Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(S): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(S): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(s): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 40, No. 3 (Spring, 1982), pp. 309- 314 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688 Accessed: 09-08-2017 22:42 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PEGGY ZEGLIN BRAND Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art IN "Convention and Dickie's Institutional lack of spontaneity in artworks, i.e., the Theory," Catherine Lord maintains loss the of flexibility espoused by Dickie's defi- following thesis: nition, is established by Lord via two routes: a) arguing that being a work of (L) If a work of art is defined as institutional and conventional, then the definition artpre- is incompatible with institutionality cludes the freedom and creativity associated (Incompatibility Argument), and b) argu- with art.' ing that the creation, presentation, and ap- Lord also maintains that the antecedent of preciation of a work of art is not governed this conditional is false. In this note, I will by conventions (Nonconventionality Argu- ment.) (In order to remain consistent with argue that (i) certain confusions and as- Lord's emphasis, analysis (a) will mainly sumptions prevent Lord from showing the discuss the freedom, originality and con- antecedent is false, and (ii) even if the ventions involved in the creation of a work antecedent is assumed to be true, there are of art; other conventions of presentation counterexamples to the entire conditional. and appreciation will play a more impor- With regard to (ii), I will suggest that con- tant role later in argument (b).) ventionality is necessary for creativity. The following reformulates Lord's In- I. compatibility Argument (a): (1) If a work of art is defined as institutional, Let us consider Lord's discussion of the then the practice of making works of art is antecedent in which the two concepts "in- essentially conservative. stitution" and "convention" are brought (2) If the institution is conservative, then the institutional definition precludes creativity. together to jointly justify the Institutional .'. (3) If a work of art is defined as institutional, definition's "loss of flexibility." 2 Lord para- then the institutional definition precludes phrases George Dickie's aims in Art and creativity. the Aesthetic as providing an institutional (4) The making of a work of art involves free- definition of "work of art" that allows for dom, creativity, originality and spontaneity. flexibility or creativity, and the specifica- .'. (5) A work of art is not to be defined as insti- tutional. tion of conventions governing the creation, presentation, and appreciation of the aes- Dickie defines "institution" as an estab- thetic features of art objects. With regard lished, continuing, traditional practice, per- to these aims, Lord adds, "Convention so haps complete with a unique history, e.g., crucial to the second aim may undermine the institution of theater.4 The particular the first, the attainment of flexibility which Dickie claims for his definition."3 This institution of art encompasses a bundle of systems, comprised of persons with learned PEGGY ZEGLIN BRAND is an artist and instructor in roles and patterns of behavior. Although the Humanities Department at the University the ofdefinition he proposes is comprised of Arizona. necessary and sufficient conditions, he holds This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 310 BRAND that his definition does not Let uspreclude now consider Lord'sthe discussion of actual creative activity of artists.the Nonconventionality Rather, it Argument (b) which allows for the constant expansion states that works of ofthe art are not governed boundaries of art by its very by conventions. looseness: In itskeeping with Lord's ac- informal character does notcount, Ipreclude will also make referenceex- to David perimentation in which subsystems Lewis's definition becomeof "convention," but will new art forms, and subsequently, cite a more recent,almost and perhaps, clearer anything is allowed to become version art. of the definition. Lord utilizes Lord's contention that an institution is Lewis's definition in order to contrast an essentially conservative, self-perpetuating, "independent" account of convention with and at times punitive, leads her to conclude that provided by Dickie. The definition of- that the practice of creating works of feredart, by Lewis is as follows: as an institution, is similarly constituted. (C) A regularity R, in action or in action and be- An objection must be made, however, to lief, is a convention in a population P if and the unsubstantiated assumptions underlying only if, within P, the following six conditions premises (1) and (2); Lord provides no evi- hold. (Or at least they almost hold. A few dence for an institution's essential conserv- exceptions to the 'everyone's' can be tol- erated.) atism, premise (1), nor an explanation of (i) Everyone conforms to R. such conservatism precluding creativity (ii) Everyone believes that the others con- within the institution of art-making, prem- form to R. ise (2). Weitz characterizes the Institutional (iii) This belief that the others conform to Theory as "establishmentarian," but Lord's R gives everyone a good and decisive mention of this fact does not constitute evi- reason to conform to R himself. dence for (2). (iv) There is a general preference for gen- Even granting, for a moment, that the eral conformity to R rather than slightly- less-than-general conformity-in particu- art-making institution runs the risk of be- lar, rather than conformity by all but coming "ultraconservative,"5 it does not any one. follow that normal artistic activity would (v) R is not the only possible regularity necessarily suffer any ill effects. For sup- meeting the last two conditions . There is at least one alternative R' . pose the established practice or continuing (that) could have perpetuated itself as tradition of creating artworks is novelty it- a convention instead of R. self: every work of art is enmeshed in an (vi) ... the various facts listed in conditions art historical context and builds upon the (i) to (v) are matters of common (or past, in a manner of speaking, but most mutual) knowledge.6 importantly, every work of art is also origi- Using (C), Lord's Nonconventionality Ar- nal in some way. (This might explain why gument (b) can be reformulated as: almost no one wants to accept fakes, for- (6) Let R* =the conventions governing the geries, and copies as works of art.) If so, creation, presentation and appreciation of then the charge of ultraconservatism would artworks and let P* = the members of the simply reflect an increase in the practice art institution or the artworld. Then conditions of (i) through (vi) of (C) of making and viewing works that flaunt hold. this novelty. Such a state of affairs would (7) But for R* and P*, (iv), (v), and (vi) of (C) certainly not yield a loss of creativity. Thus, do not hold. with the possibility that both (1) and (2) . (8) R* is not a convention, i.e., works of art of the Incompatibility Argument are false, are not conventional. i.e., Lord has not shown that the institu- tion of art-making is conservative nor that One initial problem with this argument the institution's conservatism precludes is cre- that Lord fails to be clear about conven- ativity, premise (3) is also suspect; tionsviz., R* in (6). It is not clear whether the Lord has not shown that Dickie's institu- argument depends upon R* as represent- tional definition of a work of art does in ing Dickie's notion of the one primary con- fact preclude creativity. Thus the Incom- vention in art, or secondary conventions, patibility Argument (a) fails. or both. My assumption is that R* repre- This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms Institutional Theory of Art 311 sents any and all conventions in the art- world. Lord's criticism of Dickie's notion world, since (8) is intended to show that of a primary convention would merit con- works of art are not conventional at all. siderable consideration if indeed her main But in order to show (8), Lord must showcontention in (8) of the Nonconventional- that neither the primary convention itynor Argument was that this so-called con- any secondary conventions are really ventioncon- is simply a regularity, due to (7). ventions. Premise (7) states that conditions (iv) Despite Dickie's use of several descrip- through (vi) of Lewis' (C) are violated, i.e., tions, the primary conventions in art the can conditions stipulating general prefer- best be characterized as the essential under- ence for conformity (iv), an alternative R' standing (or knowledge) between artist(s) (v), and mutual knowledge (vi).
Recommended publications
  • From Point to Pixel: a Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy
    From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric and the Designated Emphasis in Film Studies in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Whitney Davis, co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, co-chair Professor Warren Sack Professor Abigail DeKosnik Professor Kristen Whissel Spring 2010 Copyright 2010 by Hoy, Meredith All rights reserved. Abstract From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric University of California, Berkeley Professor Whitney Davis, Co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, Co-chair When we say, in response to a still or moving picture, that it has a digital “look” about it, what exactly do we mean? How can the slick, color-saturated photographs of Jeff Wall and Andreas Gursky signal digitality, while the flattened, pixelated landscapes of video games such as Super Mario Brothers convey ostensibly the same characteristic of “being digital,” but in a completely different manner? In my dissertation, From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics, I argue for a definition of a "digital method" that can be articulated without reference to the technicalities of contemporary hardware and software. I allow, however, the possibility that this digital method can acquire new characteristics when it is performed by computational technology. I therefore treat the artworks covered in my dissertation as sensuous artifacts that are subject to change based on the constraints and affordances of the tools used in their making.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Attempting Art: an Essay on Intention-Dependence
    Attempting Art: an essay on intention-dependence Michel-Antoine Xhignesse Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montréal December 2016 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Michel-Antoine Xhignesse 2016 Table of Contents Dissertation abstract ................................................................................................................ iii Résumé de thèse ....................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................... v Chapter 1 – Introductory Remarks............................................................................................. 1 Chapter 2 – Art, Intention, and Intention-Dependence ............................................................ 9 2.1 – Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 9 2.2 – Intentional action ................................................................................................................. 11 2.3 – Intention-dependence vs. concept-dependence .................................................................... 18 2.4 – Accidents and Incidents ....................................................................................................... 22 2.5 – Separating Concept- and Intention-Dependence
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore?
    KENDALL WALTON Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore? It is a very great honor to address my friends and philosophy of quantum physics are younger. But colleagues as president of the American Society these are clearly subcategories of traditional, well- for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique established areas of philosophy—ethics and phi- role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional losophy of science—and they inherit much of their branch of philosophy and also central to disci- identity and sense of purpose from their parents. plines often regarded as remote from philosophy, Aesthetics is not so fortunate. It is related in vari- as well as depending crucially on their contribu- ous important ways to epistemology, metaphysics, tions. philosophy of mind, philosophy of language— I will follow the lead of one of my distinguished indeed it overlaps all of them—but these older predecessors in this office, Peter Kivy, who used relatives are at best aunts and uncles to aesthetics, the occasion of his own presidential address twelve not parents. Aesthetics must figure out for itself years ago to step back and reflect on the state of what exactly it is. the discipline and the nature of aesthetics.1 Two kinds of issues about the field need to be addressed: What is distinctive about this branch i. what is aesthetics? of philosophy, in contrast to others? And what is philosophy? Under the first heading, we will ask Aesthetics is a strange field, in some ways a con- what aesthetics is the philosophy of , what domain fused one.
    [Show full text]
  • Broken Technologies
    Broken Technologies 2 The Angel of Machines: from Buch der Erfindungen Gewerbe und Industrien,or Book of Inven- tions,Vol.6,1887, F.Reuleaux, Editor. From Moon, Francis C. The Machines of Leonardo da Vinci and Franz Reuleaux. Kinematics of Machines from the Renaissance to the 20th Century. Springer, 2007. FrontPage: © Maria Flores Crossa 3 Broken Technologies The Humanist as Engineer Fernando Flores Morador Lund University 2011- revised 2015 4 Department of History of Ideas and Science University of Lund Broken Technologies. The Humanist as Engineer. Ver 3.0 Biskopsgatan 7, 223 62 Lund © Fernando Flores Morador, 2009, Third Edition Cover: Maria Flores Crossa Tryck: Media – Tryck, Lunds Universitet, 2011-revised 2015 ISBN: 978-91-633-9692-2 5 Contents Contents ....................................................................................................................................... 5 List of figures .................................................................................................................................. 7 List of Tables.................................................................................................................................. 9 Foreword .................................................................................................................................. 11 First Edition (Ver. 1.0) ................................................................................................................ 11 Second edition (Ver. 1.1) ...........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Hans Urs Von Balthasar, the Glory of the Lord: a Theological Aesthetics, 7 Vols, Various Translators; Vol
    Notes PREFACE 1. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, 7 vols, various translators; vol. 1 (San Francisco: Ignatius; and New York: Crossroad, 1982); vols 2-3 (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1984-86); vols 4-7, trans. in progress. The range and depth of von Balthasar's treatment of various theological issues and figures relevant to matters of theological aesthetics makes his work a major resource for study in the field, and especially for historical understanding of a kind impossible to pursue here. His treatment of issues normally dealt with in aesthetics is nonetheless spotty and erratic; many of the theological and philosophical topics central to the present study are ones on which he barely touches. That is to say, von Balthasar's work is sui generis, standing outside the main arenas of both contemporary aesthetics and modem theology. For the most part I have had to be content to let him speak for himself. 2. Nicholas Wolterstorff, Art in Action: Toward a Christian Aesthetic (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1980). 3. Gerardus van der Leeuw, Sacred and Profane Beauty: The Holy in Art, trans. David E. Green (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963). 4. John Dillenberger, A Theology of Artistic Sensibilities: The Visual Arts and the Church (New York: Crossroad, 1986). 5. Thomas R. Martland, Religion as Art (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1981). 6. F. David Martin, Art and the Religious Experience: The 'Language' of the Sacred (Lewisburg, Penn.: Bucknell University Press, 1972). 7. Frank Burch Brown, Transfiguration: Poetic Metaphor and the Languages of Religious Belief (Chapel Hill and London: University of North Carolina Press, 1983).
    [Show full text]
  • Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space
    theoretical perspective From Imaginal to Digital: Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space Nick Lambert a b s t r a c t The author suggests that the intangible characteristics of computer graphics bear some resemblance to the brain’s ability to construct mental images, as outlined by veteran s a historian of computer art, I am fascinated Kosslyn and his team at Harvard researcher Stephen M. Kosslyn. A An analogy might also be drawn by the nature of digital images and the way in which people have been looking at the visual with the “Imaginal World” of the apprehend them. Images that are rendered on a screen ap- psychology and neurophysiology Sufis, as described by Henri parently exist in a plane separate to the rest of our world, of mental imagery for several de- Corbin, which exists in a space analogous to the pictorial space developed by artists but with cades. Using PET and fMRI scan- of its own. As computer graph- an animate and interactive aspect wholly its own. Their basis is ners, Kosslyn and his collaborators ics have emerged as an artistic not visual but mathematical and process-driven, although the have discovered that particular medium, one may consider how this internalized ability influences computer has evolved into a device for generating imagery. As brain areas related to color and the artist’s response to the com- we become ever more adept at creating and navigating a range shape perception activate during puter, especially as new display of virtual worlds (whether the mundane desktop or the exotic the imaginary phase.
    [Show full text]
  • Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting
    Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting A dissertation presented to the faculty of The Patton College of Education of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Cynthia A. Agyeman December 2015 © 2015 Cynthia A. Agyeman. All Rights Reserved. 2 This dissertation titled Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting by CYNTHIA A. AGYEMAN has been approved for the Department of Educational Studies and The Patton College of Education by Teresa Franklin Professor of Educational Studies Renée A. Middleton Dean, The Patton College of Education 3 Abstract AGYEMAN, CYNTHIA A., Ph.D., December 2015, Curriculum and Instruction, Instructional Technology Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting (pp. 310) Director of Dissertation: Teresa Franklin Painting is believed to predate recorded history and has been in existence for over 35,000 (Ayres, 1985; Bolton, 2013) years. Over the years, painting has evolved; new styles have been developed and digital media have been explored. Each period of change goes through a period of rejection before it is accepted. In the 1960s, digital media was introduced to the art form. Like all the painting mediums, it was rejected. It has been over 50 years since it was introduced and yet, it has not been fully accepted as an art form (King, 2002; Miller, 2007; Noll, 1994). This exploratory study seeks to understand the artist’s perception on the use of digital media as an art tool and its benefit to the artists and art education. Grounded theory was used as a methodological guide for the study.
    [Show full text]
  • Cahiers Des Théories De L'art 1
    Revue Proteus – Cahiers des théories de l’art 1 Revue Proteus n° 4, la place de l'esthétique en philosophie de l'art Édito On le sait, les écrits de Platon abordaient séparément les questions relatives au beau et à l'art, séparément aussi celles relatives à l'art et aux sensations. e Mis à part quelques textes précurseurs, il a fallu attendre le XVII siècle pour que se théorisent plus précisément les liens unissant l'art aux sensations et que le goût intéresse les philosophes de l'art. Les règles de la bonne œuvre se voient évacuées au profit d'une appréciation subjective du spectateur. L'art est dès lors affaire d'esthétique. Quelque trois siècles ont suffi pour que se multiplient les opposants aux approches esthétiques de l'art ; ce présent numéro de la revue Proteus peut à ce sujet être lu comme un commentaire du texte de Timothy Binkley inti- tulé « “Pièces” contre l'esthétique ». Ce texte défend l'idée que l'apparence sensible de certaines pièces d'art n'est clairement plus gage de leurs appré- ciations et que l'esthétique n'a donc plus de pertinence pour penser l'art. Cette hypothèse, pour être consolidée, doit encore considérer le sujet perce- vant en plus du monde sensible lui-même : ce n'est en effet pas le monde sensible qui sent, et l'esthétique est affaire du sujet sentant. Ce sujet sentant est toutefois le même qui trouve souvent qu'il faille connaître un artiste pour aimer ses œuvres, le même qui dit parfois ne rien « comprendre » à l'art contemporain.
    [Show full text]
  • ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016 Dissertation directed by: Professor Jerrold Levinson Department of Philosophy This dissertation defends a positive answer to the question: \Can a videogame be a work of art?" To achieve this goal I develop definitions of several concepts, primarily `art', `games', and `videogames', and analyze arguments about the com- patibility between these notions. In Part One, I defend a definition of art from amongst several contemporary and historical accounts. This definition, the Intentional-Historical account, requires, among other things, that an artwork have the right kind of creative intentions behind it, in short that the work be intended to be regarded in a particular manner. This is a leading account that has faced several recent objections that I address while arguing that it is superior to other theories in its ability to answer the question of videogames' art status. Part Two examines whether games can exhibit that kind of creative intention. Recent literature has suggested that they can. I propose and defend an account of games according to which games cannot be intended to be works of art because games are goal-directed activities that require a voluntary selection of inefficient means that is incompatible with the proper manner of regarding that is necessary for artworks. While the conclusions of Part One and Part Two appear to suggest that videogames cannot be works of art, Part Three proposes and defends a new account of videogames that, contrary to first appearances, implies that not all videogames are games. This Intentional-Historical Formalist account allows for non-game videogames to be created with an art-making intention, though not every non-game videogame will have an art-making intention behind it.
    [Show full text]
  • PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014
    1 PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014 Unique # 43270, 43275, 43280 TIME: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 2:00-2:50 p.m. and a third hour LOCATION: WAG 302 (TTH 2:00 – 2:50 p.m.) (Check your schedule for third hour location) INSTRUCTOR: Prof. Kathleen Higgins OFFICE: WAG 203 (512) 471-5564 OFFICE HOURS: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:45-11:45 a.m. E-MAIL: <[email protected]> COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course will consider some of the answers given in the Western philosophical tradition to questions about the nature of art and beauty, as well as offering a brief overview of some perspectives from Japan. Particular attention will be given to the distinction between art and reality, and to the nature of the aesthetic experience from the standpoint of both the artist and the observer. TEACHING ASSISTANT: TBA TEXTBOOK: Kathleen Marie Higgins, ed., Aesthetics in Perspective POLICIES: Late assignments will automatically receive ten fewer percentage points than they would otherwise have received. Late assignments will not be accepted more than one week after the date due. Late assignments will not be accepted after the last day of class. Makeup exams or extensions will be arranged only in situations of an emergency or serious illness. The instructor may ask for evidence. Students with disabilities may request appropriate academic accommodations from the Division of Diversity and Community Engagement, Services for Students with Disabilities, 471-6259 2 GRADING AND IMPORTANT DATES: January 23 Short paper due 5% February 13 Exam I 15% March 6 Journal entries 1-6 due 10% March 20 Exam II 15% April 17 Exam III 15% April 29 Journal entries 7-12 due 10% May 1 Final written project due 20% Participation (includes attendance, in-class writing, in-class quizzes, etc.) 10% GRADING: Grades will be computed using the plus-minus system.
    [Show full text]