KEIMPE ALGRA 155-184.Qxd

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

KEIMPE ALGRA 155-184.Qxd Ο Ζήνων ο Κιτιέας και η Στωική κοσμολογία: μερικές σημειώσεις και δυο συγκεκριμένες περιπτώσεις. KEIMPE ALGRA Η έκταση και η φύση της συμβολής του Ζήνωνα στη Στωική φυσική και κοσμολογία είναι δύσκολο να θεμελιωθούν. Η ανακοίνωση αυτή μελετά μερικά από τα σχετικά προβλήματα. Η χρήση της ονομαστικής ετικέτας "Ζήνων" από τις αρχαίες μας πηγές δε θα πρέπει πάντα να αξιολογείται επιφανειακά, και η απόδοση καθώς και η διευθέτηση του υλικού του Hans Von Arnim στο Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (SVF) δε θα πρέπει να γίνεται αποδεκτή χωρίς κριτική, για λόγους που περιγράφονται σ’ αυτή την εργασία. Παρέχονται δύο συγκεκριμένες περιπτώσεις αποσπασμάτων, οι οποίες, με μια πιο προσεκτική ματιά, δε θα πρέπει να αποδοθούν στο Ζήνωνα. Τελικά, υποστηρίζεται ότι ο Ζήνων δεν ήταν παραγωγικός συγγραφέας σε θέματα φυσικής, και ότι έτυχε στους διαδόχους του ( σε μερικούς από αυτούς) – πιο συγκεκριμένα στον Σφαίρο, στον Κλεάνθη και στον Χρύσιππο – να επεξεργαστούν περαιτέρω και να συγκροτήσουν λεπτομερειακά την φυσική κοσμοεικόνα της Στωικής σχολής. Αυτό σημαίνει πως υπάρχουν περιθώρια ανάπτυξης της φυσικής και της κοσμολογίας στα πλαίσια του αρχαίου Στωικισμού, και πως, συνακόλουθα, είναι ζωτικής σημασίας να διακρίνουμε πιο ξεκάθαρα, απ’ ότι συνήθως, τι πρέπει με ασφάλεια να αποδοθεί στο Ζήνωνα και ότι τέτοιου είδους "κοινά στωικά" δόγματα πρέπεί μόνο πιθανά, ή μερικά, να ανιχνευτούν σ΄αυτόν. Zeno of Citium and Stoic Cosmology: some notes and two case studies KEIMPE ALGRA 1 Zeno of Citium, as indeed the early Stoics in general, conceived of philosophy as consisting of three interrelated parts: logic, physics and ethics.1 But although Zeno’s foundational work covered all three areas, he appears to have had his preferences. Most of the surviving book titles clearly belong to works dealing with ethics. Zeno’s activities in the area of ‘logic’, on the other hand, were largely confined to epistemology, whereas the development of logic proper was mainly the achievement of Chrysippus.2 In the area of 1 The classical tripartion (logic, physics, ethics) is ascribed to Zeno at D.L. VII, 39 and Cicero, Fin. IV, 4 (both printed as SVF I, 45) with a reference to his Περ‹ λÒγου. On the close ties between the various parts of philosophy in Stoicism, see the famous similes preserved by Sextus M VII, 16 and D.L. VII, 40 (= SVF II, 38; philosophy as an orchard, with logic as the protective wall, physics as the trees, and ethics as the fruits; or philosophy as an egg, with logic as the shell, physics as the white and ethics as the yolk). In line with the tenor of these similes, Zeno appears to have kept to the sequence logic-physics-ethics (cf. D.L. VII, 40 = SVF I, 46), a sequence which appears to reflect the relative importance of the various parts (the focus of the whole system being on ethics). 2 Most of the surviving material on Zeno’s activities in logic (in the broad sense) relates to the theory of the (kataleptic) phantasia: see the texts printed as SVF I, 52-73. In addition there is some evidence on Zeno’s being interested in (the status of) rhetoric and in poetics (he wrote a work entitled ΠροβλƵατα ῾Οµηρικὰ - cf. the catalogue at D.L. VII, 4 = SVF I, 41) and in the theory of language (he wrote a Περ‹ λ°ξεων - ibidem.) He was also interested in paradoxes and the way they might be solved by dialectic (Plutarch SR 1034 F = SVF I, 50) and he may have written about them in the work presented in the 158 Keimpe Algra physics and cosmology Zeno produced at least one work of major impact, the Περ‹ τοË ˜λου, and possibly one or two more. On the other hand we also know that later Stoics – Cleanthes, Sphaerus, Chrysippus, Posidonius – made contributions of their own, and that what in the later Hellenistic and early Imperial periods counted as Stoic physics was certainly not in all respects the system as set up by Zeno. This raises the question whether Zeno’s contribution to Stoic physics can be isolated and to what extent it is possible to trace anything like a development in this particular area of early Stoic thought.3 Any attempt to answer this question will inevitably be hampered by the nature and the quantity of the available evidence. In a sense there is too little: the amount of securely attributable material is limited and there are almost no verbatim quotations from Zeno’s physical works.4 In another sense there is too much: most of the relevant sources are rather late and do not hesitate to report what in their own days was considered to be accepted Stoic doctrine under the name label ‘Zeno’ or ‘Zeno and his school’. The latter problem can only to some extent be neutralized by a constant awareness on our part of the different status of the various sources and of the way in which their aims, methods, biases and limitations qualify the value of their evidence. Apart from this it is salutary to remind ourselves of the limitations of what has become the standard edition of the fragments and testimonies, Von Arnim’s Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (SVF). Perhaps inevitably this collection – including its ascriptions and its sometimes idiosyncratic arrangement of the catalogue as ΛÊσεις. On Zeno’s own use of syllogisms (i.e. his logica utens) see Schofield (1983). A limited contribution to logic proper on Zeno’s part is suggested by Cicero (Fin. IV, 9 = SVF I, 47): ‘de quibus etsi a Chrysippo maxime est elaboratum, tamen a Zenone minus multo quam ab antiquis’. A convenient overview of Zeno’s (possible) contributions to logic in Von Fritz (1972) 93-100. See now also Barnes (1999) 72-3. 3 As yet little work has been done in this area. Some developments in psychology and the theory of cognition have been charted by Pohlenz (1938). 4 An exception is Zeno’s argument for complete conflagration as quoted by Alexander of Lycopolis XII (p. 19, 2-4), a fragment not included in SVF. See on this text Mansfeld (1979) 147-8 and Van der Horst (1996) 321, with n. 33. Zeno of Citium and Stoic Cosmology 159 material – has acquired an almost canonical status. However, for all its merits, it should be used with caution, as the present paper may serve to show. I shall here approach the problem of Zeno’s contribution to Stoic physics mainly by focusing on some of the difficulties involved in our attempts to solve it. I shall first, in section 2, signal some of the features of Von Arnim’s collection of fragments that may be relevant to our assessment of Zeno’s position within the school. Sections 3 and 4 will offer two case studies of physical tenets that have been ascribed specifically to Zeno, both in the ancient sources and in SVF: the theory of the coherence of the cosmos as paraphrased by Arius Didymus, and the definitions of space, place and void which are presented in Stobaeus’ version of the doxography of Aetius. I shall argue that in the former case the ascription of the material to Zeno is at least doubtful, whereas in the latter case it is almost certainly unwarranted. In section 5, finally, I shall try to put these findings into a broader perspective by reviewing what evidence we have, on a more general level, of the position and development of physics in the early Stoa. 2 At first sight the arrangement of material in Von Arnim’s SVF appears to be straightforward and clear: the evidence related to Zeno and his immediate pupils up to Cleanthes is contained in volume I, whereas volumes II and III provide the Chrysippean and ‘common Stoic’ material. However, as the case studies in the next two sections of this essay may illustrate, matters are not so simple. It will be apposite at this point to have a brief look at the general criteria that have governed Von Arnim’s policy of ascribing material to Zeno, and the concomitant assignment of fragments to volume I. To begin with, we should be aware of the fact that the first volume of SVF – which was actually the last to be published – does not 160 Keimpe Algra contain the results of Von Arnim’s own investigation of the sources. It was put together as a kind of appendix to the collection of the fragments of Chrysippus (contained in volumes II and III), which constituted Von Arnim’s original research project in the context of a Preisaufgabe of the University of Göttingen (which he eventually won). Although this shows that Von Arnim in the end felt the need to include the material on Chrysippus’ predecessors as well, he was not prepared to go over the whole corpus of ancient sources once again, and was content instead to use – and where necessary to adapt to his own purpose – the material collected by others.5 In practice this means that he used the earlier editions of W. Wellmann and A. C. Pearson (the latter being itself heavily dependent on the former).6 Hence the selection of material for this first volume was to a large extent governed by Wellmann’s criteria for attributing material to Zeno. A brief examination of these criteria will therefore be apposite for our present purpose. To begin with, Wellmann claimed, not surprisingly, that we should include what are clearly verbatim quotations. Uncontroversial though this criterion may be, it will be of little help in practice, since there is so preciously little – if anything at all – that is ‘clearly’ a verbatim fragment and so much that is not.
Recommended publications
  • Language Logic and Reality: a Stoic Perspective (Spring 2013)
    Language Logic and Reality: A Stoic Perspective Aaron Tuor History of Lingustics WWU Spring 2013 1 Language, Logic, and Reality: A Stoic perspective Contents 1 Introduction: The Tripartite Division of Stoic Philosophy.............................3 2 Stoic Physics...................................................................................................4 3 Stoic Dialectic.................................................................................................4 3.1 A Stoic Theory of Mind: Logos and presentations..........................4 3.2 Stoic Philosophy of Language: Lekta versus linguistic forms.........6 3.3 Stoic Logic.......................................................................................7 3.3.1 Simple and Complex Axiomata........................................7 3.3.2 Truth Conditions and Sentence Connectives....................8 3.3.3 Inference Schemata and Truths of Logic..........................9 3.4 Stoic Theory of Knowledge.............................................................10 3.4.1 Truth..................................................................................10 3.4.2 Knowledge........................................................................11 4 Conclusion: Analysis of an eristic argument..................................................12 4.1 Hermogenes as the Measure of "Man is the measure."...................13 Appendix I: Truth Tables and Inference Schemata...........................................17 Appendix II: Diagram of Communication.........................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Enlightenments
    Copyright © 2011 Margaret Felice Wald All rights reserved STOIC ENLIGHTENMENTS By MARGARET FELICE WALD A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in English written under the direction of Michael McKeon and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey October 2011 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Stoic Enlightenments By MARGARET FELICE WALD Dissertation Director: Michael McKeon Stoic ideals infused seventeenth- and eighteenth-century thought, not only in the figure of the ascetic sage who grins and bears all, but also in a myriad of other constructions, shaping the way the period imagined ethical, political, linguistic, epistemological, and social reform. My dissertation examines the literary manifestation of Stoicism’s legacy, in particular regarding the institution and danger of autonomy, the foundation and limitation of virtue, the nature of the passions, the difference between good and evil, and the referentiality of language. Alongside the standard satirical responses to the ancient creed’s rigor and rationalism, seventeenth- and eighteenth-century poetry, drama, and prose developed Stoic formulations that made the most demanding of philosophical ideals tenable within the framework of common experience. Instead of serving as hallmarks for hypocrisy, the literary stoics I investigate uphold a brand of stoicism fit for the post-regicidal, post- Protestant Reformation, post-scientific revolutionary world. My project reveals how writers used Stoicism to determine the viability of philosophical precept and establish ways of compensating for human fallibility. The ambivalent status of the Stoic sage, staged and restaged in countless texts, exemplified the period’s anxiety about measuring up to its ideals, its efforts to discover the plenitude of ii natural laws and to live by them.
    [Show full text]
  • Letters from a Stoic Chapters
    Letters From A Stoic Chapters Scarey Udell balances beyond while Dion always inchoate his sulphurations plats debasingly, he unbalances so despondently. Vincent reindustrializes polygamously as muggiest Will circumstances her appropriations famish abandonedly. Tight-fisted and underhanded Lazare canalising her scudding plaits while Niven whacks some funny synchronistically. Modern introductions to Stoic philosophy as a knot of life. Spirit down before these letters from? Ch 1 An Essay in Interpretation In all chapter Engberg-Pederson situates his importance among the. Dodgson during slumber, than from one by ferriss tips on. Study Flashcards On Lord cause the Flies Vocabulary Chapters 1-3 at Cramcom Quickly memorize the. A Field grow to a sinister Life 53 Brief Lessons for Living UK title The Stoic Guide alongside a crap Life. He says that event like a sound practices, if you demand attention. Stoics did when it demands, pigliucci offers one is finite is an interconnected disciplines required to a chapter? He is from each! The Roman Stoics Self Responsibility and Affection. Letters from a Stoic by Seneca The John Lennon Letters by John Lennon Yoko Ono Tim Ferriss Harvard Business Review Paw. Arranged thematically in chapters about the topics of judgement externals perspective. Meditations by Marcus Aurelius stoic philosopher and roman emperor Letters from a Stoic by Seneca the. There appeared that from provocations to love is no man is pleasure which prosperity has arranged upon. Stoic Html Seneca Letters Stoic Html Learn what about using the public. So you have a definite purposes. Those who discovered by loving embrace our sense. Detail of thread of chapters 6- of that book The Physical World case the Greeks 1956 Sambursky's account of Stoic physics is also welcome for its own merits for exclude is marked.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoic Invention of Cosmopolitan Politics1
    For the Proceedings of the Conference "Cosmopolitan Politics: On The History and Future of a Controversial Ideal" Frankfurt am Main, December 2006 THE STOIC INVENTION OF COSMOPOLITAN POLITICS1 Eric Brown Department of Philosophy Washington University in St. Louis According to ancient Stoics, a polis is a place, a system of human beings, or both of these things,2 and it is a system of human beings—not just a loose collection—because it is put in order by law.3 But Stoics do not mean by 'law' the decree of a duly constituted authority. They define 'law' as "right reason," which provides "the standard of right wrong, prescribing to naturally political animals the things that ought to be done and proscribing the things that ought not."4 In point of fact, they think that no extant 1 This essay is only a lightly revised version of the programmatic lecture I delivered at the conference. Its first two thirds, which sketch an account of the Chrysippean Stoic's attachment to a cosmopolitan way of life, receive fuller development and defense in Brown (forthcoming), and the last third is more provocation than settled argument. I hope that the many people who have helped me will not be offended if I single out for special thanks Elizabeth Asmis, Pauline Kleingeld, and Martha Nussbaum; their criticisms and encouragement over many years have been invaluable to me. I also thank the organizers and the other conferees in Frankfurt for an excellent experience, and the editors of the proceedings for their patience. 2 Stobaeus II 7.11i 103,17-20 Wachsmuth.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • The Megarians’: a City and Its Philosophical School*
    Chapter 11 MATTHIAS HAAKE – Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität, Münster [email protected] für Norbert Ehrhardt zum 26. März 2018 Megara and ‘the Megarians’: a City and its Philosophical School* When Plato left Athens after the death of Socrates, he first went, along with other members of Socrates’ former entourage, to Megara. More or less nothing is known about his stay there, yet it is possible to ascertain the motives for his decision to leave his native city and relocate to a place where, in the words of the Cynic Diogenes, the inhabitants 1 “feast as if to die tomorrow, and build as if they were never to die at all” . Aside from the * I would like to thank Hans Beck for the opportunity to contribute to this volume. The origins of this article relate back to a paper on “Philosophy and the Mediterranean Wide Web. Connecting Elites and Connections in the Upper-Classes of the Graeco-Roman World”, delivered at McGill in April 2017. I am grateful to Hans Beck and his team for the invitation and the splendid time I had during my stay at McGill University. Thanks are also due to Tiziano Dorandi (Paris), Benjamin Gray (London), Peter Liddel (Manchester), Katharina Martin (Düsseldorf), and Matthew Simonton (Tempe, AZ) who offered advice and input. Anna-Sophie Aletsee (Münster) also discussed the topic with me. I am indebted to all for their generous help. Translations are generally from the Loeb Classical Library, with occasional adjustments. 1 SSR² II Diogenes Sinopeus (= V B) fr. 285 (p. 341) apud Tert. Apol. 39.14: Megarenses obsonant quasi crastina die morituri, aedificant uero quasi numquam morituri.
    [Show full text]
  • Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life
    Passionate Platonism: Plutarch on the Positive Role of Non-Rational Affects in the Good Life by David Ryan Morphew A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in The University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Victor Caston, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Professor Arlene Saxonhouse David Ryan Morphew [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4773-4952 ©David Ryan Morphew 2018 DEDICATION To my wife, Renae, whom I met as I began this project, and who has supported me throughout its development. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First and foremost, I am grateful to my advisors and dissertation committee for their encouragement, support, challenges, and constructive feedback. I am chiefly indebted to Victor Caston for his comments on successive versions of chapters, for his great insight and foresight in guiding me in the following project, and for steering me to work on Plutarch’s Moralia in the first place. No less am I thankful for what he has taught me about being a scholar, mentor, and teacher, by his advice and especially by his example. There is not space here to express in any adequate way my gratitude also to Sara Ahbel-Rappe and Richard Janko. They have been constant sources of inspiration. I continue to be in awe of their ability to provide constructive criticism and to give incisive critiques coupled with encouragement and suggestions. I am also indebted to Arlene Saxonhouse for helping me to see the scope and import of the following thesis not only as of interest to the history of philosophy but also in teaching our students to reflect on the kind of life that we want to live.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and Arius Didymus on Household and Polis
    ARISTOTLE AND ARIUS DIDYMUS ON HOUSEHOLD AND POLIS Newman noted long ago that although Aristotle was witness to the rise of Macedonia “[f]or all that appears to the contrary in its pages, the Politics may have been written while Thebes was still the leading power. Not a particle of Aristotle’s attention is diverted from the pÒliw to the ¶ynow.”1 The pÒliw remained central to his thought. As a result, Aristotle bequeathed to his followers in the world after Alexander, and especially in the centuries which saw the rise of Rome, a number of difficult philosophical and practical problems. While remaining central in many ways to the cultural and social life of Greeks (and of other peoples) it became increas- ingly difficult to make a convincing case for the political and social centrality of the pÒliw as maintained in Aristotle’s philosophy of the state. Apart from challenges from the world of politics and international affairs, there were also philosophical and purely so- cial challenges that needed to be met. Stoicism, in particular, with its doctrine of social ofike¤vsiw, the theory explaining the relation- ship of individuals to family, kin, fellow citizens and the rest of hu- mankind, offered an attractive alternative to Aristotle’s restricted emphasis on the pÒliw. Already in the works of Theophrastus and in the pseudo-Aristotelian Oeconomica we can see a shift in doc- trine. Our sources for Aristotelian political theory in the period after Alexander are extremely limited, and it is not before the age of Augustus that we have anything like an overview.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Moral Sentiments
    The Theory of Moral Sentiments Adam Smith Sixth Edition (1790) pΜεταLibriq x y c 2005 Sálvio Marcelo Soares (apply only to edition, not to text) 1st Edition Version a A . Esta obra está disponível para uso privado e individual. Não pode ser vendida nem mantida em sistema de banco de dados, em qualquer forma ou meio, sem prévia autorização escrita do detentor do copyright. Apenas este e as pessoas por ele autorizadas por escrito têm direito de reproduzir esta obra ou transmití-la eletronicamente ou por qualquer outro meio. Published by ΜεταLibri [email protected] Obra editada e publicada no Brasil. São Paulo, May 15, 2006. Contents A PART I Of the P of A S I Of the S of P . p. 4 C.I Of S . 4 C. II Of the Pleasure of mutual Sympathy. 9 C. III Of the manner in which we judge of the propriety or impropriety of the affections of other men, by their concord or dissonance with our own. 11 C. IV The same subject continued . 14 C.V Of the amiable and respectable virtues . 18 S II Of the Degrees of the different Passions which are consistent with Propriety . 22 I. 22 C.I Of the Passions which take their origin from the body . 22 C. II Of those Passions which take their origin from a particular turn or habit of the Imagination. 26 C. III Of the unsocial Passions . 29 C. IV Of the social Passions . 33 C.V Of the selfish Passions. 35 S III Of the Effects of Prosperity and Adversity upon the Judgment of Mankind with regard to the Propriety of Action; and why it is more easy to obtain their Approbation in the one state than in the other .
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. Paper 641. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism a School of Thought That Flourished in Greek and Roman
    Stoicism A school of thought that flourished in Greek and Roman antiquity. It was one of the loftiest and most sublime philosophies in the record of Western civilization. In urging participation in the affairs of man, Stoics have always believed that the goal of all inquiry is to provide man with a mode of conduct characterized by tranquillity of mind and certainty of moral worth. Nature and scope of Stoicism For the early Stoic philosopher, as for all the post-Aristotelian schools, knowledge and its pursuit are no longer held to be ends in themselves. The Hellenistic Age was a time of transition, and the Stoic philosopher was perhaps its most influential spokesman. A new culture was in the making. The heritage of an earlier period, with Athens as its intellectual leader, was to continue, but to undergo many changes. If, as with Socrates, to know is to know oneself, rationality as the sole means by which something outside of the self might be achieved may be said to be the hallmark of Stoic belief. As a Hellenistic philosophy, Stoicism presented an ars vitae, a way of accommodation for people to whom the human condition no longer appeared as the mirror of a universal, calm, and ordered existence. Reason alone could reveal the constancy of cosmic order and the originative source of unyielding value; thus, reason became the true model for human existence. To the Stoic, virtue is an inherent feature of the world, no less inexorable in relation to man than are the laws of nature. The Stoics believed that perception is the basis of true knowledge.
    [Show full text]