Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science Synthese Library

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science Synthese Library STUDIES IN THE METHODOLOGY AND FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MATHEMATICAL METHODS OF SOCIAL AND BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON~Princeton University J AAKKO HINTIKKA, University of Helsinki and Stanford University GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, Indiana University PATRICK SUPPES STUDIES IN THE METHODOLOGY AND FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE Selected Papers from 1951 to 1969 SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. ISBN 978-90-481-8320-3 ISBN 978-94-017-3173-7 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-3173-7 1969 All rights reserved No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any other means, without written permission from the publisher Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 1st edition 1969 TO ERNEST NAGEL AND ALFRED TARSKI PREFACE The twenty-three papers collected in tbis volume represent an important part of my published work up to the date of this volume. I have not arranged the paper chronologically, but under four main headings. Part I contains five papers on methodology concerned with models and measurement in the sciences. This part also contains the first paper I published, 'A Set of Independent Axioms for Extensive Quantities', in Portugaliae Mathematica in 1951. Part 11 also is concerned with methodology and ineludes six papers on probability and utility. It is not always easy to separate papers on probability and utility from papers on measurement, because of the elose connection between the two subjects, but Artieles 6 and 8, even though they have elose relations to measurement, seem more properly to belong in Part 11, because they are concerned with substantive questions about probability and utility. The last two parts are concerned with the foundations of physics and the foundations of psychology. I have used the term foundations rather than philosophy, because the papers are mainly concerned with specific axiomatic formulations for particular parts of physics or of psychology, and it seems to me that the termfoundations more appropriately describes such constructive axiomatic ventures. Part 111 contains four papers on the foundations of physics. The first paper deals with foundations of special relativity and the last three with the role ofprobability in quantum mechanics. I regret not ineluding some of the earlier work with J. C. C. McKinsey on the foundations of elassical mechanics, but I already have given an account in general terms of that work in the last chapter of my Introduction to Logic. The largest number of papers is in the final part on the foundations of psychology. The greater concentration of papers here correct1y refiects my interests over the past decade. In fact, the bulk of my papers that I think are of some conceptual importance and that are not ineluded in tbis volume are papers that lie strict1y within mathematical psychology as a VIII PREFACE scientific discipline, and are consequently not really appropriate for inc1usion in the present volume. Because so many of the papers in Part IV are concerned with the psychological foundations of mathematics in one form or another, it would almost have been appropriate to have so labeled Part IV. But I have inc1uded several papers that have nothing directly to do with his subject, and so I have kept the more general title. Two of the papers in this collection were written with co-authors. The fourth paper, 'Foundational Aspects of Theories of Measurement', was writtenjointly with Dana Scott. The eighth paper, 'An Axiomatization of Utility Based on the Notion of Utility Differences', was written jointly with Murie1 Winet. The appearance of these two papers here has been generously agreed to by them. Two of the papers have not previously been published. These are the papers, 'Behaviorism' and 'On the Theory of Cognitive Processes' . The first of these two papers was written between 1963 and 1965, and was given in various revised forms at Swarthmore College and at the University of Illinois. The second of the two papers was written in 1967 and was given as an Arnold Isenberg Memorial Lecture at Michigan State University. Acknowledgments for permission to publish the various papers are given at the bottom of the first page of each artic1e, but thanks are extended here to the many editors and publishers who generously granted this permission. No substantive or real stylistic changes have been made in any of the artic1es; only the manner of referring to published artic1es and books has been standardized, as has the formatting of seetion headings. Footnotes in the original articles are numbered, beginning anew with each artic1e; the bibliographie footnotes that originate with this publication are indicated by a dagger following the number. Same introduetory remarks about eaeh article and subsequent pertinent lit­ erature are to be found at the beginning of each part. The publication of aseries of papers spanning more than 18 years of work seems an appropriate occasion to acknowledge some of the intel­ lectual debts I have ineurred during those years. For my initial intro­ duction to the philosophy of science and for continual intellectual counsel and advice, I owe a great deal to Ernest Nagel. Shortly after my arrival at Stanford University in 1950, J. C. C. McKinsey joined the faculty of the Department of Philosophy, and I learned from hirn the set-theoretical PREFACE IX tools that have been one of my main stocks in trade over the years. Various collaborative work that we planned beyond the several articles we originaHy published was abruptly halted by his untimely death in 1953. McKinsey acknowledged that the greatest influence on his scientific career had been Alfred Tarski. Both through McKinsey and also through direct acquaintance with Tarski, inc1uding attendance at his seminars at Berkeley during the years when I was first at Stanford and through his published works as well, I learned much of what I know ab out intellectual c1arity and precision. And so, I take this occasion to acknowledge how much I owe to Tarski. I am indebted to William K. Estes for my first introduction to the conceptual and foundational problems of psychology, especially mathematical learning theory. We worked together intensively during 1955-56 when we were both Fellows at the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Stanford. In more recent years I have also learned much from Duncan Luce about both mathematical psychology and the theory of measurement. It is important to record that I owe a very considerable debt to my younger colleagues as well. I mention especiaHy Dana Scott and Richard C. Atkinson. The idea of putting this volume together originated with Donald Davidson and Jaakko Hintikka. To both ofthem I owe a further debt for enlightening and penetrating conversations about philosophical matters. This is especially true of Davidson, who was my colleague at Stanford for many years. Finally, I want to acknowledge the dedicated and able editorial assistance of Miss Diana Axelson and Mrs. Lillian O'Toole, as weH as the excellent help of Miss Anne Fagot in preparing the indexes and that of Mrs. Maria Jedd in preparing the illustrations. PATRICK SUPPES Stanford, California, January 1969 CONTENTS PREFACE VII PAR TI: METHODOLOGY: MODELS AND MEASUREMENT 1. A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences (1960) 10 2. Models of Data (1962) 24 3. A Set of Independent Axioms for Extensive Quantities (1951) 36 4. Foundational Aspects of Theories of Measurement (1958) (with Dana Scott) 46 5. Measurement, Empirical Meaningfulness, and Three-Valued Logic (1959) 65 PART Il: METHODOLOGY: PROB ABILITY AND UTILITY 81 6. The Role of Subjective Probability and Utility in Decision- Making (1956) 87 7. The Philosophical Relevance of Decision Theory (1961) 105 8. An Axiomatization of Utility Based on the Notion of Utility Differences (1955) (with Muriel Winet) 115 9. Behavioristic Foundations of Utility (1961) 130 10. Some Formal Models of Grading Principles (1966) 148 11. Probabilistic Inference and the Concept of Total Evidence (1966) 170 PART In: FOUNDATIONS OF PHYSICS 189 12. Axioms for Relativistic Kinematics with or without Parity (1959) 194 13. Probability Concepts in Quantum Mechanics (1961) 212 14. The Role of Probability in Quantum Mechanics (1963) 227 XII CONTENTS 15. The Probabilistic Argument for a Nonc1assical Logic of Quantum Mechanics (1966) 243 PART IV: FOUNDATIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY 253 16. Stimulus-Sampling Theory for a Continuum ofResponses (1960) 261 17. On an Example of Unpredictability in Human Behavior (1964) 285 18. Behaviorism (1965) 294 19. On the Behavioral Foundations of Mathematical Concepts (1965) 312 20. Towards a Behavioral Foundation of Mathematical Proofs (1965) 355 21. The Psychological Foundations of Mathematics (1967) 371 22. On the Theory of Cognitive Processes (1966) 394 23. Stimulus-Response Theory of Finite Automata (1969) 411 REFERENCES 445 INDEX OF NAMES 454 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 457 PART I METHODOLOGY: MODELS AND MEASUREMENT The five papers in this part examine some of the many issues surrounding the general use of models in empirical science, and also the conceptual foundations of the theory of measurement. In discussing both the general use of models and the particular case of measurement, I have tried to show in these papers how set-theoretical tools standard in modern mathematics can also be used to good advantage
Recommended publications
  • The Darwinian Revolution As Evidence for Thomas Kuhn's
    The Darwinian Revolution as Evidence for Thomas Kuhn’s Failure to Construct a Paradigm for the Philosophy of Science Kuhn’s goal in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions is to propose his ideas as a paradigm for the philosophy of science. He disapproves of the “textbook model” of scientific history in which all discoveries follow the simplified pattern of observation, hypothesis, experimentation, and acceptance (Kuhn 1). Instead, Kuhn proposes an original examination of the process by which scientific ideas evolve. If Kuhn’s ideas are indeed a paradigm, they must possess the paradigmatic characteristics that he describes. One of these characteristics is explanatory power for all observations; Kuhn’s suggestion must describe accurately the form taken by all scientific revolutions. If a scientific revolution occurred that does not follow Kuhn’s structure, then the structure is flawed. In his essay titled “The Kuhnian Paradigm and the Darwinian Revolution in Natural History,” John C. Greene attempts to fit the Darwinian Revolution to Kuhn’s ideas. However, he must contort his discussion of this scientific revolution to force it to conform to Kuhn’s suggestion. Because Kuhn’s structure fails to describe satisfactorily the form of the Darwinian Revolution, Kuhn has not formulated a paradigm for the philosophy of science. Kuhn’s ideas can be evaluated for paradigm status only if his field is a science; therefore we must establish a definition for science under which to examine Kuhn’s proposal. Perhaps the definition that most clearly applies to Kuhn’s field is Ernest Nagel’s: “the sciences seek to discover and to formulate in general terms the conditions under which events of various sorts occur” (Nagel 4).
    [Show full text]
  • “Thomas Kuhn.” in “The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy”, Edward Zalta, Ed
    Thomas Kuhn Reference: Bird, Alexander, 2005: “Thomas Kuhn.” In “The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy”, Edward Zalta, Ed. (online at plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2005/entries/thomas-kuhn ) Thomas Samuel Kuhn (1922-1996) became the one of most influential philosophers of science of the twentieth century, perhaps the most influential—his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions is one of the most cited academic books of all time. His contribution to the philosophy science marked not only a break with several key positivist doctrines but also inaugurated a new style of philosophy of science that brought it much closer to the history of science. His account of the development of science held that science enjoys periods of stable growth punctuated by revisionary revolutions, to which he added the controversial ‘incommensurability thesis’, that theories from differing periods suffer from certain deep kinds of failure of comparability. • 1. Life and Career • 2. The Development of Science • 3. The Paradigm Concept • 4. Perception, World-Change, and Incommensurability _ 4.1 Methodological Incommensurability _ 4.2 Perception, Observational Incommensurability, and World-Change _ 4.3 Kuhn's Early Semantic Incommensurability Thesis _ 4.4 Kuhn's Later Semantic Incommensurability Thesis • 5. History of Science • 6. Criticism and Influence _ 6.1 Scientific Change _ 6.2 Incommensurability _ 6.3 Kuhn and Social Science _ 6.4 Assessment • Bibliography • Other Internet Resources • Related Entries 1. Life and Career Thomas Kuhn's academic life started in physics. He then switched to history of science, and as his career developed he moved over to philosophy of science, although retaining a strong interest in the history of physics.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL-2031: Philosophy of Science 1
    PHIL-2031: Philosophy of Science 1 PHIL-2031: PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Cuyahoga Community College Viewing: PHIL-2031 : Philosophy of Science Board of Trustees: March 2019 Academic Term: Fall 2021 Subject Code PHIL - Philosophy Course Number: 2031 Title: Philosophy of Science Catalog Description: Study of concept formation in science and examination of patterns of scientific investigation and method. Treatment of concepts such as observation, classification, causality, law of nature, explanation, and theory. Credit Hour(s): 3 Lecture Hour(s): 3 Requisites Prerequisite and Corequisite ENG-1010 College Composition I, or ENG-101H Honors College Composition I. Outcomes Course Outcome(s): Analyze and explain philosophy of science concepts and their relationship to scientific inquiry. Essential Learning Outcome Mapping: Critical/Creative Thinking: Analyze, evaluate, and synthesize information in order to consider problems/ideas and transform them in innovative or imaginative ways. Objective(s): 1. Evaluate the objectivity of observation claims. 2. Describe and appraise the logic of scientific classification. 3. Define and assess the concept of law of nature. 4. Critically analyze types of scientific explanation and criteria for their evaluation. Course Outcome(s): Apply philosophical conceptions and theory to a philosophical issue in science and successfully argue for a position taken on it. Essential Learning Outcome Mapping: Critical/Creative Thinking: Analyze, evaluate, and synthesize information in order to consider problems/ideas and transform them in innovative or imaginative ways. Information Literacy: Acquire, evaluate, and use information from credible sources in order to meet information needs for a specific research purpose. Written Communication: Demonstrate effective written communication for an intended audience that follows genre/disciplinary conventions that reflect clarity, organization, and editing skills.
    [Show full text]
  • International Journal of Science and Technology (STECH) Bahir Dar- Ethiopia Vol
    IAARR 57 International Journal of Science and Technology Vol. 7 (1) February, 2018 International Journal of Science and Technology (STECH) Bahir Dar- Ethiopia Vol. 7 (1), S/No15, February, 2018: 57-71 ISSN: 2225-8590 (Print) ISSN 2227-5452 (Online) DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/stech.v7i1.5 SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION, INCOMMENSURABILITY AND TRUTH IN THEORIES: OBJECTION TO KUHN’S PERSPECTIVE IHEJIRIKA, CARDINAL, PhD DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PORT HARCOURT, NIGERIA PHONE: +2348028279646 E-mail: [email protected] ……………………………………………………………………….. EMEDOLU, CHRISTIAN C., PhD DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PORT HARCOURT, NIGERIA PHONE: +2348035517505 E-mail: [email protected] …………………………………………………………………………………………… ABSTRACT This is to revaluate the truth-content of scientific theory in the event of scientific revolution. In this paper, we argued that the radical views on incommensurability offered, especially, by Thomas S. Kuhn (shared by Paul Feyerabend, and others) do not actually undermine either the realist or cumulative stature of science. The core of our discussion is, ultimately, to provide a clearer and broader picture of the general characteristics of scientific revolution or theory change. In doing this, the paper pinpoints the audacity behind this change and the nature of truth undergirding any emergent or overthrown scientific theory. The paper has some rebounding echoes of the realist and cumulative features of science while addressing the issue of the real character of theory change. Following some unique interpretations of scientific revolution, truth in science could still be redeemed in the face of theory change and Kuhnian Incommensurability Thesis. To this effect, the hermeneutical approach is considered most suitable in this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap Visits Canberra: Updating the Logical Positivist Criteria of Cognitive Significance
    CARNAP VISITS CANBERRA: UPDATING THE LOGICAL POSITIVIST CRITERIA OF COGNITIVE SIGNIFICANCE A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts by Andrew Whiteley Magrath May 2012 Thesis written by Andrew Whiteley Magrath B.A., Oberlin College, 2004 M.A., Kent State University, 2012 Approved by Deborah C. Smith___________________________, Advisor David Odell-Scott___________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Timothy Moerland___________________________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS………………………………………………………………v CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 1 Logical Positivism and the Canberra Plan: A Brief Introduction............... 1 Guiding Question & Structure of the Thesis............................................... 3 My Motivation ............................................................................................ 4 Structure & Methodological Considerations .............................................. 6 II. CARNAP AND LOGICAL POSITIVISM............................................................. 8 The Use of Logic in Positivism .................................................................. 8 The Positivists' Reductionism & Expressibility.......................................... 9 A Theory of Meaning: Analytic a Priori and Synthetic a Posteriori......... 11 Ramsification: Observation Terms and Theory Terms............................
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science* Peter Machamer
    Chapter 1 A Brief Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science* Peter Machamer Philosophy of science is an old and practiced discipline. Both Plato and Aristotle wrote on the subject, and, arguably, some of the pre-Socratics did also. The Middle Ages, both in its Arabic and high Latin periods, made many commentaries and disputations touching on topics in philosophy of science. Of course, the new science of the seventeenth century brought along widespread ruminations and manifold treatises on the nature of science, scientific knowledge and method. The Enlightenment pushed this project further trying to make science and its hallmark method definitive of the rational life. With the industrial revolution, “science” became a synonym for progress. In many places in the Western world, science was venerated as being the peculiarly modern way of thinking. The nine- teenth century saw another resurgence of interest when ideas of evolution melded with those of industrial progress and physics achieved a maturity that led some to believe that science was complete. By the end of the century, mathematics had found alternatives to Euclidean geometry and logic had become a newly re-admired discipline. But just before the turn to the twentieth century, and in those decades that fol- lowed, it was physics that led the intellectual way. Freud was there too, he and Breuer having published Studies in Hysteria in 1895, but it was physics that gar- nered the attention of the philosophers. Mechanics became more and more unified in form with the work of Maxwell, Hertz and discussions by Poincaré. Plank derived the black body law in 1899, in 1902 Lorenz proved Maxwell’s equations were invariant under transformation, and in 1905 Einstein published his paper on special relativity and the basis of the quantum.
    [Show full text]
  • ERNEST NAGEL November 16, 1901-September 20, 1985
    NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES E R N E S T N AGEL 1901—1985 A Biographical Memoir by P A T R I C K S UPPES Any opinions expressed in this memoir are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Academy of Sciences. Biographical Memoir COPYRIGHT 1994 NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES WASHINGTON D.C. ERNEST NAGEL November 16, 1901-September 20, 1985 BY PATRICK SUPPES RNEST NAGEL was born November 16, 1901, in Nove Mesto, EBohemia (now part of Czechoslovakia) and came to the United States when he was ten years old. He became a naturalized U.S. citizen in 1919, and received his higher education entirely in the United States. In 1923 he received a Bachelor of Science from the College of the City of New York, in 1925 a Master's Degree in philosophy from Colum- bia University, and in 1931, a Ph.D. in philosophy from Columbia. He spent most of his academic career at Colum- bia. He was on the faculty there from 1931 to 1970, with the exception of the academic year 1966-67 when he ac- cepted a position at Rockefeller University. From 1967 to 1970 he held the position of university professor at Colum- bia, and he continued to be active in the intellectual affairs of the university after his retirement, including teaching seminars and courses. Ernest Nagel died in New York City on September 20, 1985. After his arrival in New York City in 1911, Nagel spent his entire life there, although he and his family regularly spent the summer in Vermont for many years.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Kuhn's Relativistic Legacy
    Thomas Kuhn’s Relativistic Legacy Abstract The work of Thomas Kuhn is often held to be the origin of much of the rela- tivism one finds in the philosophy of science and in science studies. Kuhn’s re- lationship to relativism is, however, complex. In this article I examine and assess potential sources of relativism in (i) the paradigm concept; (ii) incommensura- bility; (iii) Kuhn’s argument that truth is transcendent; (iv) Kuhn’s claims about ‘world-change’. I conclude by looking at Kuhn’s relativistic influence on the his- tory of science and the sociology of science. 1 Introduction Relativism is an issue of considerable interest in the philosophy of science. As else- where, this originates in large measure with arguments of a sceptical nature or which regard realism as leading to scepticism. In philosophy of science the relevant argu- ments are those that suggest that science does not deliver truth. For example the pessimistic (meta-)induction argues that the falsity of past theories is a reason to doubt that current theories are true. If that conclusion is correct about even our best theories, then the notion of (objective) truth employed in this argument cannot be a useful one for the evaluation of theories. In the light of this it is tempting to look for a standard of evaluation that is not objective and absolute but is relative. A pop- ular response to the pessimistic induction is to consider scientific progress in terms of increasing nearness to the truth (verisimilitude), which would retain an objective standard of evaluation. However, some philosophers of science regard any standard related to objective truth, including verisimilitude, as transcendent.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism and Its Heuristics: Making Methodological Reductionism Honest
    Synthese DOI 10.1007/s11229-006-9017-0 ORIGINAL PAPER Reductionism and its heuristics: Making methodological reductionism honest William C. Wimsatt © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2006 Abstract Methodological reductionists practice ‘wannabe reductionism’. They claim that one should pursue reductionism, but never propose how. I integrate two strains in prior work to do so. Three kinds of activities are pursued as “reductionist”. “Succes- sional reduction” and inter-level mechanistic explanation are legitimate and powerful strategies. Eliminativism is generally ill-conceived. Specific problem-solving heuris- tics for constructing inter-level mechanistic explanations show why and when they can provide powerful and fruitful tools and insights, but sometimes lead to erroneous results. I show how traditional metaphysical approaches fail to engage how science is done. The methods used do so, and support a pragmatic and non-eliminativist realism. Keywords Aggregativity · Biases · Eliminativism · Heuristics · Identification · Inter-level explanation · Localization · Mechanism · Methodological reductionism · Problem-solving · Wannabe reductionism We take it for granted that human activity, including science, is purposive. Yet we have ignored this fact in our analysis of reductionistic activities. Or perhaps we have too easily taken for granted the time-honored aims of the unity of science and onto- logical economy. But these are aims of the metaphysician, and not, save perhaps in foundational projects of physics, those of most scientists. Scientists pursue more local goals, at several layers of increasing locality. I investigate them here. First I argue that there are two types of reduction, differentiated by function, which I call successional reduction and inter-level explanation. I here follow the lead of Thomas Nickles’ clas- sics 1973 paper, but in characterizing them functionally, I add other distinguishing features.
    [Show full text]
  • The Historical Developmental Perspective of Thomas S
    The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts THE HISTORICAL DEVELOPMENTAL PERSPECTIVE OF THOMAS S. KUHN: A SEARCH FOR FIRST PRINCIPLES IN THE DEVELOPMENT OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE OVER TIME A Thesis in Philosophy by Rebecca E. Wayland © 2003 Rebecca E. Wayland Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2003 The thesis of Rebecca E. Wayland was reviewed and approved* by the following: Daniel W. Conway Professor of Philosophy and Science, Technology and Society Thesis Advisor Chair of Committee Emily R. Grosholz Professor of Philosophy and Institute for Arts and Humanistic Studies Fellow John P. Christman Associate Professor of Philosophy and Women’s Studies James E. Martin Associate Professor of Psychology Mitchell S. Aboulafia Professor of Philosophy Head of the Department of Philosophy *Signatures are on file in the Graduate School. Abstract This dissertation reconsiders the work of Thomas S. Kuhn on the basis of what he characterized as the historical developmental perspective. The perspective examines the activities, processes and choices involved in the development of scientific knowledge over time. It reflects case-based, rather than rules- based reasoning and provides an alternative and insightful basis for discerning changes in knowledge, ideas, and assumptions over time. The historical developmental perspective guided Kuhn’s research activities throughout his career, and through those investigations, he developed and refined both the approach and the insights that it provided. Yet the unique aspects of Kuhn’s historical developmental perspective were not recognized by many of his readers – nor, to a great extent, were they appreciated fully by Kuhn himself.
    [Show full text]
  • So What Do We Really Mean When We Say That Systems Biology Is Holistic? Derek Gatherer
    Gatherer BMC Systems Biology 2010, 4:22 http://www.biomedcentral.com/1752-0509/4/22 CORRESPONDENCE Open Access So what do we really mean when we say that systems biology is holistic? Derek Gatherer Abstract Background: An old debate has undergone a resurgence in systems biology: that of reductionism versus holism.At least 35 articles in the systems biology literature since 2003 have touched on this issue. The histories of holism and reductionism in the philosophy of biology are reviewed, and the current debate in systems biology is placed in context. Results: Inter-theoretic reductionism in the strict sense envisaged by its creators from the 1930s to the 1960s is largely impractical in biology, and was effectively abandoned by the early 1970s in favour of a more piecemeal approach using individual reductive explanations. Classical holism was a stillborn theory of the 1920s, but the term survived in several fields as a loose umbrella designation for various kinds of anti-reductionism which often differ markedly. Several of these different anti-reductionisms are on display in the holistic rhetoric of the recent systems biology literature. This debate also coincides with a time when interesting arguments are being proposed within the philosophy of biology for a new kind of reductionism. Conclusions: Engaging more deeply with these issues should sharpen our ideas concerning the philosophy of systems biology and its future best methodology. As with previous decisive moments in the history of biology, only those theories that immediately suggest relatively easy experiments will be winners. Introduction time this argument has arisen, but we have been here An old debate has made a surprising, or perhaps not so before on several occasions.Thereductionist-holist surprising, reappearance in systems biology: that of debate emerged in biology in the 1920s out of the ear- reductionism versus holism.
    [Show full text]
  • Niels Bohr's 1913 Trilogy Revisited Abir
    Author Title Aaserud & Heilbron Love, Literature, and the Quantum Atom: Niels Bohr's 1913 Trilogy Revisited Abir-Am, Dhina & Elliot, Clark A Commemorative Practices in Science: Historical Perspectives on the Politics of Collective Memory Achinstein, Peter Concepts of Science: A Philosophical Analysis Achinstein, Peter The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science Achinstein, Peter Particles and Waves Ackerknecht, Erwin H History and Geography of the Most Important Diseases Ackermann, Robert Modern Deductive Logic: An Introduction to Its Techniques and Significance Ackermann, Robert Nondeductive Inference Ackermann, Robert The Philosophy of Science: An Introduction Ackermann, Robert The Philosophy of Science: An Introduction Adler, Irving The New Mathematics Adler, Irving Probability and Statistics for Everyman: How to Understand and Use the Laws of Chance Aiken, Henry The Age of Ideology Aitkens, Edith Elementary Textbook of Botany Albert, David Quantum Mechanics and Experience Albert, David Quantum Mechanics and Experience Alexander, Franz Scope of Psychoanalysis: Selected Papers Alexander, H G The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence Alexander, S Space, Time, and Deity, Vol I Alexander, S Space, Time, and Deity, Vol II Allee, W C Cooperation Among Animals: With Human Implications Allen, C W The Atom Allen, Mea Darwin and His Flowers: The Key to Natural Selection Allen, Thomas Managing the Flow of Technology Allendoerfer, Carl Principles of Mathematics Anderson, James Metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas Andersson, Malte
    [Show full text]