Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space theoretical perspective From Imaginal to Digital: Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space Nick Lambert a b s t r a c t The author suggests that the intangible characteristics of computer graphics bear some resemblance to the brain’s ability to construct mental images, as outlined by veteran s a historian of computer art, I am fascinated Kosslyn and his team at Harvard researcher Stephen M. Kosslyn. A An analogy might also be drawn by the nature of digital images and the way in which people have been looking at the visual with the “Imaginal World” of the apprehend them. Images that are rendered on a screen ap- psychology and neurophysiology Sufis, as described by Henri parently exist in a plane separate to the rest of our world, of mental imagery for several de- Corbin, which exists in a space analogous to the pictorial space developed by artists but with cades. Using PET and fMRI scan- of its own. As computer graph- an animate and interactive aspect wholly its own. Their basis is ners, Kosslyn and his collaborators ics have emerged as an artistic not visual but mathematical and process-driven, although the have discovered that particular medium, one may consider how this internalized ability influences computer has evolved into a device for generating imagery. As brain areas related to color and the artist’s response to the com- we become ever more adept at creating and navigating a range shape perception activate during puter, especially as new display of virtual worlds (whether the mundane desktop or the exotic the imaginary phase. Nor is this technologies emerge. unreality of Second Life), the computer facilitates the exten- solely for imagery; imagined audi- sion of our visual imagination in the apparently unbounded tory experiences seem to activate virtual space created by mathematics. areas associated with hearing, and motor activities (e.g. imagined walking) bring responses from the corresponding areas for movement. Says Kosslyn: Mental IMagery With this in mind, it is worth considering the inherent hu- Many neuroimaging studies of “mental rotation” have been re- ported, all of which have shown that multiple brain areas are man faculty for generating wholly imaginary images, or “men- activated during mental rotation. For example, Richter et al. mea- tal imagery.” Mental imagery is succinctly defined by one of sured brain activation with fMRI while subjects mentally rotated its major exponents and researchers, Stephen M. Kosslyn of the three-dimensional multi-armed angular stimuli invented by Harvard’s Department of Psychology, quoted here by Samuel Shepard and Metzler [4]. Moulton: If this is indeed the case, then mental images are a crucial Mental imagery occurs “when a representation of the type cre- component of our cognition. They enable us to conceive of ated during the initial phases of perception is present but the objects and situations in our minds and to maneuver them. stimulus is not actually being perceived; such representations Similarly, computer graphics has given us a platform for creat- preserve the perceptible properties of the stimulus and ulti- ing controllable animate forms in a non-physical space that we mately give rise to the subjective experience of perception” [1]. have developed over the past 50 years. The basic contention is that when an imaginary scene is After numerous tests involving people imagining visual ob- called forth, for instance if one is asked to think of the shape jects, and comparing the brain activity and descriptions of this of an Alsatian dog’s ears (a typical Kosslyn example), then process to actual vision, Kosslyn has proposed the following: one visualizes the scene in the mind’s eye. The question is Because imagery relies on perceptual representations, it makes whether the brain actually forms an image or simply processes explicit and accessible the same types of information that are non-visual data. The veracity of mental imagery has been hotly registered by the senses during perception (including proprio- debated throughout the 20th century; Michael Tye’s seminal ception and kinaesthetic information). Mental imagery may book The Imagery Debate [2] outlines the basic argument be- best be understood in the context of mental simulation, specifi- cally as a kind of mental emulation [5]. tween imagery’s supporters and detractors. Zenon Pylshyn is one of the most prominent opponents of the idea that the Kosslyn goes on to use a computational analogy here: When brain forms actual images: his position is that “[internal rep- we see an object in our mind’s eye we can simulate how it resentations] are essentially conceptual and propositional, rather might appear under different conditions, translate it into vari- than sensory or pictorial, in nature” [3]. ous contexts or investigate it more closely. In a sense, we are calling an immaterial object to mind in order to study it. Obvi- ously there are elements of memory and recall in this process, and since Classical times this ability to compose active mental Nick Lambert (lecturer), Department of History of Art and Screen Media, Birkbeck, images has been deployed as a memory tool. The historian University of London, 43 Gordon Square, London WC1H 0PD, U.K. E-mail: <n.lambert @bbk.ac.uk>. of visual culture Frances Yates, in her magnum opus The Art See <www.mitpressjournals.org/toc/leon/44/5> for supplemental files associated with of Memory, famously described how this and the technique of this issue. creating “loci,” or imaginative sites, to serve as the locations for ©2011 ISAST LEONARDO, Vol. 44, No. 5, pp. 439–443, 2011 439 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/LEON_a_00245 by guest on 29 September 2021 specific stored memories developed into BrIdgIng the aBstract and means of realizing the images. The Byz- an important, though obscure, area of the MaterIal antine distinction between noetos and Western thought during the Renaissance aisthetos seemingly remains current. The There is a degree of resemblance be- [6]. Kosslyn, too, refers to it obliquely: question is to what degree the computer tween the imaginative simulation of the enables an interchange between both ar- mundus imaginalis and the digital simu- Memorial processes must retrieve and eas via mathematical processes rendered lation of a three-dimensional reality. later encode episodic information. in visual form. Much evidence supports this interplay I believe that one can extend the idea between memory and imagery. One uses of the “imaginal world” to the wholly imagery to simulate what one would per- ceive if one were in a specific situation; externalized digital worlds that subsist the coMputer as a this is as true of imagery used to retrieve inside a space of their own, one that is VIsual MedIuM memories as it is of imagery used to pre- seen through the computer screen. My Although computer images can be de- dict the future. As such, imagery and contention is that computer users appre- scribed as grids of pixels, they really simulation are joined at the hip, and hend the intangible visual space of the should be studied together [7]. consist of instructions: In other words, screen with similar processes to those their constituents are not visual (or physi- used for internalized mental imagery. cal). The artist can entirely redefine the This was underscored for me when I read the IMagInal realM structure of the program that gives rise to the following in Foley and Van Dam’s The word “imaginal” may be unfamiliar these images and sits outside this tightly primer on computer graphics: but it is appropriate in this context. The defined reality formed of instructions. French philosopher and researcher of [Computer graphics involves] the picto- In the earliest days of computer image- Sufism Henri Corbin identified a facet rial synthesis of real or imaginary objects making, there was a conscious decision of Sufi practice that involved the con- from their computer-based models . we to adopt some of the conventions of per- can make pictures not only of concrete templation of the alam al-mithal, a world “real-world” objects but also of abstract, spectival geometry to make computer created by the visual imagination that was synthetic objects [and] of data that have graphics represent 3D space properly not “imaginary” in a pejorative sense but no inherent geometry [10]. on a flat screen. While Ivan Sutherland’s rather had an independent existence be- Sketchpad of 1961 had introduced interac- tween the physical and spiritual planes. This informed my concept that com- tive vector graphics, it was still 2D only. Also called the “Eighth Climate” or Na- puter art differs from all traditional visual Timothy Johnson, working on MIT’s kojd-Abad, the “land of No-where,” this art in two important respects. Firstly, the Lincoln TX-2 computer, which was one zone was described as a realm with iden- artist manipulates information directly, of the few powerful enough to support tifiable cities and geography. These were without the limitations that are intrin- graphics applications, created Sketchpad imbued with symbolic meaning, where sic to a physical medium; and secondly III as a 3D version of the original. Around specific architectural features evoked the computer can respond to the artist 1963, Lawrence G. Roberts (more famous certain doctrinal and philosophical during production and to the viewer af- as a pioneer of the ARPANET, precursor points. For this reason, Corbin invented ter production, or even act as a creative to the Internet) wrote his Ph.D. thesis the term mundus imaginalis to describe agent in its own right if programmed to on 3D models created by processing 3D this place: do so. This is possible because the digi- information contained in scanned pho- tal image is intangible, like the mental tographs.
Recommended publications
  • From Point to Pixel: a Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy
    From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric and the Designated Emphasis in Film Studies in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Whitney Davis, co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, co-chair Professor Warren Sack Professor Abigail DeKosnik Professor Kristen Whissel Spring 2010 Copyright 2010 by Hoy, Meredith All rights reserved. Abstract From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric University of California, Berkeley Professor Whitney Davis, Co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, Co-chair When we say, in response to a still or moving picture, that it has a digital “look” about it, what exactly do we mean? How can the slick, color-saturated photographs of Jeff Wall and Andreas Gursky signal digitality, while the flattened, pixelated landscapes of video games such as Super Mario Brothers convey ostensibly the same characteristic of “being digital,” but in a completely different manner? In my dissertation, From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics, I argue for a definition of a "digital method" that can be articulated without reference to the technicalities of contemporary hardware and software. I allow, however, the possibility that this digital method can acquire new characteristics when it is performed by computational technology. I therefore treat the artworks covered in my dissertation as sensuous artifacts that are subject to change based on the constraints and affordances of the tools used in their making.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Attempting Art: an Essay on Intention-Dependence
    Attempting Art: an essay on intention-dependence Michel-Antoine Xhignesse Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montréal December 2016 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Michel-Antoine Xhignesse 2016 Table of Contents Dissertation abstract ................................................................................................................ iii Résumé de thèse ....................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................... v Chapter 1 – Introductory Remarks............................................................................................. 1 Chapter 2 – Art, Intention, and Intention-Dependence ............................................................ 9 2.1 – Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 9 2.2 – Intentional action ................................................................................................................. 11 2.3 – Intention-dependence vs. concept-dependence .................................................................... 18 2.4 – Accidents and Incidents ....................................................................................................... 22 2.5 – Separating Concept- and Intention-Dependence
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore?
    KENDALL WALTON Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore? It is a very great honor to address my friends and philosophy of quantum physics are younger. But colleagues as president of the American Society these are clearly subcategories of traditional, well- for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique established areas of philosophy—ethics and phi- role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional losophy of science—and they inherit much of their branch of philosophy and also central to disci- identity and sense of purpose from their parents. plines often regarded as remote from philosophy, Aesthetics is not so fortunate. It is related in vari- as well as depending crucially on their contribu- ous important ways to epistemology, metaphysics, tions. philosophy of mind, philosophy of language— I will follow the lead of one of my distinguished indeed it overlaps all of them—but these older predecessors in this office, Peter Kivy, who used relatives are at best aunts and uncles to aesthetics, the occasion of his own presidential address twelve not parents. Aesthetics must figure out for itself years ago to step back and reflect on the state of what exactly it is. the discipline and the nature of aesthetics.1 Two kinds of issues about the field need to be addressed: What is distinctive about this branch i. what is aesthetics? of philosophy, in contrast to others? And what is philosophy? Under the first heading, we will ask Aesthetics is a strange field, in some ways a con- what aesthetics is the philosophy of , what domain fused one.
    [Show full text]
  • Broken Technologies
    Broken Technologies 2 The Angel of Machines: from Buch der Erfindungen Gewerbe und Industrien,or Book of Inven- tions,Vol.6,1887, F.Reuleaux, Editor. From Moon, Francis C. The Machines of Leonardo da Vinci and Franz Reuleaux. Kinematics of Machines from the Renaissance to the 20th Century. Springer, 2007. FrontPage: © Maria Flores Crossa 3 Broken Technologies The Humanist as Engineer Fernando Flores Morador Lund University 2011- revised 2015 4 Department of History of Ideas and Science University of Lund Broken Technologies. The Humanist as Engineer. Ver 3.0 Biskopsgatan 7, 223 62 Lund © Fernando Flores Morador, 2009, Third Edition Cover: Maria Flores Crossa Tryck: Media – Tryck, Lunds Universitet, 2011-revised 2015 ISBN: 978-91-633-9692-2 5 Contents Contents ....................................................................................................................................... 5 List of figures .................................................................................................................................. 7 List of Tables.................................................................................................................................. 9 Foreword .................................................................................................................................. 11 First Edition (Ver. 1.0) ................................................................................................................ 11 Second edition (Ver. 1.1) ...........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Hans Urs Von Balthasar, the Glory of the Lord: a Theological Aesthetics, 7 Vols, Various Translators; Vol
    Notes PREFACE 1. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, 7 vols, various translators; vol. 1 (San Francisco: Ignatius; and New York: Crossroad, 1982); vols 2-3 (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1984-86); vols 4-7, trans. in progress. The range and depth of von Balthasar's treatment of various theological issues and figures relevant to matters of theological aesthetics makes his work a major resource for study in the field, and especially for historical understanding of a kind impossible to pursue here. His treatment of issues normally dealt with in aesthetics is nonetheless spotty and erratic; many of the theological and philosophical topics central to the present study are ones on which he barely touches. That is to say, von Balthasar's work is sui generis, standing outside the main arenas of both contemporary aesthetics and modem theology. For the most part I have had to be content to let him speak for himself. 2. Nicholas Wolterstorff, Art in Action: Toward a Christian Aesthetic (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1980). 3. Gerardus van der Leeuw, Sacred and Profane Beauty: The Holy in Art, trans. David E. Green (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963). 4. John Dillenberger, A Theology of Artistic Sensibilities: The Visual Arts and the Church (New York: Crossroad, 1986). 5. Thomas R. Martland, Religion as Art (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1981). 6. F. David Martin, Art and the Religious Experience: The 'Language' of the Sacred (Lewisburg, Penn.: Bucknell University Press, 1972). 7. Frank Burch Brown, Transfiguration: Poetic Metaphor and the Languages of Religious Belief (Chapel Hill and London: University of North Carolina Press, 1983).
    [Show full text]
  • Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting
    Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting A dissertation presented to the faculty of The Patton College of Education of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Cynthia A. Agyeman December 2015 © 2015 Cynthia A. Agyeman. All Rights Reserved. 2 This dissertation titled Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting by CYNTHIA A. AGYEMAN has been approved for the Department of Educational Studies and The Patton College of Education by Teresa Franklin Professor of Educational Studies Renée A. Middleton Dean, The Patton College of Education 3 Abstract AGYEMAN, CYNTHIA A., Ph.D., December 2015, Curriculum and Instruction, Instructional Technology Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting (pp. 310) Director of Dissertation: Teresa Franklin Painting is believed to predate recorded history and has been in existence for over 35,000 (Ayres, 1985; Bolton, 2013) years. Over the years, painting has evolved; new styles have been developed and digital media have been explored. Each period of change goes through a period of rejection before it is accepted. In the 1960s, digital media was introduced to the art form. Like all the painting mediums, it was rejected. It has been over 50 years since it was introduced and yet, it has not been fully accepted as an art form (King, 2002; Miller, 2007; Noll, 1994). This exploratory study seeks to understand the artist’s perception on the use of digital media as an art tool and its benefit to the artists and art education. Grounded theory was used as a methodological guide for the study.
    [Show full text]
  • Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(S): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol
    Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(s): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 40, No. 3 (Spring, 1982), pp. 309- 314 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688 Accessed: 09-08-2017 22:42 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PEGGY ZEGLIN BRAND Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art IN "Convention and Dickie's Institutional lack of spontaneity in artworks, i.e., the Theory," Catherine Lord maintains loss the of flexibility espoused by Dickie's defi- following thesis: nition, is established by Lord via two routes: a) arguing that being a work of (L) If a work of art is defined as institutional and conventional, then the definition artpre- is incompatible with institutionality cludes the freedom and creativity associated (Incompatibility Argument), and b) argu- with art.' ing that the creation, presentation, and ap- Lord also maintains that the antecedent of preciation of a work of art is not governed this conditional is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Cahiers Des Théories De L'art 1
    Revue Proteus – Cahiers des théories de l’art 1 Revue Proteus n° 4, la place de l'esthétique en philosophie de l'art Édito On le sait, les écrits de Platon abordaient séparément les questions relatives au beau et à l'art, séparément aussi celles relatives à l'art et aux sensations. e Mis à part quelques textes précurseurs, il a fallu attendre le XVII siècle pour que se théorisent plus précisément les liens unissant l'art aux sensations et que le goût intéresse les philosophes de l'art. Les règles de la bonne œuvre se voient évacuées au profit d'une appréciation subjective du spectateur. L'art est dès lors affaire d'esthétique. Quelque trois siècles ont suffi pour que se multiplient les opposants aux approches esthétiques de l'art ; ce présent numéro de la revue Proteus peut à ce sujet être lu comme un commentaire du texte de Timothy Binkley inti- tulé « “Pièces” contre l'esthétique ». Ce texte défend l'idée que l'apparence sensible de certaines pièces d'art n'est clairement plus gage de leurs appré- ciations et que l'esthétique n'a donc plus de pertinence pour penser l'art. Cette hypothèse, pour être consolidée, doit encore considérer le sujet perce- vant en plus du monde sensible lui-même : ce n'est en effet pas le monde sensible qui sent, et l'esthétique est affaire du sujet sentant. Ce sujet sentant est toutefois le même qui trouve souvent qu'il faille connaître un artiste pour aimer ses œuvres, le même qui dit parfois ne rien « comprendre » à l'art contemporain.
    [Show full text]
  • ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016 Dissertation directed by: Professor Jerrold Levinson Department of Philosophy This dissertation defends a positive answer to the question: \Can a videogame be a work of art?" To achieve this goal I develop definitions of several concepts, primarily `art', `games', and `videogames', and analyze arguments about the com- patibility between these notions. In Part One, I defend a definition of art from amongst several contemporary and historical accounts. This definition, the Intentional-Historical account, requires, among other things, that an artwork have the right kind of creative intentions behind it, in short that the work be intended to be regarded in a particular manner. This is a leading account that has faced several recent objections that I address while arguing that it is superior to other theories in its ability to answer the question of videogames' art status. Part Two examines whether games can exhibit that kind of creative intention. Recent literature has suggested that they can. I propose and defend an account of games according to which games cannot be intended to be works of art because games are goal-directed activities that require a voluntary selection of inefficient means that is incompatible with the proper manner of regarding that is necessary for artworks. While the conclusions of Part One and Part Two appear to suggest that videogames cannot be works of art, Part Three proposes and defends a new account of videogames that, contrary to first appearances, implies that not all videogames are games. This Intentional-Historical Formalist account allows for non-game videogames to be created with an art-making intention, though not every non-game videogame will have an art-making intention behind it.
    [Show full text]
  • PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014
    1 PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014 Unique # 43270, 43275, 43280 TIME: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 2:00-2:50 p.m. and a third hour LOCATION: WAG 302 (TTH 2:00 – 2:50 p.m.) (Check your schedule for third hour location) INSTRUCTOR: Prof. Kathleen Higgins OFFICE: WAG 203 (512) 471-5564 OFFICE HOURS: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:45-11:45 a.m. E-MAIL: <[email protected]> COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course will consider some of the answers given in the Western philosophical tradition to questions about the nature of art and beauty, as well as offering a brief overview of some perspectives from Japan. Particular attention will be given to the distinction between art and reality, and to the nature of the aesthetic experience from the standpoint of both the artist and the observer. TEACHING ASSISTANT: TBA TEXTBOOK: Kathleen Marie Higgins, ed., Aesthetics in Perspective POLICIES: Late assignments will automatically receive ten fewer percentage points than they would otherwise have received. Late assignments will not be accepted more than one week after the date due. Late assignments will not be accepted after the last day of class. Makeup exams or extensions will be arranged only in situations of an emergency or serious illness. The instructor may ask for evidence. Students with disabilities may request appropriate academic accommodations from the Division of Diversity and Community Engagement, Services for Students with Disabilities, 471-6259 2 GRADING AND IMPORTANT DATES: January 23 Short paper due 5% February 13 Exam I 15% March 6 Journal entries 1-6 due 10% March 20 Exam II 15% April 17 Exam III 15% April 29 Journal entries 7-12 due 10% May 1 Final written project due 20% Participation (includes attendance, in-class writing, in-class quizzes, etc.) 10% GRADING: Grades will be computed using the plus-minus system.
    [Show full text]