Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life by David Ryan Morphew A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in The University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Victor Caston, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Professor Arlene Saxonhouse David Ryan Morphew [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4773-4952 ©David Ryan Morphew 2018 DEDICATION To my wife, Renae, whom I met as I began this project, and who has supported me throughout its development. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First and foremost, I am grateful to my advisors and dissertation committee for their encouragement, support, challenges, and constructive feedback. I am chiefly indebted to Victor Caston for his comments on successive versions of chapters, for his great insight and foresight in guiding me in the following project, and for steering me to work on Plutarch’s Moralia in the first place. No less am I thankful for what he has taught me about being a scholar, mentor, and teacher, by his advice and especially by his example. There is not space here to express in any adequate way my gratitude also to Sara Ahbel-Rappe and Richard Janko. They have been constant sources of inspiration. I continue to be in awe of their ability to provide constructive criticism and to give incisive critiques coupled with encouragement and suggestions. I am also indebted to Arlene Saxonhouse for helping me to see the scope and import of the following thesis not only as of interest to the history of philosophy but also in teaching our students to reflect on the kind of life that we want to live. I have been very fortunate and greatly blessed by excellent advisors, mentors, and teachers throughout my journey at the University of Michigan, the University of Colorado at Boulder, and Baylor University. Most of all, I must thank Jeff Fish. As a great teacher and mentor, Jeff first instilled a love for Greek and the Classics and set me on this path. He has been a constant source of encouragement and a good friend. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS DEDICATION ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS iii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS viii LIST OF PLUTARCH’S WORKS CITED ix ABSTRACT xii INTRODUCTION 1 I The Purpose and Scope of This Study 1 II Plutarch: A Philosophical and Political Life 3 III Perceptions of Plutarch: Reconsidering Eclecticism 5 IV The Unity of the Academy 10 V Core Doctrines and Tenets 15 V.a. Platonic Psychology: Bipartition and Tripartition 16 V.b. Moderation or Eradication of Emotions? 17 V.c. Moderation and Eradication of Passions from Plato through Porphyry 19 V.d. Plutarch and μετριοπάθεια 22 VI Outline of Chapters 23 iv CHAPTER 1. Emotional Vulnerability and Friendship 27 I Stoic Value and the Invulnerability of Stoic Happiness 29 II Invulnerability and the Elimination of Passions (ἀπάθεια) 32 III Human Nature and the Phenomena of Human Experience 35 IV Invulnerability and the Cost of Friendship 40 V Intimacy and the Good of Friendship 49 VI Friendship, Human Nature, and the Stoic Theory of οἰκείωσις 57 VII Stoic Invulnerability and Self-Mutilation 65 2. Grief and Moderating Passions: Plutarch Against Plato? 71 I Plato on Eliminating Grief 72 II Plutarch on the Naturalness and Usefulness of Grief 78 III Plato and the Negative Evaluation of Passions 88 IV Plutarch on the Naturalness and Usefulness of Passions 100 V The Moderation of Passions (μετριοπάθεια) and Moral Virtue in Plutarch 105 VI Moral Virtue and the Harmony of Bodily Humors 113 VII Plutarch, Aristotle, and the Unified Academy 117 3. Spirit and Love: Enhancing Action 129 I Passion, Practical Action, and The Division of Virtues 130 II Passions as the Wind in Our Sails 140 III Enhancing Action and Divine Aid 144 IV Attached Passions and Intensifying Virtue 148 v V Incitement to Virtue, Enthusiasm, and Non-Rational Longing for Virtue 151 VI That Life is Better with Passions Than Without Them 156 4. Restraint and Cognitive Emotions 161 I. Rational Restraint and Passionate Restraint of Errant Desires 164 II Spirited Passions in Lieu of Reason 171 III The Spirited Part of the Soul and Cognitive Emotions in Plato: A Synopsis 177 IV Non-Rational Passions are Not Wholly Non-Rational 182 V Participating in Reason to Different Degrees 190 VI Cognitive Emotions: The Desire for Honor, Shame, Anger, Hate, and Envy 199 VII Internalizing Standards and Forming Beliefs 208 5. Honor, Shame, and Early Education 218 I Shame, Honor, and Non-Rational Persuasion (ψυχαγωγία) 220 II Correcting Xenocrates on Education and the “Grips of Philosophy” 229 II.a. The Grips of Philosophy as Preparation for Progress in Virtue 231 II.b. The Grips of Philosophy as Oar-Handles 235 II.c. The Grips of Philosophy as Enduring Holds on Character 241 III Aristotle and Plato on Habituation of Passions 244 IV Reflection and Shame as One Becomes the Cultivator of One’s Own Passions 249 V Anchoring the Sense of Shame to Reason 256 6. Cultivating Virtue and Becoming Like God 260 I Character Formation and the Metaphor of Cultivation 262 vi I.a. Cultivating Virtue: Plant Metaphors, Passions, and Pruning the 262 Desire for Honor I.b. Cultivation of Virtue and Weeds of Vice Endemic to Human Nature 271 I.c. The Growth within the Passions and the Fruit of Virtue 277 II The Seeds of Virtue: The Background 280 III Affection and the Seeds of Virtue in Plutarch 283 IV Plutarch, Identification (οἰκείωσις), and Becoming Like God (ὁμοίωσις θεῷ) 292 CONCLUSION 309 APPENDIX to Chapter 4: Plato and Spirited Evaluation: A Background 316 A.I. Plato and Spirited Evaluation of Action 317 A.II. Evaluations and Beliefs of the Non-Rational Parts of Soul in Plato 323 A.III. High Standards of Belief (δόξα) in Plato’s Sophist, Theaetetus, 326 Timaeus, and Philebus A.IV. The Top-Down View: Receiving Beliefs from the Rational 336 Part of the Soul in Plato A.V. Spirited Evaluations Independent of Rational Evaluations in Plato 347 BIBLIOGRAPHY 351 vii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Collections of Ancient Texts: DK Hermann A. Diels and Walter Kranz (edd.) 1951–2, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th revised edn. (orig. 1903), 3 vols., Berlin: Weidmann. FGrH Jacobi, Felix (ed.) 1923–1959, Die Fragmente der griechischen Historiker, Berlin: Weidmann. LS Anthony A. Long and David N. Sedley (edd.) 1987, The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. SVF Hans von Arnim (ed.) 1903–5 (repr. 1964), Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, 3 vols., Leipzig: Teubner; Maximilian Adler (1924), vol. 4 (Indices), Stuttgart: Teubner. Dictionaries and Encyclopedias: LSJ Henry G. Liddell, Robert Scott, and Henry S. Jones (edd.) 1996, A Greek-English Lexicon, 9th edn., with a revised suppl., Oxford: Clarendon Press. SEP Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab Center for the Study of Language and Information, https://plato.stanford.edu/ Ancient Authors: D.L. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers, in Miroslav Marcovich (ed.) 1999, Diogenis Laertii vitae philosophorum, 3 vols., Stuttgart: Teubner. S.E. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism and Against the Professors, in Jürgen Mau and Hermann Mutschmann (edd.) 1912–14, Sexti Empirici opera, 3 vols., Leipzig: Teubner. Stob. Stobaeus, Anthology, in Otto Hense and Curt Wachsmuth (edd.) 1884–1912 (repr. 1958), Ioannis Stobaei anthologium, 5 vols., Berlin: Weidmann. viii LIST OF PLUTARCH’S WORKS CITED Plutarch’s Moralia: How a Young Man Should Read Poetry = Quomodo adolescens poetas audire debeat (Πῶς δεῖ τὸν νέον ποιημάτων ἀκούειν) On Listening to Lectures = De recta ratione audiendi (Περὶ τοῦ ἀκούειν) How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend = Quomodo adulator ab amico internoscatur (Πῶς ἄν τις διακρίνειε τὸν κόλακα τοῦ φίλου) On Moral Progres = Quomodo quis suos in virtute sentiat profectus (Πῶς ἄν τις αἴσθοιτο ἑαυτοῦ προκόπτοντος ἐπ᾿ ἀρετῇ) How to Profit by One’s Enemies = De capienda ex inimicis utilitate (Πῶς ἄν τις ὑπ᾿ ἐχθρῶν ὠφελοῖτο) On Having Many Friends = De amicorum multitudine (Περὶ πολυφιλίας) On Virtue and Vice = De virtute et vitio (Περὶ ἀρετῆς καὶ κακίας) Consolation to Apollonius = Consolatio ad Apollonium (Παραμυθητικὸς πρὸς Ἀπολλώνιον) Advice on Keeping Well = De tuenda sanitate praecepta (Ὑγιεινὰ παραγγέλματα) Advice to Bride and Groom = Coniugalia praecepta (Γαμικὰ παραγγέλματα) Dinner of the Seven Wise Men = Septem sapientium convivium (Τῶν ἑπτὰ σοφῶν συμπόσιον) On Superstition = De superstitione (Περὶ δεισιδαιμονίας) Sayings of Kings and Emperors = Regum et imperatorum apophthegmata (Ἀποφθέγματα βασιλέων καὶ στρατηγῶν) Sayings of the Spartans = Apophthegmata Laconica (Ἀποφθέγματα Λακωνικά) Bravery of Women = Mulierum virtutes (Γυναικῶν ἀρεταί) Roman Questions = Quaestiones Romanae (Αἴτια Ῥωμαϊκά) On the Great Fortune or Virtue of Alexander 1 and 2 = De Alexandri magni fortuna aut virtute, libri ii (Περὶ τῆς Ἀλεξάνδρου τύχης ἢ ἀρετῆς, λόγοι β΄) On Isis and Osiris = De Iside et Osiride (Περὶ Ἴσιδος καὶ Ὀσίριδος) On the E at Delphi = De E apud Delphos (Περὶ τοῦ ΕΙ τοῦ ἐν Δελφοῖς) On the Oracles at Delphi = De Pythiae oraculis (Περὶ τοῦ μὴ χρᾶν ἔμμετρα νῦν τὴν Πυθίαν) On the Obsolescence of Oracles = De defectu oraculorum (Περὶ τῶν ἐκλελοιπότων χρηστηρίων) Can Virtue be Taught = An virtus doceri possit (Εἰ διδακτὸν ἡ ἀρετή) On Moral Virtue = De virtute morali (Περὶ τῆς ἠθικῆς ἀρετῆς) On the Control of Anger = De cohibenda ira (Περὶ ἀοργησίας) On Tranquility of Mind = De tranquillitate animi (Περὶ εὐθυμίας) On Brotherly Love = De fraterno amore
Recommended publications
  • Chrysippus's Dog As a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition
    Chrysippus’s Dog as a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition Michael Rescorla Abstract: I critique an ancient argument for the possibility of non-linguistic deductive inference. The argument, attributed to Chrysippus, describes a dog whose behavior supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning. Drawing on contemporary robotics, I urge that we can equally well explain the dog’s behavior by citing probabilistic reasoning over cognitive maps. I then critique various experimentally-based arguments from scientific psychology that echo Chrysippus’s anecdotal presentation. §1. Language and thought Do non-linguistic creatures think? Debate over this question tends to calcify into two extreme doctrines. The first, espoused by Descartes, regards language as necessary for cognition. Modern proponents include Brandom (1994, pp. 145-157), Davidson (1984, pp. 155-170), McDowell (1996), and Sellars (1963, pp. 177-189). Cartesians may grant that ascribing cognitive activity to non-linguistic creatures is instrumentally useful, but they regard such ascriptions as strictly speaking false. The second extreme doctrine, espoused by Gassendi, Hume, and Locke, maintains that linguistic and non-linguistic cognition are fundamentally the same. Modern proponents include Fodor (2003), Peacocke (1997), Stalnaker (1984), and many others. Proponents may grant that non- linguistic creatures entertain a narrower range of thoughts than us, but they deny any principled difference in kind.1 2 An intermediate position holds that non-linguistic creatures display cognitive activity of a fundamentally different kind than human thought. Hobbes and Leibniz favored this intermediate position. Modern advocates include Bermudez (2003), Carruthers (2002, 2004), Dummett (1993, pp. 147-149), Malcolm (1972), and Putnam (1992, pp. 28-30).
    [Show full text]
  • Plutarch's 'Lives' and the Critical Reader
    Plutarch's 'Lives' and the critical reader Book or Report Section Published Version Duff, T. (2011) Plutarch's 'Lives' and the critical reader. In: Roskam, G. and Van der Stockt, L. (eds.) Virtues for the people: aspects of Plutarch's ethics. Plutarchea Hypomnemata (4). Leuven University Press, Leuven, pp. 59-82. ISBN 9789058678584 Available at http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/24388/ It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the work. See Guidance on citing . Publisher: Leuven University Press All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in the End User Agreement . www.reading.ac.uk/centaur CentAUR Central Archive at the University of Reading Reading’s research outputs online Reprint from Virtues for the People. Aspects of Plutarchan Ethics - ISBN 978 90 5867 858 4 - Leuven University Press virtues for the people aspects of plutarchan ethics Reprint from Virtues for the People. Aspects of Plutarchan Ethics - ISBN 978 90 5867 858 4 - Leuven University Press PLUTARCHEA HYPOMNEMATA Editorial Board Jan Opsomer (K.U.Leuven) Geert Roskam (K.U.Leuven) Frances Titchener (Utah State University, Logan) Luc Van der Stockt (K.U.Leuven) Advisory Board F. Alesse (ILIESI-CNR, Roma) M. Beck (University of South Carolina, Columbia) J. Beneker (University of Wisconsin, Madison) H.-G. Ingenkamp (Universität Bonn) A.G. Nikolaidis (University of Crete, Rethymno) Chr. Pelling (Christ Church, Oxford) A. Pérez Jiménez (Universidad de Málaga) Th.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodicy: an Overview
    1 Theodicy: An Overview Introduction All of us struggle at one time or another in life with why evil happens to someone, either ourselves, our family, our friends, our nation, or perhaps some particularly disturbing instance in the news—a child raped, a school shooting, genocide in another country, a terrorist bombing. The following material is meant to give an overview of the discussion of this issue as it takes place in several circles, especially that of the Christian church. I. The Problem of Evil Defined Three terms, "the problem of evil," "theodicy," and "defense" are important to our discussion. The first two are often used as synonyms, but strictly speaking the problem of evil is the larger issue of which theodicy is a subset because one can have a secular problem of evil. Evil is understood as a problem when we seek to explain why it exists (Unde malum?) and what its relationship is to the world as a whole. Indeed, something might be considered evil when it calls into question our basic trust in the order and structure of our world. Peter Berger in particular has argued that explanations of evil are necessary for social structures to stay themselves against chaotic forces. It follows, then, that such an explanation has an impact on the whole person. As David Blumenthal observes, a good theodicy is one that has three characteristics: 1. "[I]t should leave one with one’s sense of reality intact." (It tells the truth about reality.) 2. "[I]t should leave one empowered within the intellectual-moral system in which one lives." (Namely, it should not deny God’s basic power or goodness.) 3.
    [Show full text]
  • KEIMPE ALGRA 155-184.Qxd
    Ο Ζήνων ο Κιτιέας και η Στωική κοσμολογία: μερικές σημειώσεις και δυο συγκεκριμένες περιπτώσεις. KEIMPE ALGRA Η έκταση και η φύση της συμβολής του Ζήνωνα στη Στωική φυσική και κοσμολογία είναι δύσκολο να θεμελιωθούν. Η ανακοίνωση αυτή μελετά μερικά από τα σχετικά προβλήματα. Η χρήση της ονομαστικής ετικέτας "Ζήνων" από τις αρχαίες μας πηγές δε θα πρέπει πάντα να αξιολογείται επιφανειακά, και η απόδοση καθώς και η διευθέτηση του υλικού του Hans Von Arnim στο Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (SVF) δε θα πρέπει να γίνεται αποδεκτή χωρίς κριτική, για λόγους που περιγράφονται σ’ αυτή την εργασία. Παρέχονται δύο συγκεκριμένες περιπτώσεις αποσπασμάτων, οι οποίες, με μια πιο προσεκτική ματιά, δε θα πρέπει να αποδοθούν στο Ζήνωνα. Τελικά, υποστηρίζεται ότι ο Ζήνων δεν ήταν παραγωγικός συγγραφέας σε θέματα φυσικής, και ότι έτυχε στους διαδόχους του ( σε μερικούς από αυτούς) – πιο συγκεκριμένα στον Σφαίρο, στον Κλεάνθη και στον Χρύσιππο – να επεξεργαστούν περαιτέρω και να συγκροτήσουν λεπτομερειακά την φυσική κοσμοεικόνα της Στωικής σχολής. Αυτό σημαίνει πως υπάρχουν περιθώρια ανάπτυξης της φυσικής και της κοσμολογίας στα πλαίσια του αρχαίου Στωικισμού, και πως, συνακόλουθα, είναι ζωτικής σημασίας να διακρίνουμε πιο ξεκάθαρα, απ’ ότι συνήθως, τι πρέπει με ασφάλεια να αποδοθεί στο Ζήνωνα και ότι τέτοιου είδους "κοινά στωικά" δόγματα πρέπεί μόνο πιθανά, ή μερικά, να ανιχνευτούν σ΄αυτόν. Zeno of Citium and Stoic Cosmology: some notes and two case studies KEIMPE ALGRA 1 Zeno of Citium, as indeed the early Stoics in general, conceived of philosophy as consisting of three interrelated parts: logic, physics and ethics.1 But although Zeno’s foundational work covered all three areas, he appears to have had his preferences.
    [Show full text]
  • Colin Mcallister Regnum Caelorum Terrestre: the Apocalyptic Vision of Lactantius May 2016
    Colin McAllister Regnum Caelorum Terrestre: The Apocalyptic Vision of Lactantius May 2016 Abstract: The writings of the early fourth-century Christian apologist L. Caecilius Firmianus Lactantius have been extensively studied by historians, classicists, philosophers and theologians. But his unique apocalyptic eschatology expounded in book VII of the Divinae Institutiones, his largest work, has been relatively neglected. This paper will distill Lactantius’s complex narrative and summarize his sources. In particular, I investigate his chiliasm and the nature of the intermediate state, as well as his portrayal of the Antichrist. I argue that his apocalypticism is not an indiscriminate synthesis of varying sources - as it often stated - but is essentially based on the Book of Revelation and other Patristic sources. +++++ The eminent expert on all things apocalyptic, Bernard McGinn, wrote: Even the students and admirers of Lactantius have not bestowed undue praise upon him. To Rene Pichon [who wrote in 1901 what is perhaps still the seminal work on Lactantius’ thought] ‘Lactantius is mediocre in the Latin sense of the word - and also a bit in the French sense’; to Vincenzo Loi [who studied Lactantius’ use of the Bible] ‘Lactantius is neither a philosophical or theological genius nor linguistic genius.’ Despite these uneven appraisals, the writings of the early fourth-century Christian apologist L. Caecilius Firmianus Lactantius [c. 250-325] hold, it seems, a little something for everyone.1 Political historians study Lactantius as an important historical witness to the crucial transitional period from the Great Persecution of Diocletian to the ascension of Constantine, and for insight into the career of the philosopher Porphyry.2 Classicists and 1 All dates are anno domini unless otherwise indicated.
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • Calcidius's Commentary on Plato's Timaeus in Latin Astronomy of the Ninth to Eleventh Centuries
    BRUCE S. EASTWOOD CALCIDIUS'S COMMENTARY ON PLATO'S TIMAEUS IN LATIN ASTRONOMY OF THE NINTH TO ELEVENTH CENTURIES Prior to the twelfth-century recovery of Greek and discovery of Arabic astronomical (and astrological) texts, the character of European astronomy derived from three traditions: computus, classical texts, and observation (including instruments). By the ninth century each of these was involved with the others, producing an increasing variety of ideas and investigations. While the computistical and observational traditions combined in certain ways to bring about more practical and mathematical understanding of solar, lunar, and occasionally stellar motions, generally in the context of reckoning time intervals, the classical tradition led scholars to expand their frameworks for understanding the order and regularity of the heavens created by God.1 More speculative or theoretical and quite unmathematical in nature, the classical Latin materials that offered astronomical information and doctrines tested the wits of early medieval investigators in quite different ways than did the problems of the other traditions. Among these Roman astronomical works—the writings of Aratus (in translation), Pliny the Elder, Calcidius, Macrobius, and Martianus Capella were predominant—the translation of and commentary upon Plato's Timaeus by Calcidius has received the least attention by modern students of early medieval astronomy. Yet the work of Calcidius, especially his commentary, offers us a revealing field for the display of bold exploration, limits of comprehension, and successful innovation in medieval astronomical study more than half a century before the influx of Greco-Arabic works from ca. 1100 onward. Here I present examples of the boldness, the limits, and the successes from three manuscripts of Calcidius from the ninth to early eleventh centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Inerrancy of Scripture
    ON THE INERRANCY OF SCRIPTURE David P. Bolin You do err, knowing neither the Scriptures nor the power of God. Matthew 22:29 I. Introduction In many of the recent writings of Scripture scholars there seems to be a certain reluctance to discuss the nature of the inspiration of Scripture and its relation to the interpretation ofScripture. For example, the document ofthe Pontifical Bib­ lical Commission, The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church, denies that it intends to consider the theology of inspiration. The Commission does not aim to adopt a position on all the questions which arise with respect to the Bible-such as, for example, the theology of inspiration. What it has in mind is to examine all the methods likely to contribute effectively to the task of making more available the riches coutained in the biblical texts. 1 But in order for the Biblical Commission to achieve its stated goal, it is necessary for it to take some position regard- David Bolin earned last year the degree ofLicentiate in Sacred Theo­ logy from the International Theological Institute for Marriage and the Family. This article is the thesis he submitted as part of the requirement for that degree. 1 The Interpretation of the Bible in the Church, trans.]. Kilgallen and B. Byrne (Rome: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1993), 32-33. 23 ON THE INERRANCY OF ScRIPTURE David P. Bolin ing t~e n~t~re of inspiration and its effects on Scripture, if Examples such as this reveal both that the Commission is only 1mphe1tly, even if this is contrary to the Commission's right to reject this kind of interpretation, and that it is nec­ intentions.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl Boise State University
    Boise State University ScholarWorks History Faculty Publications and Presentations Department of History 1-1-2007 Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl Boise State University Publication Information Odahl, Charles Matson. (2007). "Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy". Connections: European Studies Annual Review, 3, 89-113. This document was originally published in Connections: European Studies Annual Review by Rocky Mountain European Scholars Consortium. Copyright restrictions may apply. Coda: Recovering Constantine's European Legacy 111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111 Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl, Boise State University1 rom his Christian conversion under the influence of cept of imperial theocracy was conveyed in contemporary art Frevelatory experiences outside Rome in A.D. 312 until (Illustration I). his burial as the thirteenth Apostle at Constantinople in Although Constantine had been raised as a tolerant 337, Constantine the Great, pagan polytheist and had the first Christian emperor propagated several Olympian of the Roman world, initiated divinities, particularly Jupiter, the role of and set the model Hercules, Mars, and Sol, as for Christian imperial theoc­ di vine patrons during the early racy. Through his relationship years of his reign as emperor
    [Show full text]
  • Origen in the Likeness of Philo: Eusebius of Caesarea's Portrait Of
    SCJR 12, no. 1 (2017): 1-13 Origen in the Likeness of Philo: Eusebius of Caesarea’s Portrait of the Model Scholar JUSTIN M. ROGERS [email protected] Freed-Hardeman University, Henderson, TN 38340 The name of Philo of Alexandria occurs more in the writings of Eusebius of Caesarea than in those of any other ancient author. Philo’s name can be located over 20 times in the surviving literary corpus of Eusebius,1 and there is strong ev- idence that Eusebius’ Caesarean library is the very reason Philo’s works exist today.2 In all probability, the core of this library can be traced to the personal col- lection of Origen when he settled in Caesarea in 232 CE.3 Eusebius’ own teacher Pamphilus expanded the library, and took great pains to copy and preserve Ori- gen’s own works. What we have, then, is a literary union between Philo and Origen, Alexandrians within the same exegetical tradition. But we can go further. Ilaria Ramelli has argued that Eusebius’ accounts of Philo and Origen in the Ecclesiastical History are strikingly similar, picking up Robert Grant’s stress on the similarity between Origen and the Philonic Therapeutae.4 Here, I further Ramelli’s work by noting additional similarities in the Eusebian biographical presentations. I also point to the tension Eusebius felt between Philo Christianus and Philo Judaeus, a tension detectible in his presentation of the Therapeutae, a group about whom Philo reported and whom Eusebius considered to be the first Egyptian Christians.5 The result is that Eusebius recognized Philo to be exegeti- cally closer to Christianity, and religiously closer to Judaism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]