The Wizard of Ethereal Pictures and Virtual Places

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Wizard of Ethereal Pictures and Virtual Places The Wizard of Ethereal Pictures and Virtual Places Timothy Binkley ABSTRACT .. the computeris a 'metaphysical machine' [ 1 J. puter art in addition to being baffled by it. What is the com­ Renaissance artists con­ -Sherry Turkle puter's role in art? Does it have structed pictorial space using algorithms based on Euclidean a legitimate claim to artistic re­ geometry. Computer artists use THE ARTISTIC COMPUTER: spect? Or is it simply a techno­ algorithms based on the analytic logical charlatan, recalcitrant geometry of Descartes to compute A PROTEAN ENIGMA to acculturation and slippery as pictures as well as the subjects in them. An examination of the work­ Computers are protean. Gamboling fromthe churning high Proteus when we try to grasp its ings of these two different types of seas of Postmodern ism, they disturb the cultural waters even essence? algorithm reveals that the com­ funher with their enigmatic and plastic visages. Like the Efforts to navigate these puter offers a radical new approach to making art, which is not yet well Greek god of the sea, they are facile with disparate guises­ troubled waters sometimes liken the computer to a me­ understood. Postmodern a,lgo­ pretending to be now a pencil, then a spreadsheet, a design rithms for picturemaking are more studio, an airplane, a chess partner, a paintbrush, a racon­ dium as a way of explaining its evanescent than their Renaissance teur, and most certainly a sorcerer-all the while remaining role in art [2]. But upon exami­ counterparts because computers process information conceptually nothing other than hyperactive dervishes spinning out my­ nation, I believe we will find the concept of the computer as a instead of storing it physically. The riad illusions by proficiently manipulating numbers. Add to computer is neither a passive this that their sometimes obstreperous mischief makes them medium to be more misleading medium nor a pliant tool, but an seem more demons than deities, and it is no wonder that than useful. Computer art will active creative partner. critics and the artgoing public alike are suspicious of com- be better understood and more readily accepted by a skeptical artworld if we acknowledge Fig. L SamuelEdgerton's rendition (from Ref. [3]) of how how different it is from traditional tools. The computer is Brunelleschi constructedhis first perspective picture. The Bap­ tistryis situated behind the artist. The easel holds a mirror on the an extension of the mind, not of the hand or eye, and, unlike left and a painted panel on the right. Measurements are taken cinema or photography, it does not simply add a new me­ fromthe mirror by caliper and then transferred to the panel. dium to the artist's repertoire, based on a new technology. The role of media in artmaking is fundamentallyaltered by 'thinking machines'. It will help clarify the confusing rubric 'Computer Art', which congregates a multitude of disparate objects and events, by looking at the art-historical context. Let us begin by studying differences between picturing techniques used by Renaissance artists and those employed more recently by computer artists. By comparing the alternative ways perspec­ tive drawings are rendered, we can begin to understand in a familiar context the radical new approach to artmaking in­ troduced by computers. The computer does much more than assist imagemaking, but once we understand its novel approach in familiar territory, we will be better able to chart its wild and woolly antics. So, taking a lesson from the old myth, let us grasp this protean creature relentlessly until it gives us ,some answers. CONSTRUCTIVE ALGORITHMS: THE TRANSPARENT WINDOW Circa 1425 A.O., Filippo di Ser Brunellescho made a revolu­ tionary pilgrimage to the Baptistry of Florence to develop what we now call an 'algorithm' for making pictures. His Timothy Binkley (academic administrator), Institute for Computers in the Ans, School of Visual Arts, 209 East 23rd SL, New York, NY, 10010, U.S.A. <CJ1989 ISAST Pergamon Press pie. Printed in Japan. 0024-094X/89$3.00+0.00 LEONARDO, ComputerArt in Context Supplementallssue. pp. 13-20, 1989 13 Fig. 2. Albrecht Diirer, TheDesi gner of theL ying Woman. In this version of the ConstructiveAlgorithm, the point of view is fixed by a small obelisk marking the place where the artist moves his eye to take readings. The picture plane is the framed grid of strings.A matching grid is drawn on the paper and used to transfer points from the picture plane. Fig. 3. Albrecht Diirer, TheDesi gner of the Can. In this version of the Constructive Algorithm, the artist draws directly on the picture plane, which is transparent. achievement changed the history of embraced by many artists of the Re­ great discoveries, Brunelleschi's art. Perspective had apparently been naissance who used them to create seemed obvious once articulated, and used in ancient times, but there ex­ spectacular works of art with hereto­ the rules of the algorithm are simple isted no records of any formulae that fore unseen depth and startling points to follow. Its purpose is to correlate might be applied systematically to con­ ofview [ 4]. The illusionary panoramas points on the image with points in the struct a perspective picture. By using a these algorithms produce have be­ represented setting. This is done by re­ mirror to ascertain picture elements, come so much a pan of our culture peatedly connecting the point of view Brunelleschi essentially delineated a that we no longer feel the aston­ to points in the scene (using light rays process that can be described with a ishment they provoked in fifteenth­ in Figs 1 and 2 and a taut string in Fig. set of step-by-step instructions for century Florentines. 3). Lines so constructed will intersect transferring the appearance of the Brunelleschi's algorithm, like its the picture plane at a point that repre­ everyday three-dimensional world to a progeny, is based on the constructive sents the corresponding point in the convincing two-dimensional image on geometry of Euclid. Its essentjal pa­ world. With this sort of algorithm, the a panel [3]. According to Samuel rameters are fixed in the pictured set­ perspective picture is actually con­ Edgerton's hypothesis (Fig. 1), the art­ ting: a point-the point of view-from structedfollowing Euclid's classic prin­ ist placed a mirror on an easel next to where the scene is seen, and a plane-­ ciples of geometric construction with the panel to be painted. With his back the picture plane-determining straightedge and compass. The con­ toward the Baptistry and his own re­ where the image will be cast onto a sur­ viction of the apparition so fabricated flection partially obscuring the view, face [5]. These elements are more ap­ is grounded in Euclid's Twenty-First Brunelleschi transferred magnitudes parent as well as easier to use in one of Proposition (Fig. 4), which guarantees of reflections in the mirror onto the Albrecht Dure r's renditions (Fig. 2), by similar triangles that proportions in panel by means ofa caliper. His algo­ where the point is determined by a the picture will preserve those in its rithm spawned others that were codi­ small obelisk and the plane by a subject as perceived from the view­ fied by Alberti 10 years later and were framed grid of strings. Like many point. 14 Binkley,The Wizard of Ethereal Pictures and Virtual Places Once his algorithm became known, tion of what was outside. Brunelleschi at how the two types of picturing algo­ industrious artists foundmany ways of and his peers broke through the bar­ rithms differ. implementing and modifying Brunel­ rier of the wall and instituted a com­ The underlying frameworks are leschi's insight. Durer made a number pletely systematic method of project­ similar: beginning with an object, a of woodcuts depicting different meth­ ing three dimensions into two to plane, and a point, we create a repre­ ods. In yet another of his constructive reveal a pictured world so clear and re­ sentation of the object in the plane by algorithms (see Fig. 3), the artist again fined that it appears as if viewed scrutinizing lines connecting the ob­ fixed the pointof view with a screw eye through an open window. Easel paint­ ject and the point. Perspective projec­ mounted on a wall, but the picture ing was born on moveable framed tions using the two algorithms may plane was a transparent sheet and the panels. sometimes have similar app.earances, lines of sight were intersected with the but they are quite different and can picture plane by aiming them through yield rather different-looking results. a viewing tube attached to a string tied COMPUTATIONAL In order to highlight their differences, to the screw eye. All of these algo­ ALGORITHMS: THE let us step up to the easel beside Bru­ rithms involved geometrical construc­ nelleschi and compare 'manual' exe­ tions that are accomplished with man­ LUMINOUS SCREEN cutions of both. ual tools such as pens, strings, rulers Two hundred years after Brunel­ As Brunelleschi deftly gleans the and calipers and were carried out in leschi's discovery, Descartes built the outlines of his picture by casting the actual presence of the depicted foundation for a rather different kind glances at his mirror, we laboriously setting. Related techniques were de­ of picturing algorithm based on ana­ begin setting up a coordinate system veloped by Alberti and subsequently lytic geometry. Although such algo­ by arbitrarily (but we hope conven­ by others for designing perspective rithms were not widely used until the iently) locating an origin and three images of simple geometrical shapes advent of computers, they can be de­ perpendicular axes.
Recommended publications
  • From Point to Pixel: a Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy
    From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric and the Designated Emphasis in Film Studies in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Whitney Davis, co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, co-chair Professor Warren Sack Professor Abigail DeKosnik Professor Kristen Whissel Spring 2010 Copyright 2010 by Hoy, Meredith All rights reserved. Abstract From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric University of California, Berkeley Professor Whitney Davis, Co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, Co-chair When we say, in response to a still or moving picture, that it has a digital “look” about it, what exactly do we mean? How can the slick, color-saturated photographs of Jeff Wall and Andreas Gursky signal digitality, while the flattened, pixelated landscapes of video games such as Super Mario Brothers convey ostensibly the same characteristic of “being digital,” but in a completely different manner? In my dissertation, From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics, I argue for a definition of a "digital method" that can be articulated without reference to the technicalities of contemporary hardware and software. I allow, however, the possibility that this digital method can acquire new characteristics when it is performed by computational technology. I therefore treat the artworks covered in my dissertation as sensuous artifacts that are subject to change based on the constraints and affordances of the tools used in their making.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Attempting Art: an Essay on Intention-Dependence
    Attempting Art: an essay on intention-dependence Michel-Antoine Xhignesse Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montréal December 2016 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Michel-Antoine Xhignesse 2016 Table of Contents Dissertation abstract ................................................................................................................ iii Résumé de thèse ....................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................... v Chapter 1 – Introductory Remarks............................................................................................. 1 Chapter 2 – Art, Intention, and Intention-Dependence ............................................................ 9 2.1 – Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 9 2.2 – Intentional action ................................................................................................................. 11 2.3 – Intention-dependence vs. concept-dependence .................................................................... 18 2.4 – Accidents and Incidents ....................................................................................................... 22 2.5 – Separating Concept- and Intention-Dependence
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore?
    KENDALL WALTON Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore? It is a very great honor to address my friends and philosophy of quantum physics are younger. But colleagues as president of the American Society these are clearly subcategories of traditional, well- for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique established areas of philosophy—ethics and phi- role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional losophy of science—and they inherit much of their branch of philosophy and also central to disci- identity and sense of purpose from their parents. plines often regarded as remote from philosophy, Aesthetics is not so fortunate. It is related in vari- as well as depending crucially on their contribu- ous important ways to epistemology, metaphysics, tions. philosophy of mind, philosophy of language— I will follow the lead of one of my distinguished indeed it overlaps all of them—but these older predecessors in this office, Peter Kivy, who used relatives are at best aunts and uncles to aesthetics, the occasion of his own presidential address twelve not parents. Aesthetics must figure out for itself years ago to step back and reflect on the state of what exactly it is. the discipline and the nature of aesthetics.1 Two kinds of issues about the field need to be addressed: What is distinctive about this branch i. what is aesthetics? of philosophy, in contrast to others? And what is philosophy? Under the first heading, we will ask Aesthetics is a strange field, in some ways a con- what aesthetics is the philosophy of , what domain fused one.
    [Show full text]
  • Broken Technologies
    Broken Technologies 2 The Angel of Machines: from Buch der Erfindungen Gewerbe und Industrien,or Book of Inven- tions,Vol.6,1887, F.Reuleaux, Editor. From Moon, Francis C. The Machines of Leonardo da Vinci and Franz Reuleaux. Kinematics of Machines from the Renaissance to the 20th Century. Springer, 2007. FrontPage: © Maria Flores Crossa 3 Broken Technologies The Humanist as Engineer Fernando Flores Morador Lund University 2011- revised 2015 4 Department of History of Ideas and Science University of Lund Broken Technologies. The Humanist as Engineer. Ver 3.0 Biskopsgatan 7, 223 62 Lund © Fernando Flores Morador, 2009, Third Edition Cover: Maria Flores Crossa Tryck: Media – Tryck, Lunds Universitet, 2011-revised 2015 ISBN: 978-91-633-9692-2 5 Contents Contents ....................................................................................................................................... 5 List of figures .................................................................................................................................. 7 List of Tables.................................................................................................................................. 9 Foreword .................................................................................................................................. 11 First Edition (Ver. 1.0) ................................................................................................................ 11 Second edition (Ver. 1.1) ...........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Hans Urs Von Balthasar, the Glory of the Lord: a Theological Aesthetics, 7 Vols, Various Translators; Vol
    Notes PREFACE 1. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, 7 vols, various translators; vol. 1 (San Francisco: Ignatius; and New York: Crossroad, 1982); vols 2-3 (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1984-86); vols 4-7, trans. in progress. The range and depth of von Balthasar's treatment of various theological issues and figures relevant to matters of theological aesthetics makes his work a major resource for study in the field, and especially for historical understanding of a kind impossible to pursue here. His treatment of issues normally dealt with in aesthetics is nonetheless spotty and erratic; many of the theological and philosophical topics central to the present study are ones on which he barely touches. That is to say, von Balthasar's work is sui generis, standing outside the main arenas of both contemporary aesthetics and modem theology. For the most part I have had to be content to let him speak for himself. 2. Nicholas Wolterstorff, Art in Action: Toward a Christian Aesthetic (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1980). 3. Gerardus van der Leeuw, Sacred and Profane Beauty: The Holy in Art, trans. David E. Green (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963). 4. John Dillenberger, A Theology of Artistic Sensibilities: The Visual Arts and the Church (New York: Crossroad, 1986). 5. Thomas R. Martland, Religion as Art (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1981). 6. F. David Martin, Art and the Religious Experience: The 'Language' of the Sacred (Lewisburg, Penn.: Bucknell University Press, 1972). 7. Frank Burch Brown, Transfiguration: Poetic Metaphor and the Languages of Religious Belief (Chapel Hill and London: University of North Carolina Press, 1983).
    [Show full text]
  • Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space
    theoretical perspective From Imaginal to Digital: Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space Nick Lambert a b s t r a c t The author suggests that the intangible characteristics of computer graphics bear some resemblance to the brain’s ability to construct mental images, as outlined by veteran s a historian of computer art, I am fascinated Kosslyn and his team at Harvard researcher Stephen M. Kosslyn. A An analogy might also be drawn by the nature of digital images and the way in which people have been looking at the visual with the “Imaginal World” of the apprehend them. Images that are rendered on a screen ap- psychology and neurophysiology Sufis, as described by Henri parently exist in a plane separate to the rest of our world, of mental imagery for several de- Corbin, which exists in a space analogous to the pictorial space developed by artists but with cades. Using PET and fMRI scan- of its own. As computer graph- an animate and interactive aspect wholly its own. Their basis is ners, Kosslyn and his collaborators ics have emerged as an artistic not visual but mathematical and process-driven, although the have discovered that particular medium, one may consider how this internalized ability influences computer has evolved into a device for generating imagery. As brain areas related to color and the artist’s response to the com- we become ever more adept at creating and navigating a range shape perception activate during puter, especially as new display of virtual worlds (whether the mundane desktop or the exotic the imaginary phase.
    [Show full text]
  • Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting
    Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting A dissertation presented to the faculty of The Patton College of Education of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Cynthia A. Agyeman December 2015 © 2015 Cynthia A. Agyeman. All Rights Reserved. 2 This dissertation titled Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting by CYNTHIA A. AGYEMAN has been approved for the Department of Educational Studies and The Patton College of Education by Teresa Franklin Professor of Educational Studies Renée A. Middleton Dean, The Patton College of Education 3 Abstract AGYEMAN, CYNTHIA A., Ph.D., December 2015, Curriculum and Instruction, Instructional Technology Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting (pp. 310) Director of Dissertation: Teresa Franklin Painting is believed to predate recorded history and has been in existence for over 35,000 (Ayres, 1985; Bolton, 2013) years. Over the years, painting has evolved; new styles have been developed and digital media have been explored. Each period of change goes through a period of rejection before it is accepted. In the 1960s, digital media was introduced to the art form. Like all the painting mediums, it was rejected. It has been over 50 years since it was introduced and yet, it has not been fully accepted as an art form (King, 2002; Miller, 2007; Noll, 1994). This exploratory study seeks to understand the artist’s perception on the use of digital media as an art tool and its benefit to the artists and art education. Grounded theory was used as a methodological guide for the study.
    [Show full text]
  • Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(S): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol
    Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(s): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 40, No. 3 (Spring, 1982), pp. 309- 314 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688 Accessed: 09-08-2017 22:42 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PEGGY ZEGLIN BRAND Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art IN "Convention and Dickie's Institutional lack of spontaneity in artworks, i.e., the Theory," Catherine Lord maintains loss the of flexibility espoused by Dickie's defi- following thesis: nition, is established by Lord via two routes: a) arguing that being a work of (L) If a work of art is defined as institutional and conventional, then the definition artpre- is incompatible with institutionality cludes the freedom and creativity associated (Incompatibility Argument), and b) argu- with art.' ing that the creation, presentation, and ap- Lord also maintains that the antecedent of preciation of a work of art is not governed this conditional is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Cahiers Des Théories De L'art 1
    Revue Proteus – Cahiers des théories de l’art 1 Revue Proteus n° 4, la place de l'esthétique en philosophie de l'art Édito On le sait, les écrits de Platon abordaient séparément les questions relatives au beau et à l'art, séparément aussi celles relatives à l'art et aux sensations. e Mis à part quelques textes précurseurs, il a fallu attendre le XVII siècle pour que se théorisent plus précisément les liens unissant l'art aux sensations et que le goût intéresse les philosophes de l'art. Les règles de la bonne œuvre se voient évacuées au profit d'une appréciation subjective du spectateur. L'art est dès lors affaire d'esthétique. Quelque trois siècles ont suffi pour que se multiplient les opposants aux approches esthétiques de l'art ; ce présent numéro de la revue Proteus peut à ce sujet être lu comme un commentaire du texte de Timothy Binkley inti- tulé « “Pièces” contre l'esthétique ». Ce texte défend l'idée que l'apparence sensible de certaines pièces d'art n'est clairement plus gage de leurs appré- ciations et que l'esthétique n'a donc plus de pertinence pour penser l'art. Cette hypothèse, pour être consolidée, doit encore considérer le sujet perce- vant en plus du monde sensible lui-même : ce n'est en effet pas le monde sensible qui sent, et l'esthétique est affaire du sujet sentant. Ce sujet sentant est toutefois le même qui trouve souvent qu'il faille connaître un artiste pour aimer ses œuvres, le même qui dit parfois ne rien « comprendre » à l'art contemporain.
    [Show full text]
  • ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016 Dissertation directed by: Professor Jerrold Levinson Department of Philosophy This dissertation defends a positive answer to the question: \Can a videogame be a work of art?" To achieve this goal I develop definitions of several concepts, primarily `art', `games', and `videogames', and analyze arguments about the com- patibility between these notions. In Part One, I defend a definition of art from amongst several contemporary and historical accounts. This definition, the Intentional-Historical account, requires, among other things, that an artwork have the right kind of creative intentions behind it, in short that the work be intended to be regarded in a particular manner. This is a leading account that has faced several recent objections that I address while arguing that it is superior to other theories in its ability to answer the question of videogames' art status. Part Two examines whether games can exhibit that kind of creative intention. Recent literature has suggested that they can. I propose and defend an account of games according to which games cannot be intended to be works of art because games are goal-directed activities that require a voluntary selection of inefficient means that is incompatible with the proper manner of regarding that is necessary for artworks. While the conclusions of Part One and Part Two appear to suggest that videogames cannot be works of art, Part Three proposes and defends a new account of videogames that, contrary to first appearances, implies that not all videogames are games. This Intentional-Historical Formalist account allows for non-game videogames to be created with an art-making intention, though not every non-game videogame will have an art-making intention behind it.
    [Show full text]