For the Devil the PARADOX of EMOTIONAL RESPONSE to FICTION

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

For the Devil the PARADOX of EMOTIONAL RESPONSE to FICTION Tesis doctoral sympathy for the devil THE PARADOX OF EMOTIONAL RESPONSE TO FICTION Tesis doctoral sympathy for the devil THE PARADOX OF EMOTIONAL RESPONSE TO FICTION GEMMA DEL CARMEN ARGÜELLO MANRESA DRS. JÈSSICA JAQUES Y GERARD VILAR DEPARTAMENT DE FILOSOFIA UNIVERSITAT AUTÒNOMA DE BARCELONA 2010 Then what vast body must we make the mind Wherin are men, beasts, trees, towns, seas, and lands; And yet each thing a proper place doth find, And each thing in true proportion stands? Doubtlesse this could not bee, but that she turnes Bodies to spirits, by sublimation strange; As fire converts to fire the things it burnes As we our meats into our nature change. From their grosse matter she abstracts their formes, And draws a kind of quintessence from things; Which to her proper nature she transforms, To bear them light on her celestiall wings: Thus doth she, when from things particular, She doth abstract the universal kinds; Which bodilesse and immaterial are, And can be log’d but onely in our minds. Extract from “Of the Soule of Man and the Immortalite Thereof” by Sir John Davies (1599) index introduction 11 SECTION I: ON WHAT IS FICTION 19 1.1. Introduction 21 1.2. Eliminativist Approaches to Fiction 25 1.3. Speech Acts Theories of Fiction 35 1.4. Make-Believe Theories of Fiction 45 1.5. Fictions: Imaginary Worlds of Possibility 59 SECTION II: ON OUR EMOTIONAL ENGAGEMENT WITH FICTIONS 69 2.1. Introduction 71 2.2. The suspension of disbelief Solution 77 2.3. Simulation and Empathy Solutions 83 2.4. Thought-based Solutions 107 2.5. The Sympathy Solution 115 2.6. Sympathy for the Devil: An Approach to Aesthetic Cinematographic Experience 145 CONCLUSIONS: SOME NOTES ON IMAGINATIVE RESISTANCE 163 bibliography 169 INTRODUCTION During the last thirty years there has been a fruitful debate around the so-called “Paradox of fiction” or the “Paradox of emotional response to fiction”. That is, how can fictional situations move us even if we know they do not exist? When we read a novel, assist to the theater or when we watch a film at home we normally react emotionally if the stories these mediums present engage us in such a way that move us to tears, horror, indignation, annoyance, etc. However, we know that these stories and the characters within them are not real. Then, there is a problem, at least in philosophical terms. As members of the audience we do not think that we are falling into a paradoxical situation when we feel scared in watching or even reading It (King, 1987; Lee Wallace [dir.], 1990), on the contrary we consider that it is “normal” to feel in that way unless we would feel ashamed if someone else is watching us getting startled. But this later situation is typical, not problematic1. The problem lies in an inconsistency between our beliefs on what is presented to us, in other words, the fictitious situation, and our emotional reactions to it. In consequence the paradox of fiction consists in the following statement: “We have emotions for fictional persons or situations, even we do not believe in their existence” (Levinson, 2006b). Colin Radford first stated this paradox in 1975 in the widely discussed article “How can be moved by the fate of Anna Karenina”. In this work Radford argued that “our being moved in certain ways by works of art, thought very ‘natural’ to us and in that way only too intelligible, involves us in inconsistency and so incoherence”. In ordinary circumstances we have emotions towards objects and states of affairs in which we believe in. For example, if I am afraid to a dog I feel frightened because I believe it is dangerous, otherwise I would be calmed. This argument is based on a cognitive view of emotions that will be widely discussed in this work. According to Cheshire Calhoun and Robert Solomon (1992) studies on emotions are in between philosophy and psychology. The first philosophers in an attempt to understand emotions were Aristotle (2005, 2000, 1988) and the Stoics (Seneca, 1986) and afterwards there are five major theories that try to explain what is an emotion2: 1. Theories of the sentiment: Emotions are sensations or sentiments and it is important to understand our inner experience of them (Hume 1996, 1893, 1757a). 11 2. Physiological theories: Emotions are tied to our perception of our bodily sensations (Descartes, 1985, James, 1884). 3. Behavioral theories: Emotions are dispositions to behave in certain way like in Darwin’s proposal (Cheshire & Calhoun, 1992). 4. Evaluative theories: Emotions are intentionally directed towards the objects. They are attitudes by which we evaluate the world (Brentano 1902, Scheler, 2005). 5. Cognitive Theories: Emotions are totally or partially considered as cognitions, or as something that depends logically or causally on cognitions, i.e., beliefs (i.e., Cheshire & Calhoun, 1992, Deigh, 1993, Lyons, 1993, Nussbaum, 2005, Oksenberg, 1997, Solomon, 2003). Cognitive Theories are the core of the paradox of fiction and in this work we will try analyze them through the eyes of Aesthetics as well I will try to prove that they do not provide a satisfactory account to explain how we engage emotionally to fictions. However, for the moment we will take them as a point of departure in order to understand basically what is the “Paradox of fiction” about. Hence the fact that we necessarily need to believe in the situation we are in front of in order to feel an emotion, there is a contradiction when we are in front of fictions because we know they are not real, so is it possible that we could believe in them? There is a large tradition in philosophy that maintains that we can only believe in something that it is real and in consequence the content of our beliefs must be true. The content of each belief corresponds to states of affairs that keep up a correspondence to reality and at the same time it could be translated into propositions, so it is capable of being judged according to criterions of truthfulness and falsehood. In consequence, having a belief is asserting that something is true and that it exists. Here will not be the place to discuss this notion of belief, because it is certain that when we believe in something we believe it is true. Its correspondence with reality is another matter; however it is true at least that if we believe in the truthfulness of our beliefs we believe in the existence of their contents. Now, what happens when we are emotionally engaged by fictions? The problem arises when we look carefully at the notion of belief. We neither believe that the characters of the fictions are real, nor the stages were they act on, nor the circumstances we watch depicted. We know they are unreal, and although this evidence they move us, sometimes softly and occasionally so strongly that they have such an impact in our lives. The “Paradox of fiction” lies upon these facts; the argumentation of this paradox centers around the contradiction between the unreality of the fictional situations and the reality of our beliefs within our emotional lives (according to cognitive approach to emotions). And in consequence contains four premises: 1. We believe in statements that are true and that support that something exists. 2. In order to have an emotion we do have to believe in certain state of affairs. 3. We do not believe in the existence of the content of fictions (that is, the states of affairs purported by fictions). 4. Fictions move us. 12 These premises show us that there is a paradox when we are engaged emotionally with fictional situations that means, on the emotions we feel in the aesthetics field. Many philosophers have tried to find out a solution in order to understand why and how this paradox happens. In this work I will explore many of the most important solutions offered to this paradox. However I will divide the paradox according to the central premises (the second and the third). According to the third premise we do not believe in the existence of the content of fictions, so in order to have an emotion we have to believe that something exists. I think one of the main problems regarding the “Paradox of fiction” is that there is not a clear definition on what is a fiction and how we get engaged with them. So it is necessary to find a satisfactory definition of fictions in order to know what kind of mental relation we have towards them. Another problem, and the most important one, is related to the notion of belief concerning the definition of emotions (the second premise) and the impossibility of conceiving getting emotionally engaged with fictional or imaginary entities we do not believe in. For that reason I will divide this work in two sections. In Section 1 I will try to define what is fiction. However I am more concerned with narrative fictional works than with a definition of fiction in general or what could be an “Ontology of Fiction”. The main reason for choosing this kind of works is that the paradox of fiction has been traditionally related to narrative works whether literary, theatrical or cinematographic, because their propositional content is conceivable either as a belief, as a thought or as an imaginary mental state. In this Section we shall analyze three of the most important approaches that try to give a definition of fiction: The “Eliminativist Approaches”, the “Speech Act Theories”, and “The Make-Believe Theories”. Chapter 2 is dedicated to “Eliminativist Approaches” to Fiction.
Recommended publications
  • Transportation and Homeric Epic
    Transportation and Homeric Epic Michael O’Neill Power A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The Australian National University May 2006 ii — — iii Statement of Originality Except where due acknowledgement is given, this thesis is the result of my own research carried out under the supervision of Dr Elizabeth Minchin of the Classics Program of the Australian National University with the advice of Dr Judith Slee of the Division of Psychology of the Australian National University. _________________________________ Michael O’Neill Power May 2006 iv — — v Acknowledgements I am very grateful to everyone who has made the completion of this thesis possible: to those with whom I have discussed my ideas (whether at conferences or in cafés); to Dr Alan Rumsey of the Research School of Pacific and Asian Studies for his advice; and to the staff of the Classics Program at The Australian National University. I must also voice my thanks to Mrs Mary Harber for her assistance in translating Wilhelm Grimm’s “Die Sage von Polyphem” and for correcting a final copy of the manuscript. Early versions of several chapters of this thesis were presented at a range of conferences and seminars and benefited greatly from the questions they evoked: a version of Chapter 2 was delivered at ASCS XXVI, at the University of Otago, Dunedin, New Zealand in 1995; versions of Chapter 4 were delivered at The Homer Seminar II, at The Australian National University, Canberra, in 2003, and at ASCS XXV, at La Trobe University, Bendigo, in 2004; and a version of Chapter 5 was presented at The Homer Seminar III, at The Australian National University, Canberra, in 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • I. Produits De La Recherche
    I. Produits de la recherche 1. Journaux / revues Articles scientifiques Aharon, I., Bourgeois-Gironde, S., and Levin, Y. (2015). Special issue on “Complexity modeling in social science and economics”. Mind & Society, 14(2), pp. 153-154. Alsmith, A. and Vignemont de, F. (2012). Embodying the mind & representing the body. In A. Alsmith, and de F. Vignemont de (Eds.), The body represented/Embodied representation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, Special issue, 3 (1). Arcangeli, M. (2012). Esperimenti mentali [Thought experiments]”. APhEx (Analytical and Philosophical Explanation), 6, pp. 33-72. Arcangeli, M. (2013). Immaginare è simulare: cosa e come? [Imagining is simulating: what and how?]. Rivista di Estetica, s.i. “Nuove teorie dell’immaginazione”, 53/2, pp. 135-154. Arcangeli, M. (2014). Against cognitivism about supposition. Philosophia, 42/3, pp. 607-624. Arcangeli, M. (2017). De l’autre côté du miroir de l’imagination. Imagination et imagerie mentale. Bulletin d’analyse phénoménologique, XIII/2, pp. 108-128 Arcangeli, M. (2017). Interacting with Emotions: Imagination and Supposition. Philosophical Quarterly. Arnold, G., and Auvray, M. (2014). Perceptual learning: Tactile letter recognition transfers across body surfaces. Multisensory Research, 27(1), pp. 71-90. Atran, S. (2012). Talking to the Enemy: An Alternative Approach to Ending Intractable Conflicts. Solutions 3: pp. 41-51. Atran, S. (2012). Parasite stress is not so critical to the history of religions or major group formations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35: pp. 79-80. Atran, S. (2013). From mutualism to moral transcendence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36: pp. 81-82. Atran, S. (2014). Martyrdom’s would-be myth buster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37: pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Distancing-Embracing Model of the Enjoyment of Negative Emotions in Art Reception
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2017), Page 1 of 63 doi:10.1017/S0140525X17000309, e347 The Distancing-Embracing model of the enjoyment of negative emotions in art reception Winfried Menninghaus1 Department of Language and Literature, Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, 60322 Frankfurt am Main, Germany [email protected] Valentin Wagner Department of Language and Literature, Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, 60322 Frankfurt am Main, Germany [email protected] Julian Hanich Department of Arts, Culture and Media, University of Groningen, 9700 AB Groningen, The Netherlands [email protected] Eugen Wassiliwizky Department of Language and Literature, Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, 60322 Frankfurt am Main, Germany [email protected] Thomas Jacobsen Experimental Psychology Unit, Helmut Schmidt University/University of the Federal Armed Forces Hamburg, 22043 Hamburg, Germany [email protected] Stefan Koelsch University of Bergen, 5020 Bergen, Norway [email protected] Abstract: Why are negative emotions so central in art reception far beyond tragedy? Revisiting classical aesthetics in the light of recent psychological research, we present a novel model to explain this much discussed (apparent) paradox. We argue that negative emotions are an important resource for the arts in general, rather than a special license for exceptional art forms only. The underlying rationale is that negative emotions have been shown to be particularly powerful in securing attention, intense emotional involvement, and high memorability, and hence is precisely what artworks strive for. Two groups of processing mechanisms are identified that conjointly adopt the particular powers of negative emotions for art’s purposes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transcendental Argument of the Novel
    The Transcendental Argument of the Novel Gilbert Plumer June 11, 2017 Journal of the American Philosophical Association accepted manuscript 1. Introduction Attending to a peculiar divergence, Warner (1979: 186) provides a striking description of the reception of Samuel Richardson’s groundbreaking novel Clarissa: When the completed novel is delivered to the public and readers still persist in asserting a misguided understanding of the novel, a new tone of irritation enters Richardson’s correspondence. At best, these readers are guilty of flagrant inattention to the novel’s design; at worst, an immoral admiration for Lovelace. Richardson meets this challenge to his art by carrying out significant changes in the body of Clarissa. These modifications come in two waves. In April 1749, six months after releasing the final installment of the first edition, Richardson publishes a second edition that includes footnotes and a long index summary of the novel, placed at the beginning of the text. Over the next two years, serious “errors” of reading continue, so in the Spring of 1751 Richardson publishes a third edition that weaves two hundred pages of additional material into the text. Similarly, Palmer (1973: 8) says that Clarissa is “a novel in which the central character [whom he regards as Lovelace] breaks the bonds of control of the author and reveals unconscious impulses which Richardson ‘did not understand himself’.” As we might say using commonplace categories, ‘the character took on a life of its own’ or even ‘the story wrote itself’. For this phenomenon of divergence to be possible, there have to be at least two levels of meaning or message of a work—that intended by the author and that conveyed or implicated by the text.
    [Show full text]
  • A Manifestation of All Life : Intersections of Virtue Ethics, Philosophy of Emotion, and Philosophy of Literature
    University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 12-2010 A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature. Derek Lee Penwell 1965- University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.library.louisville.edu/etd Recommended Citation Penwell, Derek Lee 1965-, "A manifestation of all life : intersections of virtue ethics, philosophy of emotion, and philosophy of literature." (2010). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1113. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/1113 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. This title appears here courtesy of the author, who has retained all other copyrights. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A MANIFESTATION OF ALL LIFE: INTERSECTIONS OF VIRTUE ETHICS, PHILOSOPHY OF EMOTION, AND PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE By Derek Lee Penwell B.R.E., Great Lakes Christian College, 1987 M.A.R., Emmanuel School of Religion, 1990 M.Div., Lexington Theological Seminary D.Min., Lexington Theological Seminary A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Louisville in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • The Matter of Beauty: Materialism and the Self in Victorian Aesthetic Theory
    The Matter of Beauty: Materialism and the Self in Victorian Aesthetic Theory by Benjamin Joseph Morgan A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Anthony J. Cascardi, Co-Chair Professor Barbara Spackman, Co-Chair Professor C. Daniel Blanton Professor Ramona Naddaff Spring 2010 The Matter of Beauty: Materialism and the Self in Victorian Aesthetic Theory © 2010 Benjamin Joseph Morgan 1 Abstract The Matter of Beauty: Materialism and the Self in Victorian Aesthetic Theory by Benjamin Joseph Morgan Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric University of California, Berkeley Professor Anthony J. Cascardi, Co-Chair Professor Barbara Spackman, Co-Chair The Matter of Beauty proposes that Victorian aesthetic theory is not a branch of philosophy focusing on art; rather, it is best understood as an interdisciplinary investigation of how humans relate affectively to physical things. The central claim of the dissertation is that aesthetic theory in the late-Victorian period enabled a significant reconsideration of what a “human” was, and of how distinctions could be drawn between self and other. I pursue this claim across four authors—Walter Pater, William Morris, Grant Allen, and Vernon Lee—who represent different modes in which a materialist strain of aesthetics led to a recognition that individuals constitutively lack autonomy from one another and from their surroundings. My analysis of a wide range of late-Victorian writing demonstrates that aesthetic theory responded to a question that was powerfully raised by nineteenth-century science, and that remains with us today: If our most elevated emotions can be localized as electrical activity in the brain, is there a “self” that transcends our material being? The intellectual tradition that I reconstruct reveals that considering aesthetic experience is a productive step toward answering this question.
    [Show full text]
  • A Paradox of American Tragedy : Long Day's Journey Into Night and the Problem of Negative Emotion in Theatrical Performance
    University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 8-2013 A paradox of American tragedy : Long day's journey into night and the problem of negative emotion in theatrical performance. Jeremy Killian University of Louisville Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.library.louisville.edu/etd Recommended Citation Killian, Jeremy, "A paradox of American tragedy : Long day's journey into night and the problem of negative emotion in theatrical performance." (2013). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 749. https://doi.org/10.18297/etd/749 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository. This title appears here courtesy of the author, who has retained all other copyrights. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A PARADOX OF AMERICAN TRAGEDY: LONG DAY’S JOURNEY INTO NIGHT AND THE PROBLEM OF NEGATIVE EMOTION IN THEATRICAL PERFORMANCE By Jeremy Killian B.A. Pensacola Christian College 2001 M.A. Pensacola Christian College 2003 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of the University of Louisville in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Humanities University of Louisville Louisville, Kentucky August 2013 A PARADOX OF AMERICAN TRAGEDY: LONG DAY’S JOURNEY INTO NIGHT AND THE PROBLEM OF NEGATIVE EMOTION IN THEATRICAL PERFORMANCE By Jeremy Killian B.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Salmose2012.Pdf
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Towards a Poetics of Nostalgia: The Nostalgic Experience in Modern Fiction Niklas Salmose PhD English The University of Edinburgh 2012 2 Declaration I hereby declare (a) that the thesis has been composed by me, and (b) that the work is my own, and (c) that the work has not been submitted for any other degree or professional qualification. 2012-01-01 _________________________________________________ Date Niklas Salmose, PhD Candidate 3 Abstract In recent years there has been a body of studies relating nostalgia and fiction in political, sociological, feminist, or historical ways. This thesis, instead, sets out to perform an unusual textual study of nostalgia in modern fiction in order to work towards a poetics of nostalgia. Although the experience of emotion is private, the object of analytical discourse must be to approach this experience with objective tools.
    [Show full text]
  • Levinas and Literature Perspectives on Jewish Texts and Contexts
    Levinas and Literature Perspectives on Jewish Texts and Contexts Edited by Vivian Liska Editorial Board Robert Alter, Steven E. Aschheim, Richard I. Cohen, Mark H. Gelber, Moshe Halbertal, Christine Hayes, Moshe Idel, Samuel Moyn, Ada Rapoport-Albert, Alvin Rosenfeld, David Ruderman, Bernd Witte Volume 15 Levinas and Literature New Directions Edited by Michael Fagenblat and Arthur Cools The free availability of the e-book edition of this publication was made possible by the Special Information Service (SIS) Jewish Studies at the University Library J. C. Senckenberg in Frankfurt/Main and 18 academic libraries that support the open access transformation in the Jewish Studies. ISBN 978-3-11-062966-8 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-066892-6 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-066899-5 ISSN 2199-6962 DOI https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110668926 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. For details go to: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Library of Congress Control Number: 2020943673 Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2021 Michael Fagenblat and Arthur Cools, published by Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston. The book is published open access at www.degruyter.com. Cover image: Excerpt from manuscript, used with kind permission of Michael Levinas. Typesetting: Integra Software Services Pvt. Ltd. Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck www.degruyter.com Open Access Transformation in Jewish Studies Open Access for excellent academic publications in the field of Jewish Studies: This is the ob- jective of the joint initiative of the Special Information Service Jewish Studies at the University Library J.
    [Show full text]
  • University of East Anglia Digital Repository
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of East Anglia digital repository University of East Anglia Philosophy Department Katherine Allen What Joy from Misery: the Pleasures of Horror Thesis submitted for the degree of PhD Thesis supervisors – Dr. Mark Rowe and Dr. Jerry Goodenough July 2012 © This copy of the thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with the author and that use of any information derived there from must be in accordance with current UK Copyright Law. In addition, any quotation or extract must include full attribution. Katherine Allen 2012 What Joy from Misery: the Pleasures of Horror Abstract: This thesis investigates the allure of narrative genres, such as horror, that have historically been viewed as philosophically (and often morally) problematic owing to their negative content and the painful emotional responses they elicit. It departs from the majority of classical and contemporary solutions to the alleged paradox posed by such genres, in that it does not attempt to render their pleasures explicable by appealing to their fictive status, thematic or ideological meanings or the more comprehensibly-pleasurable meta-responses they inspire. Rather, this account suggests that we choose to consume stories – fictional and factual – that depict violent or distressing situations and evoke discomforting emotions, for the same reason we choose to engage with less obviously conflict-filled narratives. Fictions compel our attention insofar as they resemble potentially salient information, appealing to a set of deeply ingrained and unconscious cognitive biases that prompt us to attend to certain kinds of stimuli.
    [Show full text]
  • Problems, Puzzles, and Paradoxes for a Moral Psychology of Fiction
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2015 Problems, Puzzles, and Paradoxes for a Moral Psychology of Fiction Katherine Tullmann Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1164 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] Problems, Puzzles, & Paradoxes for a Moral Psychology of Fiction by Katherine Tullmann A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York. 2015 i © 2015 KATHERINE TULLMANN All rights reserved. ii The dissertation has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy to satisfy the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Noël Carroll _________ ___________________________________ Date Chair of the Examining Committee John Greenwood _________ ___________________________________ Date Executive Officer Jesse Prinz (adviser) Noël Carroll David Rosenthal ______________________________ Supervisory committee THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Problems, Puzzles, and Paradoxes for a Moral Psychology of Fiction By Katherine Tullmann Adviser: Dr. Jesse Prinz The goal of my dissertation is to provide a comprehensive account of our psychological engagements with fiction. While many aestheticians have written on issues concerning art and ethics, only a few have addressed the ways in which works of fiction offer problems for general accounts of morality, let alone how we go about making moral judgments about fictions in the first place.
    [Show full text]
  • Honours Course Selection Philosophy Academic Year 2018-19
    Honours Course Selection Philosophy Academic Year 2018-19 Honours Philosophy: At the honours level, philosophy students take 120 credits each year. Philosophy courses are 20 credits each. Philosophy does not have any required courses in its degree plan so for the philosophy component of their degree, students have a wide range of choices. Compared to sub-honours, the courses will be smaller, will cover topics in greater depth, and will be more challenging. Philosophy uses a variety of assessment methods, including: essays, exams, projects, and short assignments. Single honours: In their third year, single honours philosophy students normally take six philosophy honours courses of 20 credits each. All third year students are automatically enrolled in the 0 credit philosophy dissertation preparation course. In their fourth year, single honours students take four philosophy courses of 20 credits each. Single honours philosophy students earn their remaining 40 credits in fourth year by writing an independent or coursework dissertation in philosophy. Joint honours: Individual degree programmes vary so check with your personal tutor about the details of your degree programme. All third year students are automatically enrolled in the 0 credit philosophy dissertation preparation course. With exceptions: in their third year joint honours students take around half their credits in philosophy. In their fourth year, joint honours philosophy students typically take 40 credits in philosophy and 40 credits in their other subject. They earn their remaining 40 credits in fourth year by writing an independent or coursework dissertation in philosophy or a dissertation in their other subject. This year, the honours courses are divided into those normally taken in year 3 and those normally taken in year 4.
    [Show full text]