavioral and brain imag- guage usage has proven to be rather challenging ing studies, suggesting that negation involves reduced access to aspects of the affirmative to pinpoint (Speranza and Horn, 2010). In logi- mental representation. The results pave the cal negation, the negation operator has been suc- way for testing alternate semantic models of cinctly described as a truth-functional operation, negation against human semantic processing reversing the truth value of a sentence. On the in the brain. other hand, from a pragmatic point of view, the primary function of negation is to direct attention 1 Introduction to an alternative meaning and can thus be, more Computational semantic models are increasingly generally, compared to our ability for counterfac- being evaluated in their ability to capture aspects tual thinking (Hasson and Glucksberg, 2006). It is of human semantic processing, including similar- also often assumed that negation entails affirma- ity and association judgments (De Deyne et al., tion (as it is always positive by default), yet the 2016) and semantic representation in the brain extent to which the the affirmative situation need (Bulat et al., 2017). Prior work shows that dis- be processes is debated (Orenes et al., 2014). De- tributional semantic models (DSMs) are able to spite the intuition that negated meanings are in- decode functional magnetic resonance imaging deed quite distinct from their affirmative counter- (fMRI) patterns associated with the meaning of parts, there is still no comprehensive account of concrete words (Anderson et al., 2013). Relevant how the brain represents negated entities. to our work, Carota et al.(2017) showed that the Neuroscientific studies on negation have pre- similarity structure of DSMs for action words cor- dominantly focused on studying negation of relates with that of fMRI patterns in brain regions action-related sentences and suggest that nega- implicated in action-semantic processing. tion blocks access to aspects of the affirmative More recent studies have also investigated the representation (Papeo et al., 2016). For exam- 5155 Proceedings of the 57th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, pages 5155–5165 Florence, Italy, July 28 - August 2, 2019. c 2019 Association for Computational Linguistics ple, negation of action-related sentences or im- a reduced correlation between the similarity struc- peratives involves decreased activity in motor sys- ture of DSMs of action verbs and fMRI patterns tems of the brain implicated in action semantics of negated as compared to affirmative action sen- when compared to the affirmative context (Tetta- tences. Importantly, we show for the first time that manti et al., 2008; Tomasino et al., 2010). How- negation impacts semantic similarity in motor ar- ever, overall reduced activation does not necessar- eas, but also to some extent language-related brain ily equate to a lack of information across patterns regions. These findings lend further support to the of activated or deactivated voxels in a brain region hypothesis that negation may involve reduced ac- (Kriegeskorte et al., 2008). More importantly, the cess to aspects of the affirmative mental represen- degree to which negation of action-related sen- tation. tences impacts access to lexico-semantic repre- sentations and semantic similarity in the brain is 2 Related Work not yet well understood. To contribute to our un- derstanding of negation and its modeling, we in- Decoding brain activity Mitchell et al.(2008) vestigate the extent to which lexical and compo- were the first to show that DSMs based on co- sitional semantic models can decode fMRI pat- occurrence counts with 25 sensorimotor verbs terns of negated and affirmative action sentences (e.g. see, hear, taste) can predict fMRI pat- in the brain using similarity-based decoding (An- terns associated with the meaning of concrete derson et al., 2016). We also test the extent nouns. Later research has demonstrated that a to which the representational similarity structure range of DSMs can decode fMRI patterns of con- (Kriegeskorte et al., 2008) of DSMs of action- crete nouns (Murphy et al., 2012; Anderson et al., verbs correlates with that of fMRI patterns asso- 2013; Bulat et al., 2017) and, more recently, ab- ciated with negated versus affirmative sentences stract nouns (Anderson et al., 2017). Most rel- containing hand-action verbs. We focus on motor evant to our study, Carota et al.(2017) showed areas and classical language-related brain regions that the similarity structure of a Latent Seman- implicated in action-semantic processing (e.g., un- tic Analysis (LSA) model for action words (nouns derstanding action words and sentences) (Pulver- and verbs) correlates with that of fMRI patterns in muller, 2005; Kemmerer, 2015). motor areas (left precentral gyrus (LPG)) and clas- sical language-related brain regions (left inferior DSMs have proven successful in modeling as- frontal gyrus (LIFG), left posterior middle tempo- pects of semantic composition in the context ral gyurs (LMTP)) implicated in lexico-semantic of the natural language inference task (Bowman processing (Binder et al., 2009). et al., 2015b). Although the modeling of logical Moving beyond words, other studies have negation using DSMs is wrought with challenges shown that DSMs can predict brain activity pat- (Kruszewski et al., 2017), current state-of-the-art terns associated with larger linguistic units (We- neural network based models appear to capture el- hbe et al., 2014; Huth et al., 2016; Pereira et al., ements of markedness asymmetry in negation (Li 2018). For example, Pereira et al.(2018) showed et al., 2016) and, presumably, implicitly model that a regression model mapping between fMRI negation at some level. In our experiments, we patterns of words and their word embeddings investigate the extent to which DSMs are able could synthesize vector representations for novel to decode (correlate with) fMRI patterns asso- sentences that correlate with the average of the ciated with the reading of sentences containing word embeddings of the sentence. Working with negated and affirmative action verbs. We exper- larger text fragments, Wehbe et al.(2014) and iment with (1) word-level representations of ac- Huth et al.(2016) have been able to predict neu- tion verbs; and (2) compositional semantic models ral activity associated with the processing of narra- (based on addition of word-level representations tives in the brain using encoding models with word and long short-term memory (LSTM) networks). embeddings (also syntactic markers) as features. In agreement with previous work, our results Although these findings suggest that DSMs are show that distributional representations of action able to predict fMRI patterns associated with the verbs (and to some extent verb-object phrases) processing of compositional meanings, they do not show reduced decoding for negated versus affir- reveal to what extent the models capture specific mative action sentences. This is also reflected as compositional phenomena nor the specific impact 5156 of linguistic context on semantic representation in to prior studies suggesting a link between action the brain. Our work extends this line of research to negation and the inhibition of actions (de Vega study individual aspects of semantic composition, et al., 2016). focusing on the negation function. These findings seem in some regards contrary to Modeling negation in NLP Kruszewski et al. the predictions of linguistic theories of negation. (2017) contrast logical negation, which captures
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 1 Negation in a Cross-Linguistic Perspective
    Chapter 1 Negation in a cross-linguistic perspective 0. Chapter summary This chapter introduces the empirical scope of our study on the expression and interpretation of negation in natural language. We start with some background notions on negation in logic and language, and continue with a discussion of more linguistic issues concerning negation at the syntax-semantics interface. We zoom in on cross- linguistic variation, both in a synchronic perspective (typology) and in a diachronic perspective (language change). Besides expressions of propositional negation, this book analyzes the form and interpretation of indefinites in the scope of negation. This raises the issue of negative polarity and its relation to negative concord. We present the main facts, criteria, and proposals developed in the literature on this topic. The chapter closes with an overview of the book. We use Optimality Theory to account for the syntax and semantics of negation in a cross-linguistic perspective. This theoretical framework is introduced in Chapter 2. 1 Negation in logic and language The main aim of this book is to provide an account of the patterns of negation we find in natural language. The expression and interpretation of negation in natural language has long fascinated philosophers, logicians, and linguists. Horn’s (1989) Natural history of negation opens with the following statement: “All human systems of communication contain a representation of negation. No animal communication system includes negative utterances, and consequently, none possesses a means for assigning truth value, for lying, for irony, or for coping with false or contradictory statements.” A bit further on the first page, Horn states: “Despite the simplicity of the one-place connective of propositional logic ( ¬p is true if and only if p is not true) and of the laws of inference in which it participate (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • The Syntax of Answers to Negative Yes/No-Questions in English Anders Holmberg Newcastle University
    The syntax of answers to negative yes/no-questions in English Anders Holmberg Newcastle University 1. Introduction This paper will argue that answers to polar questions or yes/no-questions (YNQs) in English are elliptical expressions with basically the structure (1), where IP is identical to the LF of the IP of the question, containing a polarity variable with two possible values, affirmative or negative, which is assigned a value by the focused polarity expression. (1) yes/no Foc [IP ...x... ] The crucial data come from answers to negative questions. English turns out to have a fairly complicated system, with variation depending on which negation is used. The meaning of the answer yes in (2) is straightforward, affirming that John is coming. (2) Q(uestion): Isn’t John coming, too? A(nswer): Yes. (‘John is coming.’) In (3) (for speakers who accept this question as well formed), 1 the meaning of yes alone is indeterminate, and it is therefore not a felicitous answer in this context. The longer version is fine, affirming that John is coming. (3) Q: Isn’t John coming, either? A: a. #Yes. b. Yes, he is. In (4), there is variation regarding the interpretation of yes. Depending on the context it can be a confirmation of the negation in the question, meaning ‘John is not coming’. In other contexts it will be an infelicitous answer, as in (3). (4) Q: Is John not coming? A: a. Yes. (‘John is not coming.’) b. #Yes. In all three cases the (bare) answer no is unambiguous, meaning that John is not coming.
    [Show full text]
  • Affirmative and Negated Modality*
    Quaderns de Filologia. Estudis lingüístics. Vol. XIV (2009) 169-192 AFFIRMATIVE AND NEGATED MODALITY* Günter Radden Hamburg 0. INTR O DUCTI O N 0.1. Stating the problem Descriptions of modality in English often give the impression that the behaviour of modal verbs is erratic when they occur with negation. A particularly intriguing case is the behaviour of the modal verb must under negation. In its deontic sense, must is used both in affirmative and negated sentences, expressing obligation (1a) and prohibition (1b), respectively. In its epistemic sense, however, must is only used in affirmative sentences expressing necessity (2a). The modal verb that expresses the corresponding negated epistemic modality, i.e. impossibility, is can’t (2b). (1) a. You must switch off your mobile phone. [obligation] b. You mustn’t switch off your mobile phone. [prohibition] (2) a. Your mobile phone must be switched off. [necessity] b. Your mobile phone can’t be switched off. [impossibility] Explanations that have been offered for the use of epistemic can’t are not very helpful. Palmer (1990: 61) argues that mustn’t is not used for the negation of epistemic necessity because can’t is supplied, and Coates (1983: 20) suggests that can’t is used because mustn’t is unavailable. Both “explanations” beg the question: why should can’t be used to denote negated necessity and why should mustn’t be unavailable? Such questions have apparently not been asked for two interrelated reasons: first, the study of modality and negation has been dominated by logic and, secondly, since the modal verbs apparently do * An earlier version of this paper was published in Władysław Chłopicki, Andrzej Pawelec, and Agnieszka Pokojska (eds.), 2007, Cognition in Language: Volume in Honour of Professor Elżbieta Tabakowska, 224-254.
    [Show full text]
  • Negation, Referentiality and Boundedness In
    WECATfON, REFERENTLALm ANT) BOUNDEDNESS flV BRETON A CASE STUDY Dl MARKEDNESS ANI) ASYMMETRY Nathalie Simone rMarie Schapansky B.A. (French), %=on Fraser University 1990 M.A. (Linguistics), Simon Fraser university 1992 THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIEiEMEN'I'S FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in the Department of Linguistics @Nathalie Simone Marie Schapansky, 1996 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY November 1996 All rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. BibiiotMque nationale du Canada Acquisitions and Direction des acquisitions et Bibliogra~hicServices Branch des services bibiiographiques Your hie Vorre rbference Our hle Notre r6Orence The author has granted an k'auteur a accorde une licence irrevocable nsn-exclusive f icence irtct5vocable et non exclusive allowing the National Library of perrnettant a la Bibliotheque Canada to reproduce, loan, nationale du Canada de distribute or sell copies of reproduire, prgttor, distribuer ou his/her thesis by any means and vendre des copies de sa these in any form or format, making de quelque rnaniere et sous this thesis available to interested quelque forme que ce soit pour persons. mettre des exemplaires de cette these a la disposition des personnes interessees. The author retains ownership of L'auteur conserve la propriete du the copyright in his/her thesis. droit d'auteur qui protege sa Neither the thesis nor substantial these. Ni la these ni des extraits extracts from it may be printed or substantiels de celle-ci ne otherwise reproduced without doivent &re imprimes ou his/her permission.
    [Show full text]
  • Aug 3 1 1990 Ubraries ,% Abstract
    NEGATION IN SYNTAX: ON THE NATURE OF FUNCTIONAL CATEGORIES AND PROJECTIONS by MIREN ITZIAR LAKA MUGARZA B.A. University of the Basque Country (1985) M.A. University of the Basque Country (1986) SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS & PHILOSOPHY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT.OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS at the MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY August, 1990 c Miren Itziar Laka Mugarza The author hereby grants to M.I.T. permission to reproduce and to distribute copies of this thesis document in whole or in part Signature of Author Department of Linguilstics & Philosophy Certified by A .. ....- - r S-, Keneth Hale Thesis Supervisor Accepted by . M Wayne O'0Neil OMTASSACHUIEIT Departamen al Committee AUG 3 1 1990 UBRARIES ,% ABSTRACT. The central concern of this work is the syntactic nature of negation in Universal Grammar, and its relation to other functional elements in the Syntax. The study argues that negation is not a syntactic category on its own; rather, it is one of the values of a more abstract syntactic category, named E, which includes other sentence operators, such as affirmation and emphasis (Chapter 2). It is also argued that the syntactic feature [negation] surfaces in other syntactic categories besides E. In particular, the existence of (N] (negative) Complementizers is defended; this acounts for a range of phenomena in various languages: across-the-clause licensing of Negative Polarity Items in English, the ditribution of the -nik complementizer in Basque, and the nature of Dubitative Subjunctive in Romance (Chapter 3). Chapter I argues for the existence of a universal requirement that inflectional heads such as negation (E) must be c-commanded by the syntactic head Tense at S- structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Expression and Interpretation of Negation: an OT Typology
    [REVIEW ] Expression and Interpretation of Negation: An OT Typology By Henriëtte de Swart, Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 77, Springer, Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London, New York, 2010, xvii+279pp. KIYOKO KATAOKA Kanagawa University* Keywords: bidirectional Optimality Theory, negative concord, double nega- tion, universality, markedness 1. Introduction The work aims to give a unified view of negation, polarity, and con- cord across different languages, dialects and diachronic stages of a lan- guage. The author takes her work as providing a general theory of human language and cognition to account for cross-linguistic variation in synchronic terms as well as diachronic terms. The basic view comes from the thesis by Dahl (1979) that negation is a universal category of natural language and also the thesis by de Swart (2009) that it is presumably a universal category of human cognition. Though cross-linguistic variation is a major topic, from both a synchronic (typology) and a diachronic (language change) perspective, the book inves- tigates mainly the negative indefinites (so-called n-words, which de Swart refers to as Neg-expressions) to draw the whole picture of Negative Concord (NC), where more than one Neg-expression leads to a single negation, and Double Negation (DN), where two Neg-expressions lead to a double nega- tion. Under the assumption that knowledge of first-order logic is part of human cognition, de Swart concentrates on how propositional negation in sentence structure is derived involving Neg-expressions, and tries to con- struct the same underlying mechanisms to exploit the relations between form * I am very grateful to Jennifer L.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Both of These and the Process of Short Time, and He
    1 DOCUMENT RESUME AL 001 322 ED 021 218 48 By- McNeill, David THE DEVELOPMENT OF LANGUAGE Behavior. Michigan Univ., Ann Arbor. Centerfcr Research on Language and Language Spons Agency- Office of Education(DHEW), Washington, D.C. Bureauof Research Bureau No- BR- 6-1784 Pub Date 1 Feb 68 Con trac t OEC- 3- 6-061784- 0508 Behavior, Progress Report No.VI. Note-226p.; Supplementary Report toStudies in Language and Language EDRS Price MF-S1.00 HC-$9.12 DEVELOPMENT, PHONOLOGY, Descriptors-*CHILD DEVELOPMENT, *CHILD LANGUAGE *LANGUAGE SYNTAX, TRANSFORMATIONS (LANGUAGE), *PSYCHOLINGUISTICS,SEMANTICS SURFACE STRUCTURE *VERBAL DEVELOPMENT This chapter, to be included in"Carmichael's Manual of ChildPsychology," edited by P.A. Mussen, deals with the connectionbetween the acquisitionof language and the growth of intellect, and the connectionbetween both of these andthe process of account for maturation. The authorfeels that various theoriesof development cannot the child's acquisition of grammarin a relativelyshort time, and hediscusses the bulk of the chapter reasons aswell as the lines which theexplanation must follow. The is a survey oflanguage acquisition itself.It is organized underthree major headings, of a grammar: syntax,phonology, and one for eachof the three main components of semantics. A descriptionof the methods typically used instudying the development The emergence of the componentsthemselves is traced each component is given. light of (insofar as it is known), and adiscussion of varioustheoretical issues in the of children the empirical findings ispresented. Wherever possible,mention is made exposed to languages otherthan English, with thechief contrast languagesbeing Russian and Japanese. (Seerelated document ED 017921.) (DO) -05C-.3-6-06/7047-1).5-08 e-r44111)1e.2146/F 'THEUNIVERSITY OFMICHIGAII i3X 6- 17P/ ?1,s1 011 Studies in Language and Intot - .7.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Analysis of Double Negation
    ISSN 1799-2591 Theory and Practice in Language Studies, Vol. 1, No. 10, pp. 1442-1445, October 2011 © 2011 ACADEMY PUBLISHER Manufactured in Finland. doi:10.4304/tpls.1.10.1442-1445 A Constructive Study of English and Chinese Double Negation Fushan Sun Qingdao University of Science and Technology, Qingdao, China Email: [email protected] Abstract—As a universally used linguistic structure, double negation has long attracted the attention of scholars in Chinese and foreign countries. But so far the research of double negation is limited to the study and analysis of negative words, negative markers and the surface structure of double negation, and is also restricted to one particular language. In this essay, based on contrastive linguistics and cognitive linguistics, I launch a comparison between English double negation and its Chinese counterpart from the cognitive perspective to identify similarities and differences between them, and furthermore I also attempt to elaborate the causes and motivations for its meaning. Index Terms—double negation, cognitive, iconicity, M—Principle What is the basis of the sense of double negation? Many linguists are interested in and concentrate on this issue. Palmer and Otto Jespersen are the most typical representatives of these scholars. Palmer said that two negative elements cancel each other to form a positive sense in a sentence. Otto Jespersen (1939) explains "All the languages seem to have a common law, that is, two negative makes a positive". In fact, this theoretical basis used the principle of logic that "two noes mean a yes". As to the issue why double negation can strengthen the.
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief History of Negation ∗ J.L
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Journal of Applied Logic 8 (2010) 277–301 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Applied Logic www.elsevier.com/locate/jal A brief history of negation ∗ J.L. Speranza a,LaurenceR.Hornb, a Argentine Society for Philosophical Analysis, St. Michael Hall, Calle 58, No. 611, La Plata, Buenos Aires, B1900 BPY, Argentina b Department of Linguistics, Yale University, P.O. Box 208366, New Haven, CT 06520, USA article info abstract Article history: The history of scholarship on negation tracks and illuminates the major developments Available online 14 April 2010 in the history of metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of mind, from Parmenides, Plato and Aristotle through Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein to contemporary Keywords: formal theorists. Our perspective focuses on the catalytic role played by the 20th century Negation philosopher of language Paul Grice, whose views on negation serve as a fulcrum for Grice Neo-Traditionalists his attempt to bridge the (neo-)Traditionalist and Formalist traditions in logical thought. Modernists Grice’s remarks on negation and speaker meaning and the elaboration of his ideas by Contradictory negation subsequent neo-Griceans are summarized and situated within a broader picture of the Contrary negation role of contradictory and contrary negation in the frameworks of Aristotelians, Medievals, Asymmetry of affirmation and negation early modern schoolmaster-logicians, 19th and early 20th century neo-Idealists and Formalists, Oxford ordinary-language analytics, practitioners of classical and non-classical logics, and a range of other philosophers and linguists.
    [Show full text]
  • Negation in Syntax--On the Nature of Functional Categories and Projections
    NEGATION IN SYNTAX: ON THE NATURE OF FUNCTIONAL CATEGORIES AND PROJECTIONS HIREN ITZIAR LAKA HUGARZA B.A. University of the Basque Country ( 1985) H.A. University of the Basque Country ( 1986) SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS & PHILOSOPHY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREHENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF f HILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS at the HASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY August, 1990 c Hiren Itziar Laka Mugarza The author hereby grants to H.I.T. permission to reproduce and to distribute copies of this thesis document in whole or in part Signature of Author /hr- bkJz artment of ~ingui'6tics& Philosophy Cestif ied by r-- Keneth Hale Thesis Supervi~or \ n PA A Wayne 0 '.Neil O'A~~*~H~~#~ZTCY~,OF TE Departanen .el Committee AUG 3 1IS90 The central concern of this work is the syntactic nature of negation in Universal Grammar, and its relation to other functional elements in the Syntax. The study argues that negation is not a syntactic category on its own; rather, it is one of the values of a more abstract syntactic category, named X, which includes other sentence operators, such as affirmation and emphasis (Chapter 2). It is also argued that the syntactic feature [negation] surfaces in other syntactic categories besides X. In particular, the existence of [Nl (negative) Complementizers is defended; this acounts for a range of phenomena in various lanquages: across-the-clause licensing of Negative Polarity Items in English, the ditribution of the -nik complementizer in Basque, and the nature of Dubitative Subjunctive in Romance (Chapter 3). Chapter 1 argues for the existence of a universal requirement that inflectional heads such as negation (Z) must be c-commanded by the syntactic head Tense at S- structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Negation Processing
    NEGATION PROCESSING A DYNAMIC PRAGMATIC ACCOUNT YE TIAN Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics UCL 2014 Declaration I, Ye Tian, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Acknowledgements First and foremost, my wholehearted thanks go to my supervisor Richard Breheny. I am honoured to have been his PhD student, and to have been guided, challenged and inspired by him. I have developed as a linguist and a critical thinker because of Richard. Special thanks go to Robyn Carston for her tremendous help and encouragement during my writing up period. Thank you Nathan Klinedinst for your insightful comments and ideas. Thank you Bob van Tiel for the help with constructing experiment items in Dutch and for data collection. Thank you Billy Clark and Sylvia Shaw for giving me the opportunity to develop as a teacher. My thanks also go to Andrew Nevins, Alison Hall, Ad Neelman and Hans van de Koot, Andrea Santi, Nino Grillo, Matthew Reeve, Kriszta Szendroi, Yasu Sudo for your interesting discussions and support. My PhD journey wouldn’t have been as rewarding and fun as it would have been without the discussions, support, the friendship and the daily jokes from the supercalifragilisticexpialidocious PhD bunch in Chandler House. Thank you Zoë Belk, Harris Constantinou, Natalia Cichosz, Thiago Galery, Felicity Deamer, Giulio Dulcinati, Elizabeth Eden, Elena Titov, Patrick Elliott, Matthew Gotham, Claire Grant, Sam Green, Jiri Kaspar, Akis Kechagias, Ya-Fang Lu, Giorgos Markopoulos, Diana Mazzarella, Nick Neasom, Isabelle Needham-Didsbury, Ezekiel Panitz, Thanasis Soultatis, Chao Sun, Irini Symeonidou, Kevin Tang, Maria Varkanitsa, and Xiaobei Zheng.
    [Show full text]
  • Basque Functional Heads
    Sentence Polarity and Word Order in Basque1 A well-known fact about Basque is that word order is sensitive to sentence polarity. In negative sentences, the relative order of the auxiliary and main verb is V-Aux, while in affirmative (neutral) sentences the order is Neg-Aux-V. The main goal of this paper is to argue for a new approach to this phenomenon within a grammar that assumes antisymmetry (Kayne 1994), and only XP movement. The proposal has two main components. First, drawing on Cinque‘s (1999) universal hierarchy of functional heads, it argues that the negative order—Aux-V—is the merged order. The affirmative V-Aux order is produced by raising of the VP to a higher, polarity-related position called PolP. Second, PolP is also argued to host the negative morpheme, ez, in negative sentences, and the emphatic marker, ba, in emphatic affirmatives. Evidence from scope interaction between negation and evidential and speech act particles suggests that the surface position of ez cannot be its merged position; rather ez is merged in a lower position and raises to spec, PolP. Part 1 of this paper discusses the surface ordering of clausal functional heads within Cinque‘s (1999) framework, and argues for VP raising in affirmative sentences. Part 2 argues for raising of ez to PolP. Part 3 discusses the behavior of verbal dependents drawing on Koopman and Szabolcsi‘s (2000) analysis of verb movement in Hungarian, German and Dutch. Part 4 addresses some remaining empirical problems. 1 1. The surface order of functional morphemes within Cinque’s
    [Show full text]