The Philosophical Works of A. J. Ayer

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Philosophical Works of A. J. Ayer The Philosophical Works of A. J. Ayer 1930 Review of The Art of Thinking by Dimnet, in Oxford Outlook. 1933 'Atomic Propositions', Analysis, vol. 1, no. I, pp. 2-6. 1934 'The Genesis of Metaphysics', Analysis, vol. I, no. 4, pp. 55-8, repr. in M. Macdonald (ed.), Philosophy and Analysis. 'On Particulars and Universals', Proceedings of the Aristote­ lian Society, vol. XXXIV, pp. 51-62. 'Demonstration of the Impossibility of Metaphysics', Mind, vol. XLIII, no. 171, pp. 335-45, repr. in P. Edwards and A. Pap (eds), A Modern Introduction to Philosophy (Glencoe, Illinois Free Press; London: George Allen and Unwin, 1957). 1935 'Internal Relations', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristo­ telian Society, vol. XIV, pp. 173-85. 'The Criterion of Truth', Analysis, vol. 3, nos I and 2, pp. 28-32. 'The Analytic Movement in Contemporary British Philos­ ophy', in Histoire de Ia logique et de Ia philosophie scienti.fique (Paris: Hermann). 1936 Language, Truth and Logic (London: Gollancz). 'The Principle of Verifiability, Mind, vol. XLV, no. 178, pp. 199-203. 'Concerning the Negation of Empirical Propositions', Erkenntnis, vol. 6, pp. 260--3. 'Truth by Convention', Analysis, vol. 4, nos 2 and 3, pp. 17-22. 'Freedom of the Will', The Aryan Path. Reviews of M. M. Lewis, Infant Speech; R. Aaron and A. Jocelyn Gibbs (eds), An Early Draft of Locke"s Essay; Alfred Noyce, Voltaire; all in the Spectator. 1937 'Verification and Experience', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. XXXVII, pp. 137-56. 'Does Philosophy Analyse Common Sense?', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. XVI, pp. 162-76. Review of 'Die Sogennanten Definitionen durch Abstraction' by H. Scholtz and H. Schweitzen, in Mind, vol. XLVI, no. 182, pp. 244-7. Bibliography 335 1938 'On the Scope of Empirical Knowledge: A Rejoinder to Bertrand Russell', Erkenntnis, vol. 7, pp. 267~74. 1940 The Foundations ofEmpirical Knowledge (London: Macmillan). 1944 'The Concept of Freedom', Horizon, vol. 9, no. 52, pp. 228~37. 1945 'The Terminology of Sense-Data', Mind, vol. LIV, no. 216, pp. 289~312, (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'Jean Paul Sartre', Horizon, vol. 12, no. 67, pp. 12~26. 'Deistic Fallacies', Polemic, no. 1. 'Secret Session' (on J.-P. Sartre), Polemic, no. 2, pp. 60~3. 1946 'Freedom and Necessity', Polemic, no. 5, pp. 36~44. (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'Other Minds', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. xx, pp. 188~97. 'Contemporary British Philosophers', the Listener. 'Albert Camus', Horizon, vol. 13, no. 75, pp. 155~68. 1947 'The Claims of Philosophy', in Polemic, no. 7, pp. 18~33. and Reflections on Our Age (Unesco). 'Phenomenalism', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. XLVII, pp. 163~96, (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). Thinking and Meaning, University College London Inaugural Lecture (Athlone Press). 1948 'The Principle of Utility' in G. W. Keeton and G. Schwarzen­ berger (eds), Jeremy Bentham and the Law (repr. in Philosophi­ cal essays, 1954). 'Portrait of a Victorian Liberal: J. S. Mill', the Listener. 'Science and Philosophy', the Listener. 'Some Aspects of Existentialism', Rationalist Annual. 'Discussion: Philosophy without Science', Philosophy, vol. 23, no. 84, pp. 65~6. 'What Can Logic Do for Philosophy', Supplementary Pro­ ceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. XXII, pp. 167~ 78. 1949 'On the Analysis of Moral Judgements', Horizon, vol. 20, no. 117, pp. 171~84. 'Mr. Koestler's New System', the New Statesman. 'Uber die Gedankenfreiheit', Der Monat. 'Ockham's Razor and Modern Philosophy', the Listener. 'There is no Mystery', the Listener. 1950 'Basic Propositions' in M. Black (ed.), Philosophical Analysis (Ithaca: Cornell University Press; repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954), pp. 60~75. 'J.-P. Sartre's Definition of Liberty', the Listener. 'Religion and the Intellectual', Partisan Revue. 1951 'Statements About the Past', Proceedings of the Aristotelian 336 Perception and Identity Society, vol. LII, pp. i-xx (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'On What There Is', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristo­ telian Society, vol. xxv, pp. 137-48 (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'The Physical Basis of Mind', BBC talks (Oxford: Basil Blackwell). 'The Philosophy of Science', in A. Heath ( ed. ), Scientific Thought in the 20th Century. 1952 British Empirical Philosophers, ed. with R. Winch (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul). 'Individuals', Mind, vol. LXI, no. 244, pp. 441-57 (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'Negation', Journal of Philosophy, vol. 49, no. 26, pp. 797-815 (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 1953 'Cogito Ergo Sum', Analysis, vol. 14, no. 2, pp. 27-31. 'To See the World Rightly', 20th Century. 'The Identity of Indiscernib.les', Proceedings of XIth Inter­ national Congress of Philosophy, vol. III, pp. 124-9 (North Holland Pub. Co., Amsterdam; repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954. 'L'Immutabilite du Passe', Etudes Philosophiques, no. 1, pp. 6-15. 'One's Knowledge of Other Minds', Theoria, vol. XIX, pp. 1-20 (repr. in Philosophical Essays, 1954). 'Truth', Revue internationale de philosophie, vol. 7, pp. 183-200 (repr. in The Concept of a Person and Other Essays, 1963). 1954 Philosophical Essays (London: Macmillan). 'Discussion of: "Sur la preuve en philosophie" ', Revue inter­ nationale de philosophie, vol. 8, pp. 92-105, pp. 158-69. 'Can There be a Private Language', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. XXVIII, pp. 63-76, (repr. in The Concept of a Person, 1963). 'Beyond the Pleasure Principle', Encounter. 1955 'What is Communication', Studies in Communic&tion, vol. I (London: Seeker and War burg). 'Philosophy at Absolute Zero', Encounter and Jamtid Ock Framted. 1956 'What is a Law of Nature', Revue internationale de philosophie vol. 10, pp. 144-65 (repr. in The Concept of a Person, 1963). 'The Vienna Circle', BBC Series: The Revolution in Philosophy (London: Macmillan). 'Philosophical Scepticism' in H. D. Lewis (ed.), Contemporary Bibliography 337 British Philosophy (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.). 'The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell', the Observer. 'Mr. Wilson's Outsider', Encounter. 'Le Memoire expose', Bulletin de Ia societe francaise de philos­ ophie (Paris). The Problem of Knowledge (London: Macmillan; USA: St Martin's Press; UK Penguin Books). 1957 'In Defense of Reason', Encounter. Reviews of: G. H. Von Wright, R. Rhees, G. E. M. Ans­ combe, Ludwig Wittenstein: Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics; A. Wood, Bertrand Russell: The Passionate Sceptic; Colin Wilson, Religion and the Rebel, in the Spec­ tator. 'Perception', C. A. Mace (ed.), British Philosophy in the Mid- Century (Allen and Unwin). · 'Logical Positivism', debate with Father Copleston in P. Edwards and A. Pap (eds), A Modern Introduction to Philos­ ophy (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd). 'The Concept of Probability as a Logical Relation' in S. Korner (ed.), Observation and Interpretation, Proceeding of 9th Symposium of Colston Research Society (New York: Dover). 1958 'Meaning and Intentionality', Proceedings of Xllth Congress of Philosophy, vol. r, pp. 141-55 (Sansoni Editore: Firenze). 'Philosophie et langage ordinaire', Dialectica. Biographies of Ernst Mach and Moritz Schlick, in Encyclo­ pedia Brittanica. Reviews in the Spectator of G. J. Warnock English Philosophy Since 1900; Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books; and Norman Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir 1959 Logical Positivism, ed. A. J. Ayer (Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press; London: Allen and Unwin). 'Privacy', British Academy Henriette Hertz Trust Lecture (Oxford: University Press; repr. in The Concept of a Person, 1963). 'Critical Notice of P. F. Strawson's Individuals', Indian Jour­ nal of Philosophy. 'Phenomenology and Linguistic Analysis', Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. xxxnr, pp. 111-24. Reviews in the Spectator of K. Popper The Logic of Scientific Discovery; Bertrand Russell, My Philosophical Development; Stuart Hampshire, Thought and Action; Ernest Gellner, Words and Thin~s. 1960 'The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell' in Concise Encyclopedia 338 Perception and Identity of Philosophy and Philosophers (London: Rain bird McLean Ltd). 'Philosophy and Language', Oxford University Inaugural Lec­ ture (Oxford University Press). 'Professor Malcolm on Dreams', Journal of Philosophy, vol. LVII, no. 16, pp. 517-35 (repr. in Metaphysics and Common Sense). 1961 'The Concept of a Person', Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture (repr. in The Concept of a Person, 1963). 'Reply to Mr. Stigen on Problem of Knowledge', Inquiry, vol. 4, pp. 291-304. 'Rejoinder to Professor Malcolm', Journal of Philosophy, vol. LXIII, no. 11, pp. 297-9. Review in Encounter of P. Thody, J.-P. Sartre. Review in Scientific American of E. Nagel, The Structure of Science. 'On the Probability of Particular Events' in Revue internationale de philosophie vol. 15, pp. 336-75 (repr. in The Concept of a Person, 1963). 1962 'Breaching the Dialectical Curtain - Philosophy in Russia', Observer. 'A History of Logic. The Ghost Revives', the New Statesman. 1963 'Impressions of Contemporary Russian Philosophy', Willesden Public Library, lectured and taped. 'The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell', Into the lOth Decade (London: Allen and Unwin). 'Carnap's Treatment of Other Minds' in A. Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap (Evan ton, Illinois, USA: Northwestern University Press). 'Brain, Mind and Memory', the Sunday Times. 'Philosophy and Science' Ratio, vol. v, no. 2, pp. 156-67 (first published in Russian
Recommended publications
  • Natural Kinds and Concepts: a Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account
    Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account Ingo Brigandt Abstract: In this chapter I lay out a notion of philosophical naturalism that aligns with prag- matism. It is developed and illustrated by a presentation of my views on natural kinds and my theory of concepts. Both accounts reflect a methodological naturalism and are defended not by way of metaphysical considerations, but in terms of their philosophical fruitfulness. A core theme is that the epistemic interests of scientists have to be taken into account by any natural- istic philosophy of science in general, and any account of natural kinds and scientific concepts in particular. I conclude with general methodological remarks on how to develop and defend philosophical notions without using intuitions. The central aim of this essay is to put forward a notion of naturalism that broadly aligns with pragmatism. I do so by outlining my views on natural kinds and my account of concepts, which I have defended in recent publications (Brigandt, 2009, 2010b). Philosophical accounts of both natural kinds and con- cepts are usually taken to be metaphysical endeavours, which attempt to develop a theory of the nature of natural kinds (as objectively existing entities of the world) or of the nature of concepts (as objectively existing mental entities). However, I shall argue that any account of natural kinds or concepts must an- swer to epistemological questions as well and will offer a simultaneously prag- matist and naturalistic defence of my views on natural kinds and concepts. Many philosophers conceive of naturalism as a primarily metaphysical doc- trine, such as a commitment to a physicalist ontology or the idea that humans and their intellectual and moral capacities are a part of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Giving up the Enkratic Principle
    Giving Up the Enkratic Principle (forthcoming in Logos and Episteme) The Enkratic Principle enjoys something of a protected status as a requirement of rationality. I argue that this status is undeserved, at least in the epistemic domain. Compliance with the principle should not be thought of as a requirement of epistemic rationality, but rather as defeasible indication of epistemic blamelessness. To show this, I present the Puzzle of Inconsistent Requirements, and argue that the best way to solve this puzzle is to distinguish two kinds of epistemic evaluation – requirement and appraisal. This allows us to solve the puzzle while accommodating traditional motivations for thinking of the Enkratic Principle as a requirement of rationality. Keywords: Enkratic Principle; coherence; evidence; rationality 1. The Enkratic Principle The Enkratic Principle demands coherence. In the epistemic domain, it demands coherence between the agent’s beliefs about which epistemic attitudes she ought to have, and her first- order1 epistemic attitudes2. According to the orthodox view, the Enkratic Principle is a 1 ‘First-order’ is not the ideal term. By ‘first-order’ I mean epistemic attitudes whose content does not concern what we ought, rationally, to believe. 2 These could include believing, disbelieving, refraining from believing, suspending, or having a particular credence in a proposition. 1 requirement of epistemic rationality3. Reading O as “rationally required”, Φ as representing a doxastic attitude, and B as representing belief, the principle can be stated as follows: Enkratic Principle: O (BOΦ → Φ) The Enkratic Principle says that rationality requires either having the attitudes you believe you ought to have, or giving up the belief that you ought to have those attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • Would ''Direct Realism'' Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction?
    NOU^S 38:2 (2004) 197–232 Would ‘‘Direct Realism’’ Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction? MARC LANGE University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill I Recently, there has been a modest resurgence of interest in the ‘‘Humean’’ problem of induction. For several decades following the recognized failure of Strawsonian ‘‘ordinary-language’’ dissolutions and of Wesley Salmon’s elaboration of Reichenbach’s pragmatic vindication of induction, work on the problem of induction languished. Attention turned instead toward con- firmation theory, as philosophers sensibly tried to understand precisely what it is that a justification of induction should aim to justify. Now, however, in light of Bayesian confirmation theory and other developments in epistemology, several philosophers have begun to reconsider the classical problem of induction. In section 2, I shall review a few of these developments. Though some of them will turn out to be unilluminating, others will profitably suggest that we not meet inductive scepticism by trying to justify some alleged general principle of ampliative reasoning. Accordingly, in section 3, I shall examine how the problem of induction arises in the context of one particular ‘‘inductive leap’’: the confirmation, most famously by Henrietta Leavitt and Harlow Shapley about a century ago, that a period-luminosity relation governs all Cepheid variable stars. This is a good example for the inductive sceptic’s purposes, since it is difficult to see how the sparse background knowledge available at the time could have entitled stellar astronomers to regard their observations as justifying this grand inductive generalization. I shall argue that the observation reports that confirmed the Cepheid period- luminosity law were themselves ‘‘thick’’ with expectations regarding as yet unknown laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Isaiah Berlin in China1
    Reading Isaiah Berlin in China1 A year before his death in 1997, Isaiah Berlin was invited by a Chinese scholar named Ouyang Kang to write a summary of his thought for the Chinese reading public. Berlin, as Dr Henry Hardy recalls, much valued this new readership, and therefore wrote his last essay, ‘My Intellectual Path’. It was first published in English in the New York Review of Books, and then included in The Power of Ideas, an anthologies edited by Hardy.2 Eight years later, this piece finally received its Chinese translation. According to Ouyang Kang, his incentive is to edit a book composed of intellectual self-portraits by several distinguished Anglophone philosophers as a way to introduce contemporary Anglophone philosophy to common readers in China. Ironically, when Ouyang’s volume was published, many of Berlin’s writings had already been translated and his thought been made accessible to the general public.3 Unlike his Oxford colleague, the historian Hugh Trevor-Roper, Isaiah Berlin never went to China; nor did he write anything directly related to it. Although he sometimes mentioned China in passing, he seemed not to have known much about either its history or its status quo, and he probably viewed it, along with India and Japan, as an old, mysterious and exotic civilisation. Among his interlocutors, Joseph Alsop had served in the ‘Flying Tigers’ commanded by C.L. Chennault in fighting the Japanese. After the Communist Party took power by defeating Chiang Kai-shek’s army in 1949, thus ending a civil war lasted for three years, China became a Communist regime, which borrowed its totalitarian system entirely from the Soviet Union.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Pardubice Faculty of Arts and Philosophy Truth in the Works of George Orwell Petr Škaroupka Diploma Thesis 2020
    University of Pardubice Faculty of Arts and Philosophy Truth in the Works of George Orwell Petr Škaroupka Diploma Thesis 2020 Prohlašuji: Tuto práci jsem vypracoval samostatně. Veškeré literární prameny a informace, které jsem v práci využil, jsou uvedeny v seznamu použité literatury. Byl jsem seznámen s tím, že se na moji práci vztahují práva a povinnosti vyplývající ze zákona č. 121/2000 Sb., o právu autorském, o právech souvisejících s právem autorským a o změně některých zákonů (autorský zákon), ve znění pozdějších předpisů, zejména se skutečností, že Univerzita Pardubice má právo na uzavření licenční smlouvy o užití této práce jako školního díla podle § 60 odst. 1 autorského zákona, a s tím, že pokud dojde k užití této práce mnou nebo bude poskytnuta licence o užití jinému subjektu, je Univerzita Pardubice oprávněna ode mne požadovat přiměřený příspěvek na úhradu nákladů, které na vytvoření díla vynaložila, a to podle okolností až do jejich skutečné výše. Beru na vědomí, že v souladu s § 47b zákona č. 111/1998 Sb., o vysokých školách a o změně a doplnění dalších zákonů (zákon o vysokých školách), ve znění pozdějších předpisů, a směrnicí Univerzity Pardubice č. 7/2019 Pravidla pro odevzdávání, zveřejňování a formální úpravu závěrečných prací, ve znění pozdějších dodatků, bude práce zveřejněna prostřednictvím Digitální knihovny Univerzity Pardubice. V Pardubicích dne 20.4.2020 Petr Škaroupka ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank Mgr. Michal Kleprlík, Ph.D for accepting this diploma thesis and his valuable suggestions during the writing process. ANNOTATION This diploma thesis focuses on Orwell’s views on truth in his written works. With the aid of the contemporary philosophical literature, the notion of truth, as well as related epistemological and metaphysical issues and concepts, are described in the first part of the paper.
    [Show full text]
  • (Review Published in the Times Literary Supplement, January 16 2015, 5833, Pp. 22-23) Peter Unger EMPTY IDEAS: a CRITIQUE OF
    (Review published in The Times Literary Supplement, January 16 2015, 5833, pp. 22-23) Peter Unger EMPTY IDEAS: A CRITIQUE OF ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY 258pp. Oxford University Press. £29.99 978 0 19 933081 2 by Timothy Williamson Metaphysics is back in fashion, at least in the analytic tradition that dominates English- speaking philosophy and is growing rapidly across the rest of the world too. It’s quite a turnaround. In the mid-twentieth century, the analytic tradition had two main strands: logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy. The logical positivists dismissed metaphysics as cognitively meaningless, unverifiable by observation and logic. Ordinary language philosophers tended to be equally suspicious, diagnosing metaphysical speculation as the pathological result of using words outside the down-to-earth contexts that gave them meaning. But things have changed. These anti-metaphysical arguments rested on assumptions about meaning that have not withstood the test of time. Moreover, the resurgence of metaphysics was led by philosophers such as Saul Kripke and David Lewis, who wrote so clearly and intelligibly about essential properties (think Aristotle), possible worlds (think Leibniz), and the like that the charge of meaninglessness just would not stick. Contemporary analytic metaphysicians see themselves as theorizing boldly and systematically about the deepest and most general nature of reality. In Peter Unger’s view, they are deluded: far from resuming pre-Kantian metaphysics in the grand old style, they do little more than play with words. Their ideas are mostly empty. Indeed, he widens the charge to analytic philosophy more generally. Nor does he think better of non-analytic philosophy; he just has no time for it.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Language and Verificationism
    © Michael Lacewing Religious language and verificationism AYER’S ARGUMENT In the 1930s, a school of philosophy arose called logical positivism, concerned with the foundations and possibility of knowledge. It developed a criterion for meaningful statements, called the principle of verification. On A J Ayer’s version (Language, Truth and Logic), the principle of verification states that a statement only has meaning if it is either analytic or empirically verifiable. (can be shown by experience to be probably true/false). ‘God exists’, and so all other talk of God, is such a statement, claims Ayer. Despite the best attempts of the ontological argument, we cannot prove ‘God exists’ from a priori premises using deduction alone. So ‘God exists’ is not analytically true. Therefore, to be meaningful, ‘God exists’ must be empirically verifiable. Ayer argues it is not. If a statement is an empirical hypothesis, it predicts our experience will be different depending on whether it is true or false. But ‘God exists’ makes no such predictions. So it is meaningless. Some philosophers argue that religious language attempts to capture something of religious experience, although it is ‘inexpressible’ in literal terms. Ayer responds that whatever religious experiences reveal, they cannot be said to reveal any facts. Facts are the content of statements that purport to be intelligible and can be expressed literally. If talk of God is non-empirical, it is literally unintelligible, hence meaningless. Responses We can object that many people do think that ‘God exists’ has empirical content. For example, the argument from design argues that the design of the universe is evidence for the existence of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Methodology for Ontology Based Model Engineering
    Towards a methodology for ontology based model engineering Nicola Guarino and Christopher Welty† LADSEB/CNR Padova, Italy {guarino,welty}@ladseb.pd.cnr.it http://www.ladseb.pd.cnr.it/infor/ontology/ontology.html Phone: +39 049 829 57 51 Fax: +39 049 829 57 63 † on sabbatical from Vassar College, Poughkeepsie, NY Abstract The Formal Tools of Ontological Analysis The philosophical discipline of Ontology is evolving towards an engineering discipline, and in this evolution the Our methodology is based on four fundamental ontologi- need for a principled methodology has clearly arisen. In cal notions, which will be discussed in this section: identity, this paper, we briefly discuss our recent work towards devel- unity, rigidity, and dependence. We shall represent the oping a methodology for ontology-based model engineering. behavior of a property with respect to these notions by This methodology builds on previous methodology efforts, means of a set of meta-properties. Our goal is to show how and is founded on important analytic notions that have been these meta-properties impose some constraints on the way drawn from Philosophy and adapted to Engineering: identity, subsumption is used to model a domain. unity, rigidity, and dependence. We demonstrate how these techniques can be used to analyze properties, which clarifies many misconceptions about taxonomies and helps bring substantial order to ontologies. Preliminaries Let’s assume we have a first-order language L0 (the model- Introduction ing language) whose intended domain is the world to be modeled, and another first order language (the meta-lan- Ontologies are becoming increasingly popular in prac- L1 tice, and the number of poor quality ontologies have made guage) whose constant symbols are the predicates of L0.
    [Show full text]
  • Out of Sorts? Remedies for Theories of Object
    Out of Sorts? Some Remedies for Theories of Object Concepts: A Reply to Rhemtulla and Xu Sergey V. Blok University of Texas at Austin George E. Newman Yale University Lance J. Rips Northwestern University Psychological Review, in press. Out of Sorts? / 2 Abstract Concepts of individual objects (e.g., a favorite chair or pet) include knowledge that allows people to identify these objects, sometimes after long stretches of time. In an earlier article, we set out experimental findings and mathematical modeling to support the view that judgments of identity depend on people’s beliefs about the causal connections that unite an object’s earlier and later stages. In this article, we examine Rhemtulla and Xu’s (in press) critique of the causal theory. We argue that Rhemtulla and Xu’s alternative sortal proposal is not a necessary part of identity judgments, is internally inconsistent, leads to conflicts with current theories of categories, and encounters problems explaining empirical dissociations. Previous evidence also suggests that causal factors dominate spatiotemporal continuity and perceptual similarity in direct tests. We conclude that the causal theory provides the only existing account consistent with current evidence. Keywords: Concepts Causation Sortals Object concepts Out of Sorts? / 3 Out of Sorts? Some Remedies for Theories of Object Concepts: A Reply to Rhemtulla and Xu Many objects persist over stretches of time too long for us to track perceptually. If you attend your thirtieth high school reunion, you’re bound to run into classmates like Fred Lugbagg whom you haven’t encountered since graduation and whose perceptual appearance is no more similar to the 18-year- old Lugbagg than is the appearance of most of the other males at the reunion.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science -----Paulk
    PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE -----PAULK. FEYERABEND----- However, it has also a quite decisive role in building the new science and in defending new theories against their well-entrenched predecessors. For example, this philosophy plays a most important part in the arguments about the Copernican system, in the development of optics, and in the Philosophy ofScience: A Subject with construction of a new and non-Aristotelian dynamics. Almost every work of Galileo is a mixture of philosophical, mathematical, and physical prin~ a Great Past ciples which collaborate intimately without giving the impression of in­ coherence. This is the heroic time of the scientific philosophy. The new philosophy is not content just to mirror a science that develops independ­ ently of it; nor is it so distant as to deal just with alternative philosophies. It plays an essential role in building up the new science that was to replace 1. While it should be possible, in a free society, to introduce, to ex­ the earlier doctrines.1 pound, to make propaganda for any subject, however absurd and however 3. Now it is interesting to see how this active and critical philosophy is immoral, to publish books and articles, to give lectures on any topic, it gradually replaced by a more conservative creed, how the new creed gener­ must also be possible to examine what is being expounded by reference, ates technical problems of its own which are in no way related to specific not to the internal standards of the subject (which may be but the method scientific problems (Hurne), and how there arises a special subject that according to which a particular madness is being pursued), but to stan­ codifies science without acting back on it (Kant).
    [Show full text]
  • Putnam's Theory of Natural Kinds and Their Names Is Not The
    PUTNAM’S THEORY OF NATURAL KINDS AND THEIR NAMES IS NOT THE SAME AS KRIPKE’S IAN HACKING Collège de France Abstract Philosophers have been referring to the “Kripke–Putnam” theory of natural- kind terms for over 30 years. Although there is one common starting point, the two philosophers began with different motivations and presuppositions, and developed in different ways. Putnam’s publications on the topic evolved over the decades, certainly clarifying and probably modifying his analysis, while Kripke published nothing after 1980. The result is two very different theories about natural kinds and their names. Both accept that the meaning of a natural- kind term is not given by a description or defining properties, but is specified by its referents. From then on, Putnam rejected even the label, causal theory of reference, preferring to say historical, or collective. He called his own approach indexical. His account of substance identity stops short a number of objections that were later raised, such as what is called the qua problem. He came to reject the thought that water is necessarily H2O, and to denounce the idea of metaphysical necessity that goes beyond physical necessity. Essences never had a role in his analysis; there is no sense in which he was an essentialist. He thought of hidden structures as the usual determinant of natural kinds, but always insisted that what counts as a natural kind is relative to interests. “Natural kind” itself is itself an importantly theoretical concept, he argued. The paper also notes that Putnam says a great deal about what natural kinds are, while Kripke did not.
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq #142-144
    THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY QUARTERLY Fall 2009 Issue Numbers 142 -144 / May -November 2009 THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT Published by The Bertrand Russell Society with the support of Lehman College - City University of New York THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SoCIET¥ QUARTERLY is the official organ of the THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Bertrand Russell Society. It publishes Society news and proceedings, and QUARTERLY articles on the history of analytic philosophy, especially those on Russell's life and works, including historical materials and reviews of recent work on Fall 2009 Issue Russell. Scholarly articles appearing in the a"crrfer/,v are peer-reviewed. Numbers 142-144 / May -November 2009 Co-EDITORS: Rosalind Carey and John Ongley ASSOCIATE EDITOR: Ray Perkins Jr. EDITORIAL BOARD Rosalind Carey, Lehman College-CUNY THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT John Ongley, Bloomsburg University Raymond Perkins, Jr., Plymouth State University Christopher Pincock, Purdue University David Hyder, University of Ottawa CONTENTS Anat Biletzki, Tel Aviv University SuBMISsloNS : All communications to the Ber/ra#cJ Rwssc// Soci.edy gwcrr/er- In This Issue /y, including manuscripts. book reviews, and letters to the editor, should be Society News sent to: Prof. Rosalind Carey, Philosophy Department, Lehman College- ln Memoriam: Theo Meijer CUNY, 250 Bed ford Park Blvd. West, Bronx, NY 10468, USA, or by email to: [email protected]. Feature SuBSCRlpTloNS: The BRS gwc}rfedy is free to members of the Bertrand Rus- sell Society. Society membership is $35 a year for individuals, $40 for cou- Nicholas Griffin Speaks His Mind: An Interview by ples, and $20 for students and limited income individuals.
    [Show full text]