Scanned Using Book Scancenter 5022

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Scanned Using Book Scancenter 5022 j' I 1 Hellenistic Philosophy Introductory Readings I J ! I Second Edition Translated, with Introduction and Notes, by J Brad Inwood and L. P. Gerson ■ I [ Hackett Publishing Company Indianapolis/Cambridge 11-92 to 11-94 Ethics 191 190 follow, he will nevertheless be forced to. The same thing happens in the Diogenes, Antipater and Posidonius. For Zeno of Citium and Cleanthes, case of men. Even if they do not want to follow, they will nevertheless as might be expected from earlier thinkers, made less elaborate distinctions be forced to go along with what has been destined. in their subject matter. But they did divide both logic and physics. 85? They say that an animal’s first [or primary] impulse is to preserve itself, because nature made it congenial to itself from the beginning, as Diogenianus in Eusebius Prep. Ev. 6.8, [11-93] Chrysippus says in book one of On Goals, stating that for every animal 265d-266d (SVF 2.998) its first [sense of] congeniality is to its own constitution and the reflective So in book one of his [Chrysippus’] On Fate he used proofs of this awareness of this. For it is not likely that nature would make an animal nature, and in book two he tries to resolve the absurdities which seem alienated from itself, nor having made the animal, to make it neither to follow on the thesis that all things are necessitated, which we listed congenial to nor alienated from itself. Therefore, the remaining possibility at the beginning: for example, the destruction of our own initiative is to say that having constituted the animal she made it congenial to concerning criticism and praise and encouragement and everything which itself. For in this way,it repels injurious influences and pursues that seems to happen by our own agency. which is congenial to it. So„ in book two he says that it is obvious that many things occur by The Stoics claim that what some people say is false, viz. that the our own initiative, but nonetheless these are co-fated with the administra­ primary [or first] impulse of animals is to pleasure. 86. For they say that tion of the universe. And he uses illustrations like these. pleasure is, if anything, a byproduct which supervenes when nature itself, The non-destruction of one’s coat, he says, is not fated simply, but on its own, seeks out and acquires what is ‘suitable to [the animal’s] co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone’s being saved from constitution. It is like the condition*of thriving animals and plants in top his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children condition. And nature, they say, did not operate differently in the cases is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. For just as if, he says, of plants and of animals; for it ditects the life of plants too, though someone says that Hegesarchus the boxer will leave the ring completely without impulse and sense-perception, and even in us some processes untouched, it would be strange for him to think that Hegesarchus should are plant-like. When, in the case of animals, impulse is added (which fight with his fists down because it was fated that he should get off they use in the pursuit of things to which they have an affinity), then untouched (the man who made the assertion saying this because of the for them what is natural is governed by what is according to impulse. fellow’s extraordinary protection from being punched), so too the same When reason has been given to rational animals as a more perfect governor thing holds in other cases. For many things cannot occur without our [of life], then for them the life according to reason properly becomes being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and what is natural for them. For reason supervenes on impulse as a craftsman. zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur 87. Thus Zeno first, in his book On the Nature of Man, said that the goal in conjunction with this personal effort. But it will be in our power, was to live in agreement with nature, which is to live according to virtue. he says, with what is in our power being included in fate. For nature leads us to virtue. And similarly Cleanthes in On Pleasure and Posidonius and Hecaton in their books On the Goal. Again, “to live according to virtue” is equivalent to living according to the experience of events which occur by nature, as Chrysippus says Ethics in book one of his,0« Goals. 88. For our natures are parts of the nature of the universe. Therefore, the goal becomes “to live consistently with Diogenes Laertius 7.84-131 [11-94] nature”, i.e., according to one’s own nature and that of the universe, 84. They divide the ethical part of philosophy into these topics: on doing nothing which is forbidden by the common law, which is right impulse, on good and bad things, on passions, on virtue, on the goal, on reason, penetrating all things, being the same as Zeus who is the leader primary valued on actions, on appropriate actions, on encouragements of the administration of things. And this itself is the virtue of the happy and discouragements to actions. This is the subdivision given by the man and a smooth flow of life, whenever all things are done according followers of Chrysippus, Archedemus, Zenp of Tarsus, Apollodorus, to the harmony of the daimon in each of us with the will of the 192 II-94 Ethics 193 administrator of the universe. So Diogenes says explicitly that the goal are good and bad and neither; courage is knowledge of which things are is reasonable behaviour in the selection of things according to nature, to be chosen and avoided and neither; and .... [There is a lacuna here.] and Archedemus [says it is] to live carrying out all the appropriate acts. 93. magnanimity is knowledge or a condition which makes one superior 89. By nature, in consistency with which we must live, ChrysippuS to those things which happen alike to base and virtuous men; self-control understands both the common and, specifically, the human nature. Clean- is an unsurpassable disposition [concerned with] what accords with right thes includes only the common nature, with which one must be consistent, reason, or a condition which cannot be defeated by pleasures; endurance and not the individual. And virtue is a disposition in agreement. And it is knowledge of or a condition [concerned with] what one is to stand is worth choosing for its own sake, not because of some fear or hope or firmly by and what is not and neither; quick-wittedness is a condition some extrinsic consideration. And happiness lies in virtue, insofar as which injtantly finds out what the appropriate action is; and deliberative virtue is the soul [so] made [as to produce] the agreement of one’s excellence is a knowledge of how to consider the type and manner of whole life. actions which we must perform in ofder to act advantageously. And the rational animal is corrupted, son^etimes because of the persua­ Correspondingly, of vices too some are primary and some are subordi­ siveness of external activities and sometimes because of the influence of nate. For example, imprudence, cowardice, injustice and wantonness are companions. For the starting points provided by nature are uncorrupted. primary, and lack of self-control, slow-wittedness and poor deliberation 90. Virtue in one sense is generally a sort of completion [or: perfection] are subordinate. Those vices whose [counterpart] virtues are forms of for each thing, for example, of a statue. And there is also non-intellectual knowledge are forms of ignorance. virtue, for example, health; and intellectual virtue, for example; prudence. 94. Good is in general that from which there is something beneficial; For in book one of his On Virtues Hecaton says that those virtues which in particular it is either the same as or not different from benefit. Hence, are constituted out of theorems are knowledge-based and intellectual, for virtue itself and the good, which participates in it, are spoken of in example prudence and justice; but those which are understood by exten­ these three ways: [1] the good is that from which being benefitted is a sion from those which are constituted out of theorems are non-intellectual, characteristic result; [2] it is that according to which [being benefitted] is for example health and strength. For it turns out that health follows on a characteristic result, for example, action according to virtue; [3] it is and is extended from temperance, which is intellectual, just as strength he by whom [being benefitted is a characteristic result]; and “by whom” supervenes on the building of an arch. 91. They are called non-intellectual means, for example, the virtuous man who participates in virtue. because they do not involve assent, but they supervene even in base They give another particular definition of the good, as follows: “that people, as health and courage do. which is perfectly in accord with nature for a rational being, qua rational”. Posidonius (in book one of his Ethical Discourse) says that a sign that And virtue is such a thing, so that virtuous actions and virtuous men virtue exists is the fact that the followers of Socrates, Diogenes, and participate [in it]; and its supervenient byproducts are joy and good Antisthenes were making [moral] progress; and vice exists because it is spirits and the like.
Recommended publications
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Criticisms of the Stoic Theory of Passions
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 20 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-2003 Augustine's Criticisms of the Stoic Theory of Passions T.H. Irwin Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Irwin, T.H. (2003) "Augustine's Criticisms of the Stoic Theory of Passions," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 20 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil20032043 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol20/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. AUGUSTINE'S CRITICISMS OF THE STOIC THEORY OF PASSIONS T.H.Irwin Augustine defends three claims about the passions: (1) The Stoic position dif­ fers only verbally from the Platonic-Aristotelian position. (2) The Stoic position is wrong and the Platonic-Aristotelian position is right. (3) The will is engaged in the different passions; indeed the different passions are different expressions of the will. The first two claims, properly understood, are defensible. But the most plausible versions of them give us good reason to doubt the third claim. 1. A full exploration of Augustine's reflexions on the nature of the passions would introduce us to some of his central moral and theological concems. I do not intend to undertake this full exploration. I want to discuss his claim about the proper interpretation of the Stoic conception of the passions in relation to the Platonic and Aristotelian view.
    [Show full text]
  • Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected]
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 3-20-2014 Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Coakley, Melissa Marie, "Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature" (2014). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/4999 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aeschynē in Aristotle’s Conception of Human Nature by Melissa M. Coakley A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Science University of South Florida Major Professor: Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Bruce Silver, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 20, 2014 Keywords: Shame, Anaeschyntia, Aidōs, Aischynē, Ancient Greek Passions Copyright © 2014, Melissa M. Coakley DEDICATION This manuscript is dedicated to my husband Bill Murray and to my parents: Joan and Richard Coakley. Thank you for your endless support, encouragement, and friendship. To Dr. John P. Anton, I have learned from you the importance of having a “ton of virtue and a shield of nine layers for protection from the abysmal depths of vice.” Thank you for believing in me, my dear friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life
    Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life by David Ryan Morphew A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in The University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Victor Caston, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Professor Arlene Saxonhouse David Ryan Morphew [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4773-4952 ©David Ryan Morphew 2018 DEDICATION To my wife, Renae, whom I met as I began this project, and who has supported me throughout its development. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First and foremost, I am grateful to my advisors and dissertation committee for their encouragement, support, challenges, and constructive feedback. I am chiefly indebted to Victor Caston for his comments on successive versions of chapters, for his great insight and foresight in guiding me in the following project, and for steering me to work on Plutarch’s Moralia in the first place. No less am I thankful for what he has taught me about being a scholar, mentor, and teacher, by his advice and especially by his example. There is not space here to express in any adequate way my gratitude also to Sara Ahbel-Rappe and Richard Janko. They have been constant sources of inspiration. I continue to be in awe of their ability to provide constructive criticism and to give incisive critiques coupled with encouragement and suggestions. I am also indebted to Arlene Saxonhouse for helping me to see the scope and import of the following thesis not only as of interest to the history of philosophy but also in teaching our students to reflect on the kind of life that we want to live.
    [Show full text]
  • Emotions.Pdf
    April 2011 Forthcoming in R. Crisp ed, The Oxford Handbook to the History of Ethics Emotion and the Emotions Susan Sauvé Meyer Adrienne M. Martin A prominent theme in twentieth and early twenty-first century moral philosophy is that a full and accurate picture of the ethical life must include an important role for the emotions. The neglect of the emotions has been a major point of criticism raised against the dominant consequentialist, Kantian, and contractualist theories by virtue ethicists such as G.E.M. Anscombe, Alisdair MacIntyre, Martha Nussbaum, and Michael Stocker. Bernard Williams and Susan Wolf also develop a similar line of criticism as part of their arguments against the supremacy or priority of moral values as conceived by utilitarianism and other “impartialist” theories. There are a number of reasons why it might be a mistake for moral philosophy to neglect the emotions. To name just three: 1. It seems obvious that emotions have an important influence on motivation, and that proper cultivation of the emotions is helpful, perhaps essential, to our ability to lead ethical lives. 2. It is also arguable that emotions are objects of moral evaluation, not only because of their influence on action, but in themselves. In other words, it is a plausible thesis that an ethical life involves feeling certain ways in certain circumstances and acting from certain feelings in certain circumstances. 3. Finally, a more contentious thesis, but certainly worth considering, is that some emotions are forms of ethical perception, judgment, or even knowledge. The bulk of this chapter surveys the Ancient ethical tradition that inspires the virtue ethicist’s critique, revealing versions of each of these three theses in one guise or another.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom from Passions in Augustine
    UNIVERSITY OF HELSINKI FACULTY OF THEOLOGY FINLAND FREEDOM FROM PASSIONS IN AUGUSTINE Gao Yuan 高 源 ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Theology at the University of Helsinki in Lecture Hall 13, University Main Building, on 4 November 2015, at 12 noon Helsinki 2015 ISBN 978-951-51-1625-3 (paperback) ISBN 978-951-51-1626-0 (PDF) Copyright © Gao Yuan (高源) https://ethesis.helsinki.fi/en Cover: Wang Rui and Gao Yuan Juvenes Print Oy Helsinki 2015 ABSTRACT This study presents a general overview of Augustine’s insights into passions as well as his approach to the therapy of emotions and their sanctification. Attending to various phases of his writings, this work explores the systematic structure of Augustine’s tenets on passions and on the freedom from passions in the context of his philosophical and theological convictions on the issue of amor sui and amor Dei. The analysis begins by examining Augustine’s language of passions and the doctrinal connections between Augustine and his predecessors. I provide a survey of Augustine’s usage of emotional terms and criticise the position that Augustine suggested a dichotomy between passio and affectus as well as the claim that none of Augustine’s Latin terms can be justifiably translated by the modern term “emotion”. On the basis of terminological and doctrinal observations, I clarify the general features of Augustine’s psychology of passions in Chapter 2. In addressing the issue of how Augustine transformed his predecessors’ therapy of passions and their ideal of freedom from emotion into his theological framework in Chapter 3, I examine a series of related concepts, such as propatheia, metriopatheia, apatheia and eupatheia, to determine how he understood them in various stages of his philosophical and theological thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Medicine and Rhetoric: Therapeutic Arguments in Roman Stoicism
    e­­‑ISSN 2084–1043 p-ISSN 2083–6635 Vol. 9 (1/2019) pp. 11–24 Published online: 30.11.2019 www.argument-journal.eu Between medicine and rhetoric: therapeutic arguments in Roman Stoicism Krzysztof ŁAPIŃSKI* ABSTRACT In this paper, I intend to focus on some rhetorical strategies of argumentation which play crucial role in the therapeutic discourse of Roman Stoicism, namely in Musonius Rufus, Ep- ictetus, Seneca, and Marcus Aurelius. Reference is made to Chaim Perelman’s view of ancient rhetoric as an art of inventing arguments. Moreover, it is pointed out that in rhetorical educa- tion (cf. Cicero, Ad Herennium, Quintilian, etc.) as well as in therapeutic discourse the concept of “exercise” and constant practice play a crucial role. KEYWORDS Stoicism; Musonius Rufus; Epictetus; Seneca; Marcus Aurelius; Chaim Perelman; consola- tion; spiritual exercise * PhD, assistant professor, Institute of Philosophy, University of Warsaw. E-mail: [email protected]. This research paper was supported by an NCN Miniatura 2 grant to carry out research at the University of Cambridge, UK (reg. no. 2018/02/X/HS1/01200). DOI: 10.24917/20841043.01 12 Krzysztof ŁAPIŃSKI Ancient Greek and Roman philosophy was focused not only on inquiring into the nature of the world, but also on transforming human minds. In order to describe that tendency more adequately, various scholars have labelled it as, for example, spiritual exercises (Pierre Hadot), the art of living (Michel Foucault), the therapy of desire (Martha Nussbaum), or spiritual guidance (Paul Rab- bow and Ilsetraut Hadot). The therapeutic paradigm becomes predominant in Hellenistic and Roman times.
    [Show full text]
  • Akrasia and Enkrateia in Ancient Stoicism: Minor Vice and Minor Virtue?*
    AKRASIA AND ENKRATEIA IN ANCIENT STOICISM: MINOR VICE AND MINOR VIRTUE?* Jean-Baptiste Gourinat At fi rst glance, the case of akrasia in Ancient Stoicism is quickly closed: the word is found twice in the Stoicorum veterum fragmenta, while the word akratês may be found once, and akrasia again may be found twice in Epictetus1 and nowhere in Marcus Aurelius.2 One may try to persuade oneself that the ten or so occurrences of impotens and impotentia in Seneca refer to akrasia, but, in fact, this is rather unlikely. This situation is echoed by the quasi-absence of the word in classical or recent accounts of Stoic ethics: the word occurs once in Dyroff ’s classic study,3 never appears in Max Forschner’s Die stoische Ethik,4 and Brad Inwood, in Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism, shows excellently that the phenomenon of weak will was rejected by the Stoics.5 Akrasia evidently does not play in Stoic ethics the central role it plays in Aristotelian ethics, for instance. The reason for this is clear: akrasia implies a confl ict between two parts of the soul, a rational part and an irrational one, the weakness of the rational part being unable to dominate the irrational one. But the Stoics * I am very grateful to Pierre Destrée for convincing me to work on this topic, which, at fi rst, seemed to me of no great pertinence for Stoic thought. This paper will show, I hope, that the matter is more important than it may seem to be, and that Pierre Destrée was well inspired.
    [Show full text]
  • A STUDY of SENECA‟S MORAL PHILOSOPHY by Robert
    Curing Human Misery: A Study of Seneca's Moral Philosophy Item Type text; Electronic Dissertation Authors Wagoner, Robert Stephen Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 01/10/2021 21:28:23 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/202933 1 CURING HUMAN MISERY: A STUDY OF SENECA‟S MORAL PHILOSOPHY by Robert Stephen Wagoner _____________________ Copyright © Robert Stephen Wagoner 2011 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2011 2 THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA GRADUATE COLLEGE As members of the Dissertation Committee, we certify that we have read the dissertation prepared by Robert Wagoner entitled Curing Human Misery: A Study of Seneca’s Moral Philosophy and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 8/10/11 Julia Annas _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 8/10/11 Rachana Kamtekar _______________________________________________________________________ Date: 8/10/11 Mark Timmons Final approval and acceptance of this dissertation is contingent upon the candidate‟s submission of the final copies of the dissertation to the Graduate College. I hereby certify that I have read this dissertation prepared under my direction and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Passions, Virtue, And
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Passions, Virtue, and Moral Growth in John of Apamea’s Dialogues on the Soul A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Theology and Religious Studies Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Rodrigue J. Constantin Washington, D.C. 2020 Abstract Passions, Virtue, and Moral Growth in John of Apamea’s Dialogues on the Soul Rodrigue J. Constantin, Ph.D. Director: Paul J. Scherz, Ph.D. Virtue cultivation is an under-researched topic in theological virtue ethics. Moreover, little attention is given in virtue ethics to vice and its impact on virtue cultivation. In this dissertation, I respond to this lacuna by examining the role of the removal of evil passions in moral growth in the Dialogues on the Soul, whose author, John of Apamea, is a fifth-century ascetic who has introduced the discussion of passions in Syriac Christianity. For John, moral growth occurs in three stages: somaticity, psychicality, and pneumaticity. I argue that, for John, the gradual healing from evil passions facilitates one’s moral progress from one stage to another. After examining John’s theological anthropology, in the first chapter, I explore his views on the relationship of the body and the soul with the passions in chapters two and three. In chapter four, I focus on the morality of the passions, that is, whether the passions in themselves are good or evil, and to what degree one is morally responsible for them. I, then, reconstruct, in chapter five, a list of the passions and their variations in the Dialogues on the Soul, as well as the structure of the passions as stirrings that are intimately connected to thoughts.
    [Show full text]
  • Anger, Present Injustice and Future Revenge in Seneca's
    2006020. Volk Williams. 05_Vogt. Proef 1. 10-4-2006:14.48, page 57. ANGER, PRESENT INJUSTICE AND FUTURE REVENGE IN SENECA’S DE IRA Katja Maria Vogt De ira is, as Seneca states in the beginning, a treatise on how to alleviate anger.* While other emotions may still have something calm about them, anger, according to Seneca, is all excitement, raging towards vengeance (1.1.1). The idea that we should aim at getting rid of anger is tied to the theoretical discussion of anger: once we understand what we actively do when we experience anger, we can stop short of getting angry. De ira stands within a Stoic tradition of discussing the therapy of the emotions.1 Seneca’s concern with anger is not only in line with the general Stoic conviction that emotions are irrational, but also with a more widespread ancient interest in anger as a particularly violent emotion. However, in spite of the particular attention that is devoted to anger, it seems that, of all emotions, anger is surprisingly difficult to understand within the Stoic framework. The violent anger which is at stake in ancient discussions has an element of pain and an element of desire; the agent feels unjustly harmed and desires revenge. But according to the Stoic framework, an emotion can either be a kind of pain (lupê)2 or a kind of desire * I am grateful to William Harris for inviting me to present an earlier version of this paper at the Conference “New Directions in Seneca Studies” (Columbia Univeristy, February 2004), and for the helpful comments and questions from the participants at the conference.
    [Show full text]
  • Paulo Fernando Tadeu Ferreira Destino, Exortações Eficazes E Punições Justas Em Crisipo
    UNIVERSITY OF SÃO PAULO FACULTY OF PHILOSOPHY, LANGUAGES, AND HUMAN SCIENCES DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE SCHOOL IN PHILOSOPHY PAULO FERNANDO TADEU FERREIRA DESTINO, EXORTAÇÕES EFICAZES E PUNIÇÕES JUSTAS EM CRISIPO VERSÃO CORRIGIDA/REVISED VERSION SÃO PAULO 2017 PAULO FERNANDO TADEU FERREIRA CHRYSIPPUS ON FATE, EFFECTIVE EXHORTATION, AND DESERT VERSÃO CORRIGIDA/REVISED VERSION A Thesis submitted to the Graduate School in Philosophy of the Department of Philosophy of the Faculty of Philosophy, Languages, and Human Sciences of the University of São Paulo, in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, under the supervision of Prof. Dr. Marco Antonio de Avila Zingano. In agreement: ____________________ Prof. Dr. Marco Zingano SÃO PAULO 2017 Autorizo a reprodução e divulgação total ou parcial deste trabalho, por qualquer meio convencional ou eletrônico, para fins de estudo e pesquisa, desde que citada a fonte. Catalogação na Publicação Serviço de Biblioteca e Documentação Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de São Paulo Ferreira, Paulo Fernando Tadeu F383c Chrysippus on Fate, Effective Exhortation, and Desert / Paulo Fernando Tadeu Ferreira ; orientador Marco Antonio de Avila Zingano. - São Paulo, 2017. 138 f. Tese (Doutorado)- Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas da Universidade de São Paulo. Departamento de Filosofia. Área de concentração: Filosofia. 1. Chrysippus. 2. Fate. 3. Exhortation. 4. Punishment. I. Zingano, Marco Antonio de Avila, orient. II. Título. ACCEPTANCE PAGE FERREIRA, P.F.T. 2017. Chrysippus on Fate, Effective Exhortation, and Desert. Revised Version. PhD Thesis. Faculty of Philosophy, Languages, and Human Sciences. Department of Philosophy, University of São Paulo, 2017. Approved in: ____/____/____ Examining Committee: Prof.
    [Show full text]