<<

Accommodating Retrocausality with Free Will

Yakir Aharonov 1,2, Eliahu Cohen 3,1 & Tomer Shushi 4

1 School of Physics and Astronomy, , Tel-Aviv, Israel. E-mail: eliahuco@[email protected] 2 Schmid College of Science, Chapman University, Orange, California, USA. E-mail: [email protected] 3 H.H. Wills Physics Laboratory, University of Bristol, Tyndall Avenue, Bristol, UK. E-mail: [email protected] 4 University of Haifa, Haifa 27019, Israel. E-mail: [email protected]

Editors: First Editor, Second Editor & Third Editor Article history: Submitted on Month Day, 2014; Accepted on Month Day, 2014; Published on Month Day, 2014.

etrocausal models of QM add further weight 1 Introduction to the conflict between causality and the pos- Rsible existence of free will. We analyze a sim- Time-symmetric formulations of QM are gaining growing ple closed causal loop ensuing from the interaction interest. Using two boundary conditions rather than the between two systems with opposing thermodynamic customary one, they offer novel twists to several foun- time arrows, such that each system can forecast “fu- dational issues. Such are the Wheeler-Feynman electro- ture” events for the other. The loop is avoided by the magnetic absorber theory [1], and Hoyle and Narlikar’s fact that the choice to abort an event thus forecasted modification [2] and Cramer’s transactional interpreta- leads to the destruction of the forecaster’s past. Phys- tion [3]. Among these, however, the ABL rule [4] and ical law therefore enables prophecy of future events Aharonov’s Two-State-Vector Formalism (TSVF) [5] are only as long as this prophecy is not revealed to a free distinct, in that they even predict some novel effects for a agent who can otherwise render it false. This reso- combination of forwards and backwards evolving wave lution is demonstrated on an earlier finding derived functions. When performing a complete post-selection from the Two-State-Vector Formalism (TSVF), where of the , otherwise counterfactual questions a weak measurement’s outcome anticipates a future can be intriguingly answered with regard to the state’s choice, yet this anticipation becomes apparent only previous time evolution. after the choice has been actually made. To quan- These advances, however, might seem come with a arXiv:1512.06689v1 [quant-ph] 21 Dec 2015 tify this assertion, “weak information” is described in price that even for adherents is too heavy, namely, dis- terms of Fisher information. We conclude that an “al- missing free will. While quantum indeterminism seemed ready existing” future does not exclude free will nor to offer some liberation from the chains imposed on our invoke causal paradoxes. On the quantum level, par- choices by classical causality, time-symmetric QM some- ticles can be thought of as weakly interacting accord- ing to their past and future states, but causality re- mains intact as long as the future is masked by quan- This is an open access article distributed under the terms tum indeterminism. of the Creative Commons Attribution License CC-BY-3.0, which Quanta 2015; 4: xx–yy. permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 1 what undermines quantum indeterminism, as it renders avoided by the past’s instability. We subsequently con- future boundary conditions the missing source of possible sider a more acute variant of this paradox and discuss causes. This might eventually reveal causality to be just a few possible resolutions. Then we present the quan- as strict and closed as classical causality. If the future tum counterpart of these two paradoxes where inherent is, in some sense, “already there” to the point of being indeterminism saves causality. We show that within the causally equal to the past, free will (which is defined TSVF, although both future and past states of the system in the next section) might appear to be as illusory as it are known, genuine freedom is not necessarily excluded. has appeared within the classical framework. We aim to We then define and quantify the term “weak information” show this is not necessarily the case. TSVF is no worse – the kind of information coming from the future that can off than classical physics, or other formulations of quan- be encrypted in the past without violating causality. tum as it pertains to the incorporation of free will. In other words, free will is not precluded even when discussing a quantum world having both past and future 3 An Interaction between Two boundary. Systems with Opposing In this special issue of Quanta, dedicated to Richard Time-Arrows Feynman and discussing time-symmetry in quantum me- chanics, we examine what might seem to be a problem in To demonstrate the possibility of knowing one’s future these formulations, namely the notion of free will [6]. Dis- and its consequences, we discuss a highly simplified clas- cussion of this kind might at first be regarded as philosoph- sical gedanken experiment. Naturally, there are immedi- ical in character, but we hope to formulate the problem ate difficulties with such a setup. Can, e.g., two regions in rigorously enough to yield nontrivial physical insights. space have opposite time arrows to begin with? Can ob- servers inside them communicate? etc. These questions 2 The Problem deserve further probing, but we focus here only on what would happen if several conditions are met, rather than whether and how they can be achieved. Following Russell and Deery [6], we propose defining Consider, then, a universe comprised of only two free will as follows. Let a physical system be capable of closed, non-interacting laboratories located at some dis- initiating complex interactions with its environment, gain- tance from one another. Suppose further that their ther- ing information about it and predicting its future states, as modynamic time arrows are opposite to one another, such well as their effects on the system itself. This grants the that each system’s “future” time direction is the other’s system purposeful behavior, which nevertheless fully ac- “past”. Finally let each laboratory host a free agent, hence- cords with classical causality. Now let there be more than forth Alice and Bob, capable of free choice. one course of action that the system can take in response to a certain event, which in turn lead to different future It is challenging to create a communication channel outcomes that the system can predict. “Free will” then between two laboratories of this kind. An exchange of denotes the system’s taking one out of various courses signals is possible in the following form. A light beam is of action, independently (at least to some extent) of past sent from the exterior part of one laboratory to the other’s restrictions. This definition is very close in spirit to the boundary, where a static message is posted. The beam is one employed in [7], i.e. the ability to make choices. It then reflected back to its origin. If the labs are massive should be emphasized that even in our time-symmetric enough, the beam imparts only a negligible momentum context, free will means only freedom from the past, not transfer. from the future (see also [5]). The gedanken experiment is as follows (see Fig. 1): t(b) In classical physics, conservation laws oblige any event 1 : Bob sends a light-beam (red arrow) to Alice’s lab. (b) to be strictly determined by earlier causes. In our con- t2 : He receives through his returning beam a message text, this might apparently leave only one course of action from Alice saying: “Let me know if you see this message” for the system in question, and hence no real choices. (dotted blue world-line). (b) When moving to the quantum realm, free will might be t3 : Bob posts a confirmation saying: “I saw your recovered [7], but then again, if one adds a final boundary message”(red world-line). condition to the description of the quantum system, can Then there are the following events in Alice’s lab: (a) free will exist? We shall answer both classical and quan- t1 : Alice sends a light-beam (blue arrow) to Bob’s tum questions on the affirmative, employing statistical lab. and quantum fluctuations, respectively. (a) t2 : Alice receives through her returning beam of par- In what follows, we analyze a classical causal paradox ticles that scattered off Bob’s message, i.e. she gets the

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 2 consistent answer is: Bob’s past. Upon Alice’s decision to remove her message at t(a)3, Bob’s “prophecy”, i.e. the message of Bob to Alice regarding her future choice, turns out to be false. This is clearly inconsistent with his earlier observation of Alice’s message, which is understood now to be highly unstable. His observation turns out to be a large (hence very rare) statistical fluctuation. We can now define the arrow of time of any system as the thermodynamic direction which is stable against changes. While a small change at the large system’s present will negligibly affect its future, it can have dra- matic effects into its past. Alice’s future was coupled in our example to Bob’s past. By employing her free will, she could completely alter his previous observations, but the apparent paradox is resolved by taking into account the chaotic nature of the entropy decreasing direction. Indeed, the signals are weak enough, which makes them amenable for this reinterpretation as fluctuations.

5 A More Acute Paradox

Figure 1: An illustration of the two labs gedanken experiment We shall now discuss an operationally simpler, yet con- with free agents. ceptually harder version of the paradox, which empha- sizes the role of free will. Let the two labs with opposing time arrows contain two simple machines rather than free information from Bob through this beam reflected from agents (see Fig. 2). One machine, A, posts 0 if it receives Bob’s system to her system. 0 as an input, and 1 if it receives 1. The second lab’s t(a): Alice, realizing that this confirmation comes from 3 machine, B, posts 1 if it receives 0 and 0 if it receives 1. her future, chooses not to post a message. The paradox is as follows: In case A receives 0 from the The Causal Paradox is obvious: The dotted blue world- other lab, it posts 0. Then B receives the 0 as an input and line represents an absent message. How, then, could Bob posts 1, in contrast to A’s earlier input. Alternatively, A reply to a message which was removed before he was receives 1 from B, then posts 1. Then, B receives this 1 supposed to see it? and posts 0, again in contrast to the A’s initial input. It should be noted, that alongside with this formula- It follows there are no valid initial conditions for this tion of the paradox, one can equivalently describe the combined system at a given time. complementary scenario: Bob finds through his return- The resolution may be: ing beam that Alice did not post a message. Therefore, (1) Communication is impossible between two such sys- he sends no confirmation, but eventually Alice, having tems. free will, decides to post a message in contrast to Bob’s (2) The past of both systems is symmetrically unstable. observation. (3) There must be some stochastic element allowing con- sistency. 4 The Suggested Resolution (4) The operations of the two machines must be coordi- nated. A key element in this causal paradox’s resolution is the As explained above, we assume that communication of following well-known fact: Entropy-increasing processes simple static messages is possible, hence we shall avoid are highly stable, not sensitive to small changes in their the first option (nevertheless, this paradox could actually initial conditions or their evolution, whereas entropy- suggest that a special communication protocol is needed decreasing processes are extremely vulnerable to any between two such systems with opposite time arrows). interference. Options (2) and (3) complement each other and resonate Our question therefore is: Which time direction is with the above notion of free will, as well as with the affected by Alice’s decision to change the “future”that quantum paradox to be presented below. Naturally, this “has been forecasted” by Bob? The simplest and most combination is favored by us. We believe this paradoxical

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 3 the next Section). However, since all the weak outcomes were classically recorded, upon slicing them according to the projective outcomes, one finds in retrospect, with extreme accuracy, the weak values corresponding to all Bell orientations (not only the ones eventually chosen for the projective measurement). The question is then, how could the values reside in the weak data prior to the Figure 2: An illustration of the two machines gedanken exper- final Bell measurements which demonstrated almost per- iment. The paradox is symmetric, but for simplicity it is shown fect non-local correlations? Bell’s proof certainly forbids to reside on the B side. them to be prepared in such a way so the TSVF answer would be they came from the future! The important point in this retrocausal interpretation is the weak values could situation could have been avoided if a minor degree of be there, that is, could had causal effect on the pointer’s freedom (e.g. at the form of free will) were allowed. In shift, without forcing a specific future outcome. contrast, alternative (4) implies (see The resolution is therefore simple: Quantum indeter- for instance [8,9]) or the so called “conspiracy” between minacy guarantees that, should someone try to abort a the two machines, which is philosophically disturbing (at future event about which they have received a prophecy, least in our view), negating free will altogether. that prophecy would turn out to be a mere error. Therefore, even in the TSVF where present is deter- 6 Going Quantum: The TSVF and mined by both past and future events, the quantum inde- terminism enables free will. Weak Measurements Naturally, more mundane explanations ought to be considered before concluding that results of weak mea- The possibility for resolving the above problem on classi- surement contain information regarding a future event. cal grounds encourages seeking more interesting avenues By normal causality, it should be Alice’s measurements at the quantum level. Indeed a similar resolution will which affected Bob’s, rather than vice versa. Perhaps, for be offered, i.e. the possibility of re-interpreting the past. example, some subtle bias induced by her weak measure- However, the basic concept on which the resolution re- ments affected his later strong ones. lies shifts from thermodynamic to quantum fluctuations Such a “past-to-future” effect is considerably strained which are more suitable for describing small microscopic by the following question: How robust is the alleged systems. This is where time-symmetric quantum causality bias introduced by the weak measurements? If it is ro- comes in most naturally. bust enough to oblige the strong measurements, then it is TSVF is a time-symmetric formulation of quantum me- equivalent to full collapse, namely the very local hidden chanics employing in addition to the forward evolving variables already ruled out by Bell’s inequality. This is (pre-selected state) also a backwards evolv- clearly not the case: weakly measured particles remain ing wave function (post-selected state). This combination nearly fully entangled. But then, even the weakest bias, as gives rise to the two-state-vector, which provides a richer long as it is expected to show up over a sufficiently large notion of quantum reality between two projective mea- N, is ruled out of the same grounds. The “weak bias” surements. This world-view has produced several predic- alternative is ruled out also by the robust correlations tions, so far well verified by weak measurements [10–13] predicted between all same-spin measurements, whether which delicately gather information about the quantum weak or strong. state without collapsing it, and thus do not change to Can Alice predict Bob’s outcomes on the basis of her post-selection probability. own data? To do that, she must feed all her rows of out- In an earlier work [13] the following gedanken experi- comes into a computer that searches for a possible series ment was proposed. A large ensemble of N EPR spins is of spin-orientation choices plus measurement outcomes, prepared. Each particle in every pair is weakly measured such that, when she slices her rows accordingly, she will along the three Bell orientations, before being strongly get the complex pattern of correlations described above. projected along one of them. As was shown, each weak The number of such possible sequences that she gets ! measurement only slightly disturbs the state and hence N N from her computation is ∝ √2 . Each such se- the well-known non-local correlations between the strong N/2 N outcomes are maintained in this experiment. It should be quence enables her to slice each of her rows into two N/2 noted that in return each weak measurement provides only halves and get the above correlations between her weak a negligible amount of information (to be quantified in measurements and the predicted strong measurements.

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 4 Notice that, according to√ Sec. 5, the results’ distribu-√ above. However, if Bob only tells her she will find an tion is a Gaussian with λ N/2 expectation and δ N/2 “up” result along some direction, no causal paradox will standard√ deviation, so a δ shift in one of the results, or ensue (see also [14]. This is the kind of weak information even in N of them, is very probable. Hence, even if which does not clash with Alice’s free will nor with Bob’s Alice computes all Bob’s possible future choices, she history. still cannot tell which choice he will take, because there are many similar subsets giving roughly the same value. Also, as Aharonov et al. pointed out in [13], when Al- 8 Fisher Information for Strong and ice finds a subset with a significant deviation from the Weak measurements expected 50%-50% distribution, its origin is much more likely, upon a real measurement by Bob, to turn out to Fisher information is a tool to quantify the hidden infor- be a measurement error than a genuine physical value. mation in a random variable Q regarding a parameter it Obviously, then, present data is insufficient to predict the depends on. Using Fisher information we can now quanti- future choice. tatively define the strong and weak information concepts that were qualitatively introduced in the Section above. Suppose there is an unknown parameter θ which we 7 The “strength” of Information want to estimate (θ can stand for, e.g., the relative phase Transmission between two superposed wave-packets). We define a den- sity function of Q by f , and another auxiliary parameter ∆ The information transmission between Alice and Bob which describes the type of information, strong or weak. can be categorized into two different types with different In probabilistic terms, it is called the “scale parameter” “strength”: of Q. In this case, Fisher information as a function of ∆, 1. Strong information: This type describes the infor- I∆(θ), is given by mation that, in general, has the potential to interfere with " #2   ∂  Alice’s free choice. This is the classical kind of informa-  |  I∆(θ):= E  ln f (∆Q; θ) θ . (1) tion transmitted in the first gedanken experiment. ∂θ 2.Weak information: In this case the information that It can be easily shown that I∆(θ) is in fact the product of Bob sends to Alice will not, in any circumstance, interfere ∆−1 and I(θ): with Alice’s free choice because it is buried much below " #2 the quantum uncertainty level. Z ∂ I (θ) = ln f (∆Q; θ) f (∆Q; θ) dQ (2) While the strong information transmission was dis- ∆ ∂θ cussed in Secs. 3-4 and was shown to cast instability into " #2 1 Z ∂ Bob’s past, it seems the weak information notion should = ln f (Q; θ) f (Q; θ) dQ (3) be further explained and quantified. ∆ ∂θ −1 We now understand that weak information represents = ∆ I(θ). (4) information that does not actively interfere with the Al- → ice’s and Bob’s systems. Therefore, weak information Now, in case of ∆ 0, we find can be described employing weak measurement outcomes −1 limI∆(θ) = lim∆ I(θ) = ∞, (5) since individually they only provide very partial infor- ∆→0 ∆→0 mation that does not interfere neither Alice’s nor Bob’s hence we conclude that ∆ → 0 indicates strong informa- system consistency. Similarly, strong information is re- tion. lated to projective measurement outcomes since they do The opposite case of ∆ → ∞ leads to disturb the systems and provide definite results. To create a clear distinction between the two kinds of −1 lim I∆(θ) = lim ∆ I(θ) = 0, (6) information, we shall discuss a simple thought experi- ∆→∞ ∆→∞ ment. Suppose Alice has a spin she wants to measure. which implies weak information, so for sufficient large To do that, she will use a Stern-Gerlach magnet with a value of ∆, weak information is described by a negligible non-homogeneous magnetic field along some direction. Fisher information. Bob, having an opposite time arrow, already knows that Let us now demonstrate this concept. Suppose that Alice will choose the z-axis and and will find an “up” θ is the relative phase between two superposed wave- outcome. If Bob sends this (strong) information to Al- packets, which we want to measure in some interference ice, she may choose the y-axis instead and find a “down” experiment. Let us assume that the interference pattern is outcome, reproducing the paradoxical situation discussed detected via some coupling 1/∆ to a measuring pointer.

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 5 If our estimation for the relative phase is described by a as in [21, 22] and was shown to naturally arise in post- Gaussian random variable Q, then the density function selected closed-timelike curves [23].   of Q will be f (Q; θ) = √1 exp − 1 Q2 . Depending 2πθ 2θ2 on the coupling strength, the Fisher information will be −1 −2 I∆(θ) = ∆ θ . 11 Free will and Becoming

Classical physics treats time as a purely geometrical in- 9 Cryptography Can Protect gredient of the universe, alongside the three spatial dimen- sions. Against the perfect logical rigor and experimental Causality support that make relativity so powerful, many find the “block universe” picture emerging from it man- Weak or encrypted information can be used for communi- ifestly awkward. In fact, the very notion of space-time cation between future and past in a causality preserving implies that, just as all locations have the same degree manner thanks to quantum indeterminism. The main idea of reality in space, so do all past, present, and future mo- behind this type of communication is quantum cryptogra- ments exist along the temporal dimension without any phy [15]. Suppose Bob somehow knows what Alice will moment being unique as the privileged “now ”. choose in the future. He uses a quantum cryptography Against this mainstream view, there are alternative ac- scheme to encode Alice’s future choice and gives her the counts [24]. They suspect that, if we experience time encrypted prophecy. However, he does not share with her so differently from space, this difference may be objec- the key to decode this revelation until she actually makes tive. They provide some models to capture this notion of her choice. In this case, similarly to the example in Sec. dynamic time. 6, both Bob’s past and Alice’s future are secured. Due to Bob’s access to Alice’s future in the classical gedanken quantum indeterminism, Alice still has free will. experiment above and the double boundary condition on For example, in the BB84 scheme [16], even though the wave function proposed by the TSVF may seem at Alice and Bob communicate through a public channel, first sight to resonate with a block universe approach. their secret key is secured due to another form of quantum However, as we have just seen, statistical and quantum indeterminism, namely, that non-orthogonal states are fluctuations may provide us with freedom to define the indistinguishable. This means that even if the generated present. As was shown in Secs. 4-5, this freedom, and string contains information regarding Eve’s future, it will also the notion of becoming, is subjective and system- not create a causal paradox. dependent. Within the TSVF, while both backward and forward states evolve deterministically, they have limited physical 10 A Few alternatives significance on their own — physical reality is created by the product of the causal chains extending in both In addition to the proposed resolution for the above para- temporal directions. The past does not determine the fu- doxes, there exist some other well-known possibilities. ture,yet the future is set, and only together do they form The parallel universe resolution suggests that if one goes the present. However, the existence of a future boundary back in time and kills his grandfather he actually does it condition,and its deterministic effect, do not deny our in a parallel universe and therefore he does not interfere freedom of choice. It is allowed due to the inaccessibility with the laws of nature [17, 18]. A different approach of the data (which is a requirement of causality, as dis- to solve this is by postulating another time dimension cussed in Sec. 5). Examining the concept of free will in which such disagreements can be solved before being from a physical point of view,we find it must contain at recorded in our history [19, 20]. least partial freedom from past causal constraints, and These two resolutions clearly lack simplicity and oblige such freedom is duly manifested in the TSVF, where a an excessive ontology to our existing theories. Moreover, juxtaposition of freedom and determinacy is epitomized. detailed work is needed to refute each and every paradox. Therefore, bearing in mind Occam’s razor as a tool for denying complex theories, it seems these alternative 12 Conclusions solutions are unfavorable. Another solution simply dictates that one cannot cre- We examined the possibility of free will in a retrocausal ate paradoxes in the universe and therefore cannot, for theory. Closed causal loops, which arise due to the inter- instance, kill his grandfather. This approach implies a action between two systems with opposing time arrows universe guided by global consistency condition such were discussed. The suggested resolution of the ensuing

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 6 paradoxes relies on the thermodynamic instability of the [6] Russell P, Deery O. The philosophy of free past. will: essential readings from the contemporary Moving to the quantum realm, a similar paradox can debates New-York: Oxford University Press, be solved via the quantum indeterminism, which is under- 2013. https://books.google.co.uk/books? stood to protect free will. This resonates with previous id=qEVpAgAAQBAJ. findings of Georgiev [7]. Furthermore, we discussed the [7] Georgiev D. Quantum no-go theorems and con- “strength” of information transmission, where the terms sciousness. Axiomathes 2013; 23 (4): 683– “strong” and “weak” are related to strong (projective) and 695. http://link.springer.com/article/ weak values, respectively. When information about a 10.1007/s10516-012-9204-1. future event is buried under quantum indeterminism it cannot violate free will. Similarly, encrypted information, [8] ’t Hooft G. The free-will postulate in quantum e.g., the one available through weak measurements, does mechanics. arXiv preprint quant-ph/0701097 2007. not violate causality. The existence of free will in these http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0701097. time symmetric models was conjectured to resonate with a dynamical notion of time. [9] ’t Hooft G. The cellular automaton interpretation of . A view on the quantum nature of our universe, compulsory or impossible? arXiv Acknowledgements preprint arXiv:1405.1548 2007. http://arxiv. org/abs/1405.1548. We thank A.C. Elitzur and Nissan Itzhaki for very helpful discussions. Y.A. and E.C. acknowledge support of the [10] Aharonov Y, Albert DZ, Vaidman L. How the result Israel Science Foundation Grant No. 1311/14 and ERC- of a measurement of a component of the spin of a AD NLST. Y.A. also acknowledges support from ICORE spin-1/2 particle can turn out to be 100. Physcal Excellence Center “Circle of Light”. Review Letters 1988 60(14): 1351–1354. doi:10. 1103/PhysRevLett.60.1351. References [11] Tamir B, Cohen E. Introduction to weak measure- ments and weak values. Quanta 2013 2(1): 7-17. [1] Wheeler JA, Feynman RP. Interaction with the doi:10.12743/quanta.v2i1.14. absorber as the mechanism of radiation. Reviews [12] Aharonov Y, Cohen E, Elitzur AC. Foundations of Modern Physics 1945 17(2–3): 157–161. doi: and applications of weak quantum measurements. 10.1103/RevModPhys.17.157. Physical Review A 2014 89(5): 052105. doi:10. [2] Hoyle F, Narlikar JV. A new theory of gravita- 1103/PhysRevA.89.052105. tion. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London- [13] Aharonov Y, Cohen E, Elitzur AC. Can a future Series A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineer- choice affect a past measurement’s outcome? An- doi: ing Sciences 1964 282(1389): 191–207. nals of Physics 2015 355: 258–268. doi:10.1016/ 10.1098/rspa.1964.0227 . j.aop.2015.02.020. [3] Cramer JG. The transactional interpretation of quan- [14] Elitzur AC, Cohen E, Shushi T. The too-late- tum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics 1986 choice experiment: Bell’s proof applied to a 58(3): 647–687. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.58. time-reversed setting. Forthcoming. http: 647. //www.ijqf.org/wps/wp-content/uploads/ 2015/07/Elitzur-IJQF-paper-2.pdf. [4] Aharonov Y, Bergmann PG, Lebowitz JL. Time symmetry in the quantum process of measurement. [15] Gisin N, Ribordy G, Tittel W, Zbinden H. Quantum Physivsl Review 1964; 134(6): B1410. doi:10. cryptography. Reviews of Modern Physics 2002 1103/PhysRev.134.B1410. 74(1): 145–195. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.74. 145 [5] Aharonov Y, Cohen E, Gruss E, Landsberger T. Measurement and collapse within the Two- [16] Bennett C, Brassard G. Quantum cryptography: State-Vector Formalism. Quantum Studies: Public key distribution and coin tossing. in Proceed- Mathematics and Foundations 2014; 1(1-2):133– ings of IEEE International Conference on Comput- 146. http://link.springer.com/article/ ers, Systems and Signal Processing 1984 175–179. 10.1007/s40509-014-0011-9. http://ci.nii.ac.jp/naid/20001457561

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 7 [17] Bousso R, Susskind L. Multiverse interpretation of quantum mechanics. Physical Review D 2012 85(4): 045007. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.85.045007.

[18] Deutsch D. The structure of the multiverse. Pro- ceedings of the Royal Society of London-Series A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 2002 458(2028): 2911–2923. doi:10.1098/rspa. 2002.1015.

[19] Bars I. Survey of two-time physics. Classical Quan- tum Gravity 2001 18(16): 3113. DOI:10.1088/ 0264-9381/18/16/303.

[20] Bars I, Terning J, Nekoogar F, Krauss LM. Ex- tra dimensions in space and time pp. 67–87 Heidelberg: Springer, 2010. doi:10.1007/ 978-0-387-77638-5.

[21] Carlini A, Frolov VP, Mensky MB, Novikov ID, Soleng HH. Time machines: the principle of self- consistency as a consequence of the principle of minimal action. International Journal of Modern Physics D 2012 4(05): 557–580. doi:10.1142/ S0218271895000399.

[22] Novikov ID. Time machine and self-consistent evo- lution in problems with self-interaction. Physical Review D 1992 45(6): 1989-1994. doi:10.1103/ PhysRevD.45.1989.

[23] Lloyd S, Maccone L, Garcia-Patron R, Giovannetti V, Shikano Y. Quantum mechanics of time travel through post-selected teleportation. Physical Review D 2011 84(2): 025007. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD. 84.025007.

[24] Aharonov Y, Popescu S, Tollaksen JM. Each instant of time a new universe. In Quantum Theory: A Two-Time Success Story, Struppa DC, Tollaksen JM (editors), pp. 21–36. Milan: Springer, 2014. 10. 1007/978-88-470-5217-8_3.

Quanta | DOI: 10.12743/quanta.xxx Month 2014 | Volume X | Issue Y | Page 8