1. Hans Urs Von Balthasar, the Glory of the Lord: a Theological Aesthetics, 7 Vols, Various Translators; Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1. Hans Urs Von Balthasar, the Glory of the Lord: a Theological Aesthetics, 7 Vols, Various Translators; Vol Notes PREFACE 1. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, 7 vols, various translators; vol. 1 (San Francisco: Ignatius; and New York: Crossroad, 1982); vols 2-3 (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1984-86); vols 4-7, trans. in progress. The range and depth of von Balthasar's treatment of various theological issues and figures relevant to matters of theological aesthetics makes his work a major resource for study in the field, and especially for historical understanding of a kind impossible to pursue here. His treatment of issues normally dealt with in aesthetics is nonetheless spotty and erratic; many of the theological and philosophical topics central to the present study are ones on which he barely touches. That is to say, von Balthasar's work is sui generis, standing outside the main arenas of both contemporary aesthetics and modem theology. For the most part I have had to be content to let him speak for himself. 2. Nicholas Wolterstorff, Art in Action: Toward a Christian Aesthetic (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1980). 3. Gerardus van der Leeuw, Sacred and Profane Beauty: The Holy in Art, trans. David E. Green (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963). 4. John Dillenberger, A Theology of Artistic Sensibilities: The Visual Arts and the Church (New York: Crossroad, 1986). 5. Thomas R. Martland, Religion as Art (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1981). 6. F. David Martin, Art and the Religious Experience: The 'Language' of the Sacred (Lewisburg, Penn.: Bucknell University Press, 1972). 7. Frank Burch Brown, Transfiguration: Poetic Metaphor and the Languages of Religious Belief (Chapel Hill and London: University of North Carolina Press, 1983). CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION 1. Hal Foster, 'Postmodernism: A Preface', in The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture, ed. Hal Foster (Port Townsend, Wash.: Bay Press, 1983). 2. David Carroll, Paraesthetics (London: Methuen, 1987) pp. xiv, xv. See also Christopher Norris, Paul de Man: Deconstruction and the Critique of Aesthetic Ideology (London: Routledge, 1988). 3. Janet Wolff, Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983) p. 107. 4. See Jacques Derrida, 'Parergon', in The Truth in Painting, trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987). 5. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 1960; trans. G. Barden and J. Cumming (New York: Continuum, 1975). Aesthetics naturally 195 196 Notes to Chapter 2 merges with hermeneutics at the point of inquiring specifically into meaning and meaningfulness, or into truth and significance. Our divergence from Gadamer is partly a matter of emphasis. 6. See Martin Heidegger, 'The Origin of the Work of Art', in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York: Harper & Row, 1971). 7. See Roland Barthes, The Rustle of Language, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Hill & Wang, 1986) pp. 76-7; Barthes, Image, Music, Text, trans. Stephen Heath (New York: HilI & Wang, 1977) pp. 179-89; and Julia Kristeva, Desire in Language: A Semiotic Approach to Literature and Art, ed. Leon Roudiez (New York: Columbia University Press, 1980) p. 133. 8. Both of these kinds of concern are expressed, for example, by Sallie McFague in Models of God: Theology for an Ecological, Nuclear Age (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1987). 9. Cf. Giles Gunn, The Culture of Criticism and the Criticism of Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987). CHAPTER 2: CAN AESTHETICS BE CHRISTIAN? 1. See Stanley Hauerwas, The Peaceable Kingdom: A Primer in Christian Ethics (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983) pp. 50-4. 2. James M. Gustafson, Can Ethics Be Christian? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975). 3. See Oliver O'Donovan, Resurrection and Moral Order: An Outline for an Evangelical Ethics (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1987). 4. Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Glory of the Lord: A Theological Aesthetics, 7 vols; vol. 1 (San Francisco: Ignatius; and New York: Crossroad, 1982); vols 2-3 (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1984-6) vols 4-7, trans. in progress. 5. For documentation on the theological study of the arts and aesthe­ tics in North America, see Wilson Yates, The Arts in Theological Education (Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1987). 6. Dorothy L. Sayers, 'Towards a Christian Aesthetic', 1944; reprinted in Nathan A. Scott, Jr, ed., The New Orpheus: Essays Toward a Christian Poetic (New York: Sheed & Ward, 1964) pp. 3-20; quotation from p. 4. 7. von Balthasar, Glory I, 117. 8. For a discussion of writings sharply critical of aesthetics, see Mary Mothersill, Beauty Restored (London: Oxford University Press­ Clarendon, 1984) pp. 1-73. 9. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations: On Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, ed. Cyril Barrett (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967) p. 1. 10. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Aesthetica, 2 vols, 1750-8; reprint edn (Hildesheim: G.Olms, 1961). See also Ted Cohen and Paul Guyer, eds, Essays in Kant's Aesthetics (Chicago: University of Chica­ go Press, 1982) p. In. Notes to Chapter 2 197 11. William Blake, 'Aphorisms on the Laocoon Group', in Selected Poetry and Prose of Blake, ed. Northrop Frye (New York: Random House­ Modern Library, 1953) pp. 330, 328. 12. See R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (New York: Oxford University Press-Galaxy, 1958); and Benedetto Croce, 'Aesthetics', in the Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th edn; reprinted in Philosophies of Art and Beauty, ed. Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns (Chicago: Univerity of Chicago Press-Phoenix, 1976) pp. 556-76. Collingwood, in particular, is inconsistent, finally deciding that there is no good writing that is not art. See ibid., pp. 298-9. 13. See, for example, Monroe C. Beardsley, 'The Aesthetic Point of View', in Philosophy Looks at the Arts, rev. edn, Joseph Margolis, ed. (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1978) pp. 6-24. 14. Harold Osborne, 'Aesthetic Relevance', British Journal of Aesthetics 17 (1977): 294. 15. Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Criticism (Boston, Houghton Mifflin 1960) p. 36. 16. Virgil Aldrich, Philosophy of Art (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1963) p. 20. Stolnitz and Aldrich are criticized by George Dickie in his Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1974) pp. 113-46. 17. See Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, trans. Ralph Manheim, 3 vols. (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1953); and Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978). 18. See Martin Heidegger, 'The Origin of the Work of Art' and 'What Are Poets For?', in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York: Harper & Row, 1971). 19. See Etienne Gilson, The Arts of the Beautiful, 1965; reprint edn (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1976); Painting and Reality, 1957; reprint edn (Cleveland: World-Meridian, 1959); and Jacques Mari­ tain, Creative Intuition in Art and Poetry, 1953; reprint edn (New York: Meridian, 1955). Of the two thinkers Maritain is less purist in inclination, writing that 'poetry [in the very broadest sense] is the fruit neither of the intellect alone, nor of imagination alone. Nay more, it proceeds from the totality of man, sense, imagination, intellect, love, desire, instinct, blood and spirit together' (p. 80). Yet even Maritain is hemmed in by Aristotelian categories. In restricting art to the productive intellect, he cannot reckon adequately with the ways in which theoretical reason and moral deliberation may interact with poiesis and aesthesis, or vice versa. 20. See Susanne K. Langer, Feeling and Form (New York: Scribner's, 1953); and Mikel Dufrenne, The Phenomenology of Aesthetic Experience, trans. Edward S. Casey et al (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern Universi­ ty Press, 1973), esp. p. 551. 21. See John Dewey, Art as Experience, 1934; reprint edn (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons-Capricorn, 1958). Dewey would be the last person to want to separate art from the everyday interests and experiences of life, having fought vigorously against what he terms 198 Notes to Chapter 2 the 'compartmental conception of fine art' (p. 8). Yet he is better at describing formal 'rhythms' of art and everyday aesthetic experi­ ence than in seeing how they actually qualify thoughts, moral judgments, intellectual systems, and religious valuations. 22. Sir Thomas Browne, Religio Medici, in Selected Writings, ed. Sir Geoffrey Keynes (London: Faber & Faber, 1968), p. 80. 23. Igor Stravinsky, Poetics of Music, trans. Arthur Knodel and Ingolf Dahl, 1942; reprint edn (New York: Random House-Vintage, 1947) p.l46. 24. Karl Barth, Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart, trans. Clarence K. Pott (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1986) pp. 16,20,33-40,55-7. 25. Clive Bell, Art, 1913; reprint edn (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons­ Capricorn, 1958) p. 54. 26. Lynn Poland well documents this feature of the New Criticism in her book Literary Criticism and Biblical Hermeneutics: A Critique of Formalist Approaches (Chico, Calif.: Scholars Press, American Academy of Religion Academy Series, no. 48, 1985). 27. Hans-Georg Gadamer explicitly constructs an analogy between, on the one hand, a Lutheran or Catholic conception of the sacramental bread and wine as the flesh and blood of Christ and, on the other hand, the way in which the work of art, rather than referring to something outside itself, constitutes and signifies in itself 'an increase in being'. See Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays, trans. Nicholas Walker, ed. Robert Bernasconi (Cam­ bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986) p. 35. Cf. Erich Heller, The Disinherited Mind: Essays in Modern German Literature and Thought, 1952; reprint edn (Cleveland: World-Meridian, 1959) pp. 261-4. 28. Mark C. Taylor, Erring: A Postmodern A/theology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984) pp. 146-69. 29. von Balthasar, I, 117, 118. 30. John Henry Newman, 'Poetry, with Reference to Aristotle's Poetics', in Essays and Sketches, ed. Charles Frederick Harrold. 3 vols (London: Longmans, Green, 1948) vol. I, p. 76. 31. S0ren Kierkegaard, On Authority and Revelation: The Book on Adler, or a Cycle of Ethico-Religious Essays, trans.
Recommended publications
  • From Point to Pixel: a Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy
    From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric and the Designated Emphasis in Film Studies in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Whitney Davis, co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, co-chair Professor Warren Sack Professor Abigail DeKosnik Professor Kristen Whissel Spring 2010 Copyright 2010 by Hoy, Meredith All rights reserved. Abstract From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics by Meredith Anne Hoy Doctor of Philosophy in Rhetoric University of California, Berkeley Professor Whitney Davis, Co-chair Professor Jeffrey Skoller, Co-chair When we say, in response to a still or moving picture, that it has a digital “look” about it, what exactly do we mean? How can the slick, color-saturated photographs of Jeff Wall and Andreas Gursky signal digitality, while the flattened, pixelated landscapes of video games such as Super Mario Brothers convey ostensibly the same characteristic of “being digital,” but in a completely different manner? In my dissertation, From Point to Pixel: A Genealogy of Digital Aesthetics, I argue for a definition of a "digital method" that can be articulated without reference to the technicalities of contemporary hardware and software. I allow, however, the possibility that this digital method can acquire new characteristics when it is performed by computational technology. I therefore treat the artworks covered in my dissertation as sensuous artifacts that are subject to change based on the constraints and affordances of the tools used in their making.
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Attempting Art: an Essay on Intention-Dependence
    Attempting Art: an essay on intention-dependence Michel-Antoine Xhignesse Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montréal December 2016 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Michel-Antoine Xhignesse 2016 Table of Contents Dissertation abstract ................................................................................................................ iii Résumé de thèse ....................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................... v Chapter 1 – Introductory Remarks............................................................................................. 1 Chapter 2 – Art, Intention, and Intention-Dependence ............................................................ 9 2.1 – Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 9 2.2 – Intentional action ................................................................................................................. 11 2.3 – Intention-dependence vs. concept-dependence .................................................................... 18 2.4 – Accidents and Incidents ....................................................................................................... 22 2.5 – Separating Concept- and Intention-Dependence
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore?
    KENDALL WALTON Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore? It is a very great honor to address my friends and philosophy of quantum physics are younger. But colleagues as president of the American Society these are clearly subcategories of traditional, well- for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique established areas of philosophy—ethics and phi- role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional losophy of science—and they inherit much of their branch of philosophy and also central to disci- identity and sense of purpose from their parents. plines often regarded as remote from philosophy, Aesthetics is not so fortunate. It is related in vari- as well as depending crucially on their contribu- ous important ways to epistemology, metaphysics, tions. philosophy of mind, philosophy of language— I will follow the lead of one of my distinguished indeed it overlaps all of them—but these older predecessors in this office, Peter Kivy, who used relatives are at best aunts and uncles to aesthetics, the occasion of his own presidential address twelve not parents. Aesthetics must figure out for itself years ago to step back and reflect on the state of what exactly it is. the discipline and the nature of aesthetics.1 Two kinds of issues about the field need to be addressed: What is distinctive about this branch i. what is aesthetics? of philosophy, in contrast to others? And what is philosophy? Under the first heading, we will ask Aesthetics is a strange field, in some ways a con- what aesthetics is the philosophy of , what domain fused one.
    [Show full text]
  • Broken Technologies
    Broken Technologies 2 The Angel of Machines: from Buch der Erfindungen Gewerbe und Industrien,or Book of Inven- tions,Vol.6,1887, F.Reuleaux, Editor. From Moon, Francis C. The Machines of Leonardo da Vinci and Franz Reuleaux. Kinematics of Machines from the Renaissance to the 20th Century. Springer, 2007. FrontPage: © Maria Flores Crossa 3 Broken Technologies The Humanist as Engineer Fernando Flores Morador Lund University 2011- revised 2015 4 Department of History of Ideas and Science University of Lund Broken Technologies. The Humanist as Engineer. Ver 3.0 Biskopsgatan 7, 223 62 Lund © Fernando Flores Morador, 2009, Third Edition Cover: Maria Flores Crossa Tryck: Media – Tryck, Lunds Universitet, 2011-revised 2015 ISBN: 978-91-633-9692-2 5 Contents Contents ....................................................................................................................................... 5 List of figures .................................................................................................................................. 7 List of Tables.................................................................................................................................. 9 Foreword .................................................................................................................................. 11 First Edition (Ver. 1.0) ................................................................................................................ 11 Second edition (Ver. 1.1) ...........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space
    theoretical perspective From Imaginal to Digital: Mental Imagery and the Computer Image Space Nick Lambert a b s t r a c t The author suggests that the intangible characteristics of computer graphics bear some resemblance to the brain’s ability to construct mental images, as outlined by veteran s a historian of computer art, I am fascinated Kosslyn and his team at Harvard researcher Stephen M. Kosslyn. A An analogy might also be drawn by the nature of digital images and the way in which people have been looking at the visual with the “Imaginal World” of the apprehend them. Images that are rendered on a screen ap- psychology and neurophysiology Sufis, as described by Henri parently exist in a plane separate to the rest of our world, of mental imagery for several de- Corbin, which exists in a space analogous to the pictorial space developed by artists but with cades. Using PET and fMRI scan- of its own. As computer graph- an animate and interactive aspect wholly its own. Their basis is ners, Kosslyn and his collaborators ics have emerged as an artistic not visual but mathematical and process-driven, although the have discovered that particular medium, one may consider how this internalized ability influences computer has evolved into a device for generating imagery. As brain areas related to color and the artist’s response to the com- we become ever more adept at creating and navigating a range shape perception activate during puter, especially as new display of virtual worlds (whether the mundane desktop or the exotic the imaginary phase.
    [Show full text]
  • Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting
    Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting A dissertation presented to the faculty of The Patton College of Education of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Cynthia A. Agyeman December 2015 © 2015 Cynthia A. Agyeman. All Rights Reserved. 2 This dissertation titled Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting by CYNTHIA A. AGYEMAN has been approved for the Department of Educational Studies and The Patton College of Education by Teresa Franklin Professor of Educational Studies Renée A. Middleton Dean, The Patton College of Education 3 Abstract AGYEMAN, CYNTHIA A., Ph.D., December 2015, Curriculum and Instruction, Instructional Technology Artists' Perception of the Use of Digital Media in Painting (pp. 310) Director of Dissertation: Teresa Franklin Painting is believed to predate recorded history and has been in existence for over 35,000 (Ayres, 1985; Bolton, 2013) years. Over the years, painting has evolved; new styles have been developed and digital media have been explored. Each period of change goes through a period of rejection before it is accepted. In the 1960s, digital media was introduced to the art form. Like all the painting mediums, it was rejected. It has been over 50 years since it was introduced and yet, it has not been fully accepted as an art form (King, 2002; Miller, 2007; Noll, 1994). This exploratory study seeks to understand the artist’s perception on the use of digital media as an art tool and its benefit to the artists and art education. Grounded theory was used as a methodological guide for the study.
    [Show full text]
  • Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(S): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: the Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol
    Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art Author(s): Peggy Zeglin Brand Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 40, No. 3 (Spring, 1982), pp. 309- 314 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688 Accessed: 09-08-2017 22:42 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/429688?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism This content downloaded from 150.135.239.97 on Wed, 09 Aug 2017 22:42:09 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PEGGY ZEGLIN BRAND Lord, Lewis, and the Institutional Theory of Art IN "Convention and Dickie's Institutional lack of spontaneity in artworks, i.e., the Theory," Catherine Lord maintains loss the of flexibility espoused by Dickie's defi- following thesis: nition, is established by Lord via two routes: a) arguing that being a work of (L) If a work of art is defined as institutional and conventional, then the definition artpre- is incompatible with institutionality cludes the freedom and creativity associated (Incompatibility Argument), and b) argu- with art.' ing that the creation, presentation, and ap- Lord also maintains that the antecedent of preciation of a work of art is not governed this conditional is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Cahiers Des Théories De L'art 1
    Revue Proteus – Cahiers des théories de l’art 1 Revue Proteus n° 4, la place de l'esthétique en philosophie de l'art Édito On le sait, les écrits de Platon abordaient séparément les questions relatives au beau et à l'art, séparément aussi celles relatives à l'art et aux sensations. e Mis à part quelques textes précurseurs, il a fallu attendre le XVII siècle pour que se théorisent plus précisément les liens unissant l'art aux sensations et que le goût intéresse les philosophes de l'art. Les règles de la bonne œuvre se voient évacuées au profit d'une appréciation subjective du spectateur. L'art est dès lors affaire d'esthétique. Quelque trois siècles ont suffi pour que se multiplient les opposants aux approches esthétiques de l'art ; ce présent numéro de la revue Proteus peut à ce sujet être lu comme un commentaire du texte de Timothy Binkley inti- tulé « “Pièces” contre l'esthétique ». Ce texte défend l'idée que l'apparence sensible de certaines pièces d'art n'est clairement plus gage de leurs appré- ciations et que l'esthétique n'a donc plus de pertinence pour penser l'art. Cette hypothèse, pour être consolidée, doit encore considérer le sujet perce- vant en plus du monde sensible lui-même : ce n'est en effet pas le monde sensible qui sent, et l'esthétique est affaire du sujet sentant. Ce sujet sentant est toutefois le même qui trouve souvent qu'il faille connaître un artiste pour aimer ses œuvres, le même qui dit parfois ne rien « comprendre » à l'art contemporain.
    [Show full text]
  • ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: ARE VIDEOGAMES ART? Brock Rough, Doctor of Philosophy, 2016 Dissertation directed by: Professor Jerrold Levinson Department of Philosophy This dissertation defends a positive answer to the question: \Can a videogame be a work of art?" To achieve this goal I develop definitions of several concepts, primarily `art', `games', and `videogames', and analyze arguments about the com- patibility between these notions. In Part One, I defend a definition of art from amongst several contemporary and historical accounts. This definition, the Intentional-Historical account, requires, among other things, that an artwork have the right kind of creative intentions behind it, in short that the work be intended to be regarded in a particular manner. This is a leading account that has faced several recent objections that I address while arguing that it is superior to other theories in its ability to answer the question of videogames' art status. Part Two examines whether games can exhibit that kind of creative intention. Recent literature has suggested that they can. I propose and defend an account of games according to which games cannot be intended to be works of art because games are goal-directed activities that require a voluntary selection of inefficient means that is incompatible with the proper manner of regarding that is necessary for artworks. While the conclusions of Part One and Part Two appear to suggest that videogames cannot be works of art, Part Three proposes and defends a new account of videogames that, contrary to first appearances, implies that not all videogames are games. This Intentional-Historical Formalist account allows for non-game videogames to be created with an art-making intention, though not every non-game videogame will have an art-making intention behind it.
    [Show full text]
  • PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014
    1 PHL 317K Introduction to Philosophy of the Arts Spring 2014 Unique # 43270, 43275, 43280 TIME: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 2:00-2:50 p.m. and a third hour LOCATION: WAG 302 (TTH 2:00 – 2:50 p.m.) (Check your schedule for third hour location) INSTRUCTOR: Prof. Kathleen Higgins OFFICE: WAG 203 (512) 471-5564 OFFICE HOURS: Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:45-11:45 a.m. E-MAIL: <[email protected]> COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course will consider some of the answers given in the Western philosophical tradition to questions about the nature of art and beauty, as well as offering a brief overview of some perspectives from Japan. Particular attention will be given to the distinction between art and reality, and to the nature of the aesthetic experience from the standpoint of both the artist and the observer. TEACHING ASSISTANT: TBA TEXTBOOK: Kathleen Marie Higgins, ed., Aesthetics in Perspective POLICIES: Late assignments will automatically receive ten fewer percentage points than they would otherwise have received. Late assignments will not be accepted more than one week after the date due. Late assignments will not be accepted after the last day of class. Makeup exams or extensions will be arranged only in situations of an emergency or serious illness. The instructor may ask for evidence. Students with disabilities may request appropriate academic accommodations from the Division of Diversity and Community Engagement, Services for Students with Disabilities, 471-6259 2 GRADING AND IMPORTANT DATES: January 23 Short paper due 5% February 13 Exam I 15% March 6 Journal entries 1-6 due 10% March 20 Exam II 15% April 17 Exam III 15% April 29 Journal entries 7-12 due 10% May 1 Final written project due 20% Participation (includes attendance, in-class writing, in-class quizzes, etc.) 10% GRADING: Grades will be computed using the plus-minus system.
    [Show full text]