Negation in Syntax--On the Nature of Functional Categories and Projections

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Negation in Syntax--On the Nature of Functional Categories and Projections NEGATION IN SYNTAX: ON THE NATURE OF FUNCTIONAL CATEGORIES AND PROJECTIONS HIREN ITZIAR LAKA HUGARZA B.A. University of the Basque Country ( 1985) H.A. University of the Basque Country ( 1986) SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS & PHILOSOPHY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREHENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF f HILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS at the HASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY August, 1990 c Hiren Itziar Laka Mugarza The author hereby grants to H.I.T. permission to reproduce and to distribute copies of this thesis document in whole or in part Signature of Author /hr- bkJz artment of ~ingui'6tics& Philosophy Cestif ied by r-- Keneth Hale Thesis Supervi~or \ n PA A Wayne 0 '.Neil O'A~~*~H~~#~ZTCY~,OF TE Departanen .el Committee AUG 3 1IS90 The central concern of this work is the syntactic nature of negation in Universal Grammar, and its relation to other functional elements in the Syntax. The study argues that negation is not a syntactic category on its own; rather, it is one of the values of a more abstract syntactic category, named X, which includes other sentence operators, such as affirmation and emphasis (Chapter 2). It is also argued that the syntactic feature [negation] surfaces in other syntactic categories besides X. In particular, the existence of [Nl (negative) Complementizers is defended; this acounts for a range of phenomena in various lanquages: across-the-clause licensing of Negative Polarity Items in English, the ditribution of the -nik complementizer in Basque, and the nature of Dubitative Subjunctive in Romance (Chapter 3). Chapter 1 argues for the existence of a universal requirement that inflectional heads such as negation (Z) must be c-commanded by the syntactic head Tense at S- structure. Assuming this requirement, a unified account is provided for apparently unrelated phenomena induced by neqation i? English (do-support, sections 1.3 and 1.4) and in Basqu- [,ne.~ement of the inflected auxiliary, sections 1.1. and 1 2). Chapter 2 also presents an account of the phenomenon of 'double negation' in Romance, in terms of the category C and its projection, CP (section 2.6). It is argued that preverbal instances of the elements that induce 'double negation', such as nadie, nada, ninqQn etc., involve movement of the item in question to the specifier of XP, which is headed by a phonolagically non-overt negative element. Also, 'yes' and 'no' answers are discussed in relation to the C Projection; it is argued that such answers make crucial use of this syntactic category, and parametric differences between the three lanquages under study (English, Spanish and Basque) are considered in support of the hypothesis (section 2.7). The structure of Inflection in Spanish is considered in Chapter 3. The nsture of Subjunctive and its relation to Negation and Imperative Mood is discussed. A proposal is made concerning the inflectional structure of Spanish, this proposal is shown to generate exhaustively the entire verbal paradigm of this language, and it predicts a number of language-particular properties of Spanish (section 3.5). ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. It is of course impossible to be fair in dissertation acknowledgments. There are too many names to write down, and too many debts to attach to each one. Also, crucial help and inspiration often comes from unknown or even long forgotten sources. So dissertations may have authors who signed them and "own" them, but the fact remains that ideas are never born to a single, lonely thinker; they are the product of a community of minds. This is the nature of the game, no matter how inconvenient for administrative purposes. Hence, I can gladly claim that more people than I can name or even remember contributed to this work. Despite the hopelesneos of the task, I would still like to single out a few people, among the many I am indebted to. Thanks to all the members of the HIT Linguistics & Philosophy department; I consider myself inmensely lucky for the opportunity to participate in such a stimulating and challenging environment during my graduate years. The members of my thesis committee figure prominently in the group of people to whom I am most indebted: Howard Lasnik and David Pesetsky lent their wealth of knowledge of anything ever done in generative syntax, and yet their genuine excitement over any new puzzle; they provided a continuous and plentiful supply of energy and intelligence. Noam Chomsky and Ken Hale have been to main points of reference from the very beggining of my graduate years. They shared with me, always generously, the depth and breadth, the detail and the globality, the coherence and the diversity, the rigor and the fascination that pave their work in linguistics; my debt to them is inmense, and I only regret having been able to absorb but a minimal portion of what I was offered. Thanks to Richard Larson for being always enthusiastic, for arguing and disagreeing, and yet for making me think that what I said made sense, or, often, for having made what I said make sense, by arguing and disagreeing. To Irene Heim, for her intellectual frankness, which made each appointment a pleasure, and for giving me so many crucial comments and suggestions during the last stages of this dissertatioh. To Richard Kayne for his lectures, his suggestions, and for having the gift to teach one how to work. TO Jim Higginbotham for my first evr contact with semantics, and for unraveling in front of me the mysteries hidden inside something as simple as "snow is white". To Wayne O'Neil, for his survey in linguitics, where he let us relax and say what we thought without knocking us down with the flaws in our arguments. To Jim Harris for his input as a member of my generals committee, and for his help throuqh the secret ways of the administration. To Morris Halle and Donca Steriade, for introducing me to phonology and for never avoiding a question, no matter how many there were. Thanks to all the students in the department, to whom I owe many memorable times. To my classmatus Lori Holmes, Michael Hegarty, Kate Kearns, Peter Kipka, Scott Meredith and Duanmu San. To the 'youngsters', for all the fun and the warmth: Mika Hoffman, Peter Ihionu, Utpal Lahiri, Paul Law, Rolf Noyer and Chris Tancredi. To the unique 'fifth year' people, for a1 1 the chit-chat and advise: Vivian Deprez, Betsy Klipple, Harry Leder, Li Yafei, Bao Ziming. Very special thanks to Eulalia Bonet and Sabine Iatridou for being there, ready to talk and laugh about life, and for the long hours in the midst of a snow storm. To Anoop Mahajan for every single thing, and particularly for having stood by me, soothingly, in laughter and sorrow, day after day. To Doug Saddy, for reminding me to enjoy time. And lest, but absolutely not least, to my dearest 24 Magazine St. witches: Lisa Cheng, Hamida Demirdash and Kelly Sloan, for frienship, fun, feelings and fabulous food. TO Esther Torrego, who has been both a demanding professor and a most honest friend; both intellectually and personally, she has given me crucical support: I certainly owe her more than I will evEr have the chance to return. To Juan Uriagereka for his continuous and generous help from the beggining to the end, in work and in life. I would also like to thank Ignacio Bosque, whom I have never met, for his inspiring and austerely elegant work on Spanish syntax. Also, to Elena Benedicto, John Frampton, Jane Grimshaw, Beth Levin, hndrea Moro, Jean-Yves Pollock, Georges Rebuschi, Luiggi Rizzi, and Raffaella Zannuttini for their always insightful comments and suggestions at various stages of my work. The Basque colleagues that invaded the department in the fall of my last year made me feel at home: we all argued with the same passion and loudness over the same topics, at the same late hours of the night, to the amazement of those not in the know. Esker haunitz, Andolin Eguzkitza, Xabier Ormazabal, Jon Ortiz de Urbina, BeRat Oihartzabal and Miriam Uribe-etxebarria. To Jose Ignacio Hualde and Xabier Artiagagoitia for e-mail support and more. To the professors and friends at the University of the Basque Country, Patxi Goenaga, Joseba Lakarra, Lourdes ORederra, Ines Pagola and Pel10 Salaburu. To Ibon Sarasola, for his opening statement in my first undergraduate course: 'do not believe what I say just because I say it'. To Paul Horwich, for an extremely sharp and original prespective. Also, for sharing with me the long hours and the bitter coffee late at night in the office, keeping me sane and happy through dissertation rush. I would like to dedicate this dissertation to my school teachers, who run a clandestine school where kids could learn in Basque. I want to thank them for smiling and being cool when the state inspector came and we all had to speak in Spanish. And for the most wonderful History lessons, where two version that never coincided were taught: the one written by the loosers, which we could not repeat outside the walls of the classroom, and the one written by the winners, which we had to repeat, every year, in the state- exam. To all those brave and loving people who made going to school so much fun: AndereXo Maria Antonia, Irene, BegoFia, Belen, Antton, and many others whose names fade in my memory, and to my parents, Ikerne Mugartza and Pablo Laka, who sent me there and always gave it all expecting nothing in return. TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ACNOWLEDGMENTS CHAPTER ONE: THE TENSE C-COMMAND CONDITION 1.0. INTRODUCTION 1.1.
Recommended publications
  • Representation of Inflected Nouns in the Internal Lexicon
    Memory & Cognition 1980, Vol. 8 (5), 415423 Represeritation of inflected nouns in the internal lexicon G. LUKATELA, B. GLIGORIJEVIC, and A. KOSTIC University ofBelgrade, Belgrade, Yugoslavia and M.T.TURVEY University ofConnecticut, Storrs, Connecticut 06268 and Haskins Laboratories, New Haven, Connecticut 06510 The lexical representation of Serbo-Croatian nouns was investigated in a lexical decision task. Because Serbo-Croatian nouns are declined, a noun may appear in one of several gram­ matical cases distinguished by the inflectional morpheme affixed to the base form. The gram­ matical cases occur with different frequencies, although some are visually and phonetically identical. When the frequencies of identical forms are compounded, the ordering of frequencies is not the same for masculine and feminine genders. These two genders are distinguished further by the fact that the base form for masculine nouns is an actual grammatical case, the nominative singular, whereas the base form for feminine nouns is an abstraction in that it cannot stand alone as an independent word. Exploiting these characteristics of the Serbo­ Croatian language, we contrasted three views of how a noun is represented: (1) the independent­ entries hypothesis, which assumes an independent representation for each grammatical case, reflecting its frequency of occurrence; (2) the derivational hypothesis, which assumes that only the base morpheme is stored, with the individual cases derived from separately stored inflec­ tional morphemes and rules for combination; and (3) the satellite-entries hypothesis, which assumes that all cases are individually represented, with the nominative singular functioning as the nucleus and the embodiment of the noun's frequency and around which the other cases cluster uniformly.
    [Show full text]
  • 2008. Pruning Some Branches from 'Branching Spacetimes'
    CHAPTER 10 Pruning Some Branches from “Branching Spacetimes” John Earman* Abstract Discussions of branching time and branching spacetime have become com- mon in the philosophical literature. If properly understood, these concep- tions can be harmless. But they are sometimes used in the service of debat- able and even downright pernicious doctrines. The purpose of this chapter is to identify the pernicious branching and prune it back. 1. INTRODUCTION Talk of “branching time” and “branching spacetime” is wide spread in the philo- sophical literature. Such expressions, if properly understood, can be innocuous. But they are sometimes used in the service of debatable and even downright per- nicious doctrines. The purpose of this paper is to identify the pernicious branching and prune it back. Section 2 distinguishes three types of spacetime branching: individual branch- ing, ensemble branching, and Belnap branching. Individual branching, as the name indicates, involves a branching structure in individual spacetime models. It is argued that such branching is neither necessary nor sufficient for indeterminism, which is explicated in terms of the branching in the ensemble of spacetime mod- els satisfying the laws of physics. Belnap branching refers to the sort of branching used by the Belnap school of branching spacetimes. An attempt is made to sit- uate this sort of branching with respect to ensemble branching and individual branching. Section 3 is a sustained critique of various ways of trying to imple- ment individual branching for relativistic spacetimes. Conclusions are given in Section 4. * Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, USA The Ontology of Spacetime II © Elsevier BV ISSN 1871-1774, DOI: 10.1016/S1871-1774(08)00010-7 All rights reserved 187 188 Pruning Some Branches from “Branching Spacetimes” 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Layers and Operators in Lakota1 Avelino Corral Esteban Universidad Autónoma De Madrid
    Kansas Working Papers in Linguistics, Vol. 36 (2015), 1-33 Layers and operators in Lakota1 Avelino Corral Esteban Universidad Autónoma de Madrid Abstract Categories covering the expression of grammatical information such as aspect, negation, tense, mood, modality, etc., are crucial to the study of language universals. In this study, I will present an analysis of the syntax and semantics of these grammatical categories in Lakota within the Role and Reference Grammar framework (hereafter RRG) (Van Valin 1993, 2005; Van Valin and LaPolla 1997), a functional approach in which elements with a purely grammatical function are treated as ´operators`. Many languages mark Aspect-Tense- Mood/Modality information (henceforth ATM) either morphologically or syntactically. Unlike most Native American languages, which exhibit an extremely complex verbal morphological system indicating this grammatical information, Lakota, a Siouan language with a mildly synthetic / partially agglutinative morphology, expresses information relating to ATM through enclitics, auxiliary verbs and adverbs, rather than by coding it through verbal affixes. 1. Introduction The organisation of this paper is as follows: after a brief account of the most relevant morpho- syntactic features exhibited by Lakota, Section 2 attempts to shed light on the distinction between lexical words, enclitics and affixes through evidence obtained in the study of this language. Section 3 introduces the notion of ´operator` and explores the ATM system in Lakota using RRG´s theory of operator system. After a description of each grammatical category, an analysis of the linear order exhibited by the Lakota operators with respect to the nucleus of the clause are analysed in Section 4, showing that this ordering reflects the scope relations between the grammatical categories conveyed by these operators.
    [Show full text]
  • Definiteness and Determinacy
    Linguistics and Philosophy manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Definiteness and Determinacy Elizabeth Coppock · David Beaver the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract This paper distinguishes between definiteness and determinacy. Defi- niteness is seen as a morphological category which, in English, marks a (weak) uniqueness presupposition, while determinacy consists in denoting an individual. Definite descriptions are argued to be fundamentally predicative, presupposing uniqueness but not existence, and to acquire existential import through general type-shifting operations that apply not only to definites, but also indefinites and possessives. Through these shifts, argumental definite descriptions may become either determinate (and thus denote an individual) or indeterminate (functioning as an existential quantifier). The latter option is observed in examples like `Anna didn't give the only invited talk at the conference', which, on its indeterminate reading, implies that there is nothing in the extension of `only invited talk at the conference'. The paper also offers a resolution of the issue of whether posses- sives are inherently indefinite or definite, suggesting that, like indefinites, they do not mark definiteness lexically, but like definites, they typically yield determinate readings due to a general preference for the shifting operation that produces them. Keywords definiteness · descriptions · possessives · predicates · type-shifting We thank Dag Haug, Reinhard Muskens, Luca Crniˇc,Cleo Condoravdi, Lucas
    [Show full text]
  • Verbal Case and the Nature of Polysynthetic Inflection
    Verbal case and the nature of polysynthetic inflection Colin Phillips MIT Abstract This paper tries to resolve a conflict in the literature on the connection between ‘rich’ agreement and argument-drop. Jelinek (1984) claims that inflectional affixes in polysynthetic languages are theta-role bearing arguments; Baker (1991) argues that such affixes are agreement, bearing Case but no theta-role. Evidence from Yimas shows that both of these views can be correct, within a single language. Explanation of what kind of inflection is used where also provides us with an account of the unusual split ergative agreement system of Yimas, and suggests a novel explanation for the ban on subject incorporation, and some exceptions to the ban. 1. Two types of inflection My main aim in this paper is to demonstrate that inflectional affixes can be very different kinds of syntactic objects, even within a single language. I illustrate this point with evidence from Yimas, a Papuan language of New Guinea (Foley 1991). Understanding of the nature of the different inflectional affixes of Yimas provides an explanation for its remarkably elaborate agreement system, which follows a basic split-ergative scheme, but with a number of added complications. Anticipating my conclusions, the structure in (1c) shows what I assume the four principal case affixes on a Yimas verb to be. What I refer to as Nominative and Accusative affixes are pronominal arguments: these inflections, which are restricted to 1st and 2nd person arguments in Yimas, begin as specifiers and complements of the verb, and incorporate into the verb by S- structure. On the other hand, what I refer to as Ergative and Absolutive inflection are genuine agreement - they are the spell-out of functional heads, above VP, which agree with an argument in their specifier.
    [Show full text]
  • Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: a Case Study from Koro
    Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro By Jessica Cleary-Kemp A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair Assistant Professor Peter S. Jenks Professor William F. Hanks Summer 2015 © Copyright by Jessica Cleary-Kemp All Rights Reserved Abstract Serial Verb Constructions Revisited: A Case Study from Koro by Jessica Cleary-Kemp Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics University of California, Berkeley Associate Professor Lev D. Michael, Chair In this dissertation a methodology for identifying and analyzing serial verb constructions (SVCs) is developed, and its application is exemplified through an analysis of SVCs in Koro, an Oceanic language of Papua New Guinea. SVCs involve two main verbs that form a single predicate and share at least one of their arguments. In addition, they have shared values for tense, aspect, and mood, and they denote a single event. The unique syntactic and semantic properties of SVCs present a number of theoretical challenges, and thus they have invited great interest from syntacticians and typologists alike. But characterizing the nature of SVCs and making generalizations about the typology of serializing languages has proven difficult. There is still debate about both the surface properties of SVCs and their underlying syntactic structure. The current work addresses some of these issues by approaching serialization from two angles: the typological and the language-specific. On the typological front, it refines the definition of ‘SVC’ and develops a principled set of cross-linguistically applicable diagnostics.
    [Show full text]
  • Tagalog Pala: an Unsurprising Case of Mirativity
    Tagalog pala: an unsurprising case of mirativity Scott AnderBois Brown University Similar to many descriptions of miratives cross-linguistically, Schachter & Otanes(1972)’s clas- sic descriptive grammar of Tagalog describes the second position particle pala as “expressing mild surprise at new information, or an unexpected event or situation.” Drawing on recent work on mi- rativity in other languages, however, we show that this characterization needs to be refined in two ways. First, we show that while pala can be used in cases of surprise, pala itself merely encodes the speaker’s sudden revelation with the counterexpectational nature of surprise arising pragmatically or from other aspects of the sentence such as other particles and focus. Second, we present data from imperatives and interrogatives, arguing that this revelation need not concern ‘information’ per se, but rather the illocutionay update the sentence encodes. Finally, we explore the interactions between pala and other elements which express mirativity in some way and/or interact with the mirativity pala expresses. 1. Introduction Like many languages of the Philippines, Tagalog has a prominent set of discourse particles which express a variety of different evidential, attitudinal, illocutionary, and discourse-related meanings. Morphosyntactically, these particles have long been known to be second-position clitics, with a number of authors having explored fine-grained details of their distribution, rela- tive order, and the interaction of this with different types of sentences (e.g. Schachter & Otanes (1972), Billings & Konopasky(2003) Anderson(2005), Billings(2005) Kaufman(2010)). With a few recent exceptions, however, comparatively little has been said about the semantics/prag- matics of these different elements beyond Schachter & Otanes(1972)’s pioneering work (which is quite detailed given their broad scope of their work).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Negation in a Cross-Linguistic Perspective
    Chapter 1 Negation in a cross-linguistic perspective 0. Chapter summary This chapter introduces the empirical scope of our study on the expression and interpretation of negation in natural language. We start with some background notions on negation in logic and language, and continue with a discussion of more linguistic issues concerning negation at the syntax-semantics interface. We zoom in on cross- linguistic variation, both in a synchronic perspective (typology) and in a diachronic perspective (language change). Besides expressions of propositional negation, this book analyzes the form and interpretation of indefinites in the scope of negation. This raises the issue of negative polarity and its relation to negative concord. We present the main facts, criteria, and proposals developed in the literature on this topic. The chapter closes with an overview of the book. We use Optimality Theory to account for the syntax and semantics of negation in a cross-linguistic perspective. This theoretical framework is introduced in Chapter 2. 1 Negation in logic and language The main aim of this book is to provide an account of the patterns of negation we find in natural language. The expression and interpretation of negation in natural language has long fascinated philosophers, logicians, and linguists. Horn’s (1989) Natural history of negation opens with the following statement: “All human systems of communication contain a representation of negation. No animal communication system includes negative utterances, and consequently, none possesses a means for assigning truth value, for lying, for irony, or for coping with false or contradictory statements.” A bit further on the first page, Horn states: “Despite the simplicity of the one-place connective of propositional logic ( ¬p is true if and only if p is not true) and of the laws of inference in which it participate (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moods of Verbs Reteaching
    Name Date Lesson 5 The Moods of Verbs Reteaching The mood of a verb indicates the status of the action or condition it describes. Some actions and conditions are factual, while others exist only as possibilities or ideas. Indicative mood is used to make statements and ask questions about factual actions and conditions. STATEMENT Variety shows were popular in the early days of television. QUESTION Were ventriloquists more popular than acrobats? Imperative mood is used to give a command or make a request. The understood subject in a command is you. COMMAND Pick a flower from this bunch. Subjunctive mood is used primarily to express a wish or to refer to actions or conditions that are contrary to fact. The subjunctive form of a verb matches the past form of that verb. The subjunctive form of be is were. If a variety show were popular now, I might appear as a juggler. Another subjunctive form is used in formal writing to refer to a request or command. The top-rated singer insisted that we give him a better dressing room. A. Identifying the Mood of a Verb Indicate the mood of each underlined verb by labeling it with IND for indicative, IMP for imperative, or SUBJ for subjunctive. 1.Call your parents when you will be late. ____________ 2. Harry Truman became president after the death of Franklin Delano Roosevelt. ____________ 3. Take a moment to look over your term paper before you pass it in. ____________ CHAPTER 4 4. The Faculty Advisor urges that the meetings be over by 3:30.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 English Subjectless Tagged Sentences Paul Kay Department Of
    1 English subjectless tagged sentences Paul Kay Department of Linguistics University of California Berkeley, CA 94720 [email protected] 2 Abstract A colloquial English sentence like Fooled us, didn't they? contains a finite main verb but no expressed subject. The identity of the missing subject of fooled is recovered from the tag subject they: compare Fooled us, didn't she?, Fooled us, didn't you? This paper argues (1) that such subjectless tagged sentences (STSs) pose a problem for grammatical approaches based on movement and empty categories and (2) that STSs receive a revealing analysis as part of a finely articulated family of tagged sentence constructions when viewed within a non-derivational, constructional, multiple-inheritance-based approach.* *I would like to thank Peter Culicover, Liliane Haegeman, Charles Fillmore Andreas Kathol and Richard Oehrle for comments on previous versions of this paper, as well as an anonymous reviewer for Language. They have doubtless offered more good advice than I have accepted. 3 0. Introduction. It has been argued from several points of view that whatever can be done with empty categories (ecs) can be done without them (Ades and Steedman 1982, Gazdar et al. 1984, Kaplan and Zaenen 1989, Pollard and Sag 1994 chapter 9, Sag and Fodor 1994, Kay and Fillmore 1999, Sag 1999). It has also been argued that, because there is no hard evidence for their existence, linguistic theory would be better off dispensing with these unobservable entities (Pickering and Barry 1991, Sag and Fodor 1994, Sag 1999).1 The present paper purports to take the argument one step further by showing that there are things that can be done without empty categories that cannot be done with them, at least not with any of the ecs currently available.
    [Show full text]
  • The Syntax of Answers to Negative Yes/No-Questions in English Anders Holmberg Newcastle University
    The syntax of answers to negative yes/no-questions in English Anders Holmberg Newcastle University 1. Introduction This paper will argue that answers to polar questions or yes/no-questions (YNQs) in English are elliptical expressions with basically the structure (1), where IP is identical to the LF of the IP of the question, containing a polarity variable with two possible values, affirmative or negative, which is assigned a value by the focused polarity expression. (1) yes/no Foc [IP ...x... ] The crucial data come from answers to negative questions. English turns out to have a fairly complicated system, with variation depending on which negation is used. The meaning of the answer yes in (2) is straightforward, affirming that John is coming. (2) Q(uestion): Isn’t John coming, too? A(nswer): Yes. (‘John is coming.’) In (3) (for speakers who accept this question as well formed), 1 the meaning of yes alone is indeterminate, and it is therefore not a felicitous answer in this context. The longer version is fine, affirming that John is coming. (3) Q: Isn’t John coming, either? A: a. #Yes. b. Yes, he is. In (4), there is variation regarding the interpretation of yes. Depending on the context it can be a confirmation of the negation in the question, meaning ‘John is not coming’. In other contexts it will be an infelicitous answer, as in (3). (4) Q: Is John not coming? A: a. Yes. (‘John is not coming.’) b. #Yes. In all three cases the (bare) answer no is unambiguous, meaning that John is not coming.
    [Show full text]
  • Sequence-Of-Tense and the Features of Finite Tenses Karen Zagona University of Washington*
    Sequence-of-tense and the Features of Finite Tenses Karen Zagona University of Washington* Abstract Sequence-of-tense (SOT) is often described as a (past) tense verb form that does not correspond to a semantically interpretable tense. Since SOT clauses behave in other respects like finite clauses, the question arises as to whether the syntactic category Tense has to be distinguished from the functional category tense. I claim that SOT clauses do in fact contain interpretable PRESENT tense. The “past” form is analyzed as a manifestation of agreement with the (matrix past) controller of the SOT clause evaluation time. One implication of this analysis is that finite verb forms should be analyzed as representing features that correspond to functional categories higher in clause structure, including those of the clausal left periphery. SOT morphology then sheds light on the existence of a series of finer- grained functional heads that contribute to tense construal, and to verbal paradigms. These include Tense, Modality and Force. 1. Introduction The phenomenon of sequence-of-tense (SOT) poses several challenges for the standard assumption that a “past tense” verb form signals the presence of a functional category in clause structure with an interpretable ‘past’ value. SOT is illustrated by the ‘simultaneous’ reading of sentence (1): (1) Terry believed that Sue was pregnant. a. The time of Sue’s pregnancy precedes time of Terry’s belief (precedence) b. The time of Sue’ pregnancy overlaps time of Terry’s belief (simultaneity) For the ‘precedence’ reading in (1a), the embedded clause tense is semantically transparent in the sense that the past form was corresponds to a past ordering relation (relative to the time of Terry’s belief).
    [Show full text]