<<

Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB)

The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter

12-1978 Intellectualism in David Keyt University of Washington, [email protected]

Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons

Recommended Citation Keyt, David, "Intellectualism in Aristotle" (1978). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 87. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/87

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. INTELLECTUALISM IN ARISTOTLE

David Keyt University of Washington 1978

I

When Aristotle returns to the topic of happiness at the end of the Nicoma­ chean Ethics (X.6-8) presumably to give us his final and best thoughts on the matter, he says that perfect happiness (he. teleia ) is theoretical activity (the�retik� energeia), that happiness and contemplation (theoria) are coextensive, and that the life of reason (ho kata ton � bios), also called 1 the philosophic or theoretical life (I.5.1095bl9, �.E. I . 4. 1215bl-2, �passim), is the happiest life (X. 7.1177al2-18, 1178a4-8, 8.ll 78b7-32). He goes on to say that the life in accordance with the other excellence (ho kata tl!'n allen areten bios)--namely, the life in accordance with practical wisdom and moral virtue, elsewhere called the political or practical life (I. 5. 1095bl8, Pol. VII. 2.1324a40)-­

is the second happiest life (X. 8.1178a9-22). An'd he draws a sharp contrast between the activities that characterize the two lives: theoretical activity is leisured, aims at no end beyond its elf, and is loved for its own sake whereas practical ac­ tivity is unleisured, aims at an end (other than itself), and is not chosen for its own sake (X. 7.1177bl-26). As for the relation between the two sorts of activ­ ity, Aristotle implies that practical activity is merely a means to theoretical

activity: " •••we work in order that we may have leisure and wage war in order that we_ may have peace" (X. 7 .1177b4-6).

These remarks raise a major and well-known interpretive problem about Aris­ totle's· ethical ideal. and his conception of the best life for a man, for they seem to conflict with things he says earlier in the Nicomachean Ethics and elsewhere. They seem to conflict, in particular, with his account of the distinction between making (poiesis) and doing (praxis) and with the conclusion of the function argu­ ment. In distinguishing making and doing, Aristotle says that "the end of making is something different from the making, but not the end of doing; for good action (eupraxia) itself is� end" (VI.5.1140b6-7); and in arguing that the goodness of an action is unlike the goodness of a product of. one of the arts, he insists that for an act to be good it must be chosen for its own sake. The goodness of a pro­ duct of one of the arts (a shoe or a statue) is a quality of the work itself; but, Aristotle argues, the goodness of an act is not a quality of the act itself. Orte must also consider the agent's state of knowledge, his motive, and his character. For an act to be good it must be done with knowledge, it must be chosen and chosen for its own sake, and it must issue from a stable character (II.4.1105a26- b9). This account of good action appears to directly contradict Aristotle's statement in the tenth book of the Nicomachean Ethics that practical activity, in contrast to theoretical, aims at an end (other than itself) and is not chosen for its own sake.

The conclusion of the function argument is that "the good for man turns out to be activity of·soul in accordance with virtue (kat' areten), and if there are sev­ eral virtues, in accordance with the best and most final" (or "tnost complete", teleiotatc§n)(I. 7.1098al6-'18). There are two interpretations of teleiotate arete. v v 

Dм E¤ ȣ%м м ΃dм tFʑ̥ гм Ȥ΄  '΅ Ĝ ȥ@Άʒм м ‹м Пp Ɯ ͮȦм Oм  ǟ м м qTEv Œȧ6Ɲм  Рŝ?ʓmŞм Ǭ¥̾gF ij м #ȨſÑм ¬Kм ˔%м ǭм ̿·ęм ! м ̂˕  “̃Lм  м ΈǮм  %Ήм Ί>м LJ̀ƞǯ<Йм ³ǰм &ȩ#м n м dм -´м $ ̄ʉм (м ̧́‡Dž м p” м 8)Ɵм  м Ơϭ<Ȫ*˖ Aм м ΋Ž̅ `@! Ĵ м   &ȫ7yм ĝ ­ Šм "м ơм Ȭ ȭЍм !˗® ϫʇ м E ɹ ̆ʔ2м Ϯ0м ΌDZм t+ ' м ΍м ǚǀ͂м ¦м +ʕΎƢм &Ȯ̓Å9мÆ 0м µм ;7м Ώм eм ş§*Őȯ˘ĵ!м ̇.м  ʖм ¶)м ЎȰ ϯ'Òм $"м * ʗм Gм ȱ˙ʘʙϰ ÝYŋм "Dzм ŠPLʚ¾ȲOм Ljм dzм  ǠЊ˚qм 5> "м p м lj м oNJʛȳš"м Кȴ·eм ΐм Џ #м ̈Iм м Α2m‹м $̉ʊ,м ı=м Β м ȵ +̈́ƣΓΔȶм (м őм Εм ̊­ͅŢм 'Bм Nj м ŒǴм >м  Q¾ м ě~ʜС•м Rм –˒—· Тм  'м ¸м njϱţϢ–м ͆%м Ōм Ζм .̋ Ťм  .м Ž-м  6 м “ 3 Ǎм Ƥ̽ϲȷ м 6>

:м "ǵ=м ̨;%м ˓ œУм ͇H‚ %м Ηƥм ϳ˛ Rȸм ͈%ˋм Ğ "Θ Ʀм G ² ˜u ǡ м Ƕ м 4Q²м .м ƧMм !"% ģ˜ м Ƿ¯м /> <м ϴ м м Á5 (Bм ǎʝHм <м   Ћ R0м ȹм Ǣ  м Ι>Κм ~ м Ǹ†м ʞ4м . м м o;ZHv  м ǹ5 м " ˝%Cм İ  Фм °м  ƨм Mƀ0м ťм м Ǻo͉Óм ʟ  Ôм Ėм Nм (ǻм  Ʃм Ŧ 5˞м $(м  м ¹!͊м ¨Ом ʋм м Ǐ м "м ʐƪм Jм ̌͋м Λ ǣZм ĢGÕм ǐȺĶʠʡ4Öм Μ ƫм  м 5м  Ǽм ͯм ǽ««!3м Ν)м   м ķ#Хм Ǿ м Ǒ м Ξ• м Лм p9[Iv Ɓм 5& м Qlv e! ʌм ePv 7Ο!˟Ǥм ʢͰ'Cм 0v ǿʽʾм ʿ м ¡м м  м ‘м J ͌¹м rtkGv м Ãϵ$ АȻvvм dž¢Ƃ×м ǒм (м ŧƃм ЦQм м U϶œ̍ ȼNĸ"-Äм ƄØм ōм Iм Πм ΡȀ ͍м ΢Ч̩м *> :!9 & 9> 3,м ğм ϷʣΣȽ*@м _м Ⱦм ̎ им. ȿĹʤм Ç a ɀq®̏Wм fˠм ! sŔ ƅɁˡ3м Bм ˢƆм ! 0ϸ^͎Ƈɂ£Τм ˣƈм Rȁм м 0ŕ` &gˤΥм ˥Ɖ,м ĤϹ ΦȂƬ  м *> ʥºƭм ƮMƊм ˦˧Χм Ŗм *_м */ м #͏ΨȃШм ̐ м ̑Ƀƒм => )=м ƋɄɺ̡˨м _Jv 4³)Ʌ%Cм ĥ͐м VKv ! Nм ĺ͑м 3 Ȅм ’ ˩м I¯м ! м #м ͱ›`м ŗм ^ȅм Ωǥ¶Ȇ м ͒м K м #§ dЩм Ǔм ‚O м Ϊм ϣȇb͓м 4. 1 7"=> Ϋм άȈH 2м ! м м ˌ̪̒Sм -ƌм έ’"м ˍŘ Ũм $м ! # м  fм ! Ϻ$̓ ƍɆ˪;"2м VƯм 8)@#$%v м ͔ưм 012*:]( &v ˫м ! 3v đáõ1čāřʦùÞDðÌZм ĦĻ̫̬ɇLм Wmv ϻũм '> Ɉˬ ϼɉБƱм ˭Ǝм   âñ[\Ē$žм|XD[Wм Əм Ͳм ͳϽм 0м cм ˎ¥ήм Ǜɻ?м È?!ίΰˮAм м    % 6UHv ʹЉŚ̔ Ɛαм Ƒ͵м ŸɊ̕˯м >sv Ġ͕ɋ"O(œ29Y Ùм ̭k†°м =Bv 0 4-*> 8WYà͖bм (ȉм ˰м dOv fм βȊ м ʧ ВÚм µȋƲм ̮?»ŪlBм γм ̯© ϾϤj м Lƒм δȌ'м ȍ™ʨ̖̗Ȏ˜ūм =TʩЪм É2м / 'v ĎãöïĕĐ$ú1X D{м   м ‡м εȏм ™ м ̰ͶǦHм Ɍм @м ζ)м ¸¦͗  м  ɍГЫм ηм bNv *,;4> ͷм м sś̘͘Ɠ˱м ˲м ικм h м *#;> м м ̱̙λм 6м /μ м ǔм νм ʪ*м м Œ̲Ɏ äм Ĩм Мªʫ„м м rм @Ȑξм Ƴм ]Ŭοɏ¿ɐπ7м ”м ŭ © _Ŏ м #ɑ»åмȑƴм /rм ʬм Дɒ͙ρм ͚ˆ м ςм ɓм м Ů˳ е  м ˆм σȒм ‰Ͽ τ!̚м  ǧˏυм ¼м Ŝ2м ȓм  ɔ&!Эм φȔχм Pm ɕºψм )м ¼м  * $ (+=> ļ ɖTʃϩЮм *> ů  ƔĽ -м #ȕм ˀˁм ωƵм Àɗ͛͸м o  м ľƕм ɘˉˊ ж

ϊ˅íм

! Ű˴м -˵м ̛ м .ĿЕ ə%м ! *%;4 <> 1 91> ϋȖм )> t ͹ɚͭм ɛ ̳ з "ŀ½ ̢́м aMv όȗм ű  ɜªм `Lv м Ѐ¡ƒ ¨м € Ǩ*ƶ£м 2> ύм Șм ͜ŠSː-˶ώм ɝqͺ м ʭͻм Ϗ>ϐм -м RhiCv ./ м Kŏм 4>   Жϑ7wм ˷nϒм ˸ʮЯм ɞм F / Ɩ]Ųм Á!Ϫм šʯ ̴u ʰм #ɟ<м ^Ём ʱ0м !˹м Ł ͝ƗžFм # ϓм ¬ʲм Àɠ͞Ʒм ;м ± ϔɡ м #hæм ĩм ɢ ͟Ϭʈ6м ‘м  6Ђ*(м ! ș&м Ƹϕм "$% Ѓ̵̶ʳаɣ˺ǩм ɤм ɥ˂—Žʂм + ˑÛм ϖ¤м ͼм Yv hMм ϗȚм J̣ͫм  м ! Tłˇʄм „=ƘЄ ´&м  %Ÿçм

E ɦ( bм ɧ!%ɨțм JЅ м %˻͠Ńʴм Ǖ g/¢ йм м м ]ɩм Н ʵėм ϘPм ƹ+͡u  ! ˼м (/м Sм ǖ̜м ϙм +͢i&км "м K&cм Ǘ̝ͣм м   ƺм "м Ȝ'ͤм ƙм nм ɪʍм V'м ! E,м   "#% :ĭyĄèązĉńûďxм Īī:Z\éĆ1ü Ċ9òĔÐCм 5SDnDv ṳ̈̀S м ǘ˽ų ˾м 6  м Ǚͬͽм ̞ м ̦Ęм )'м ˿ІϚ± ¿м Gм + ƚЇ" Зм žʅ ǁxм ÂȝɫŴȞм ɬм ; ƛм $бм ˃lм Ë  Íм ˈʆ& N%м ϛȟɭǪм Êд̟ŅÎĚм >м  ŵɼ&5м  ǂwм  м м Ƞͥм $4м  м ɮʶм   ņм U"ƻм +   м ɽ м  м м #ɯ м м м  Pʷм Q ɰ  Uм #ȡɱ м ! Ϳ̷ !?м r/м & *> V:ëм ē,ó[\}ʸ9ćм ,+v -v" v |1ʹýĈ9$}м Įˆîм IJ:Ĭì÷1,ø1ăþ$1XċAêм !  j$!%м 9 4> Ȣ м ɾ‰м м м ugFv ! ̹ͧ€ ϥɿ  м ˄ ǞǃÜм ġ ̠½ʺм ɳм  Ќ$ 4м !%м 8> # м ̺ ŊϦʀʏƽм *> > ǫ3  лмƾм )м  ʻЈaм ϝ)ͨšŶŇ м ŷɴ&iвм ΀м #kʼм 3> +ͩňŸϞ ʼn м ŹϟɵИɶ4м ̀м Ϡм ̻ ɷм cм 8'м 4f\ v 7.- v !v ôĂÿČ$ {ßĀzÏ,м įͪ; (j kм  ϧ& 7м X^v м ̼żIʁźм ΁3м ΂ϡм ?Dv ls'м ɸŻƿм  ! / / 

E ƭæθ³ǀθ şɱθ θ +łɲθ ˢθ %#'N  Hθ / /   < Əθ ̼!Ʈ ºɗX Ģ /θ  8'./ '3< '*0)(%#< «θ 1ǥ θ ǦƎθ θ < » ɘKɳθ ̗̅ )Ƌnθ &.<  + θ + 1ȑCŃθ „«Ɛθ ̆ń̘θ    ̽fŵ θ yĵɴθ ĿĭIJì2\27Ćć ÿ?">5Û$θ ģ Ȓrˤ̾#θ  θ θ Dȓ̿Ȕd-Ǩθ  ɵ ̃Uə'θ ɚǁθ ʿŶ#θ #Σŷ#̇1θ ™ θ θ ǂθ ʽˆȕθ Ņ¡θ ŠȖQņɶθ (,/ 3< */ /Í%ºθ Aŀ5~ė7ţ\"ò2θ   < AZûëč8ēLđäó?(θ ˥ ȗθ B4θ +#¼w ̈ɛ˽ˀθ 1%< "/%:6%+4'8%< $θ İıijí9θĎĈĀ ɷĐåô5($θ

ķ θ 1ǩƯθ Ňθ ̀Ǫθ ǃR-θ d# ɸθ DŽ΍Uθ ¬θ ́!θ J)Q θ Ιmɹθ θ ƑȘ ͂ șŤX ;̓ưƒθ !(/ ǫθ ň1θ +S Țθ %θ  θ DžÊU)¬θ  ǜΊÃθ ĸθ mˁɺ θ džɻ/˦ θ ʜθ  ¢θ ̙̉ț̱̲θ θ ť˂θ  θ %Ϳ θ ǝ˃ ʼnɼθ ̊ )̋ɽ$θ ^T θ ˄θ ɧθ LJθ ʰ ̈́ i̳θ i'Ȝ.θ Ǭ˅.θ θ θ :θ š˧e θ θ BƓθ ) θ ˨q*θ ʼθ Ljθ !θ θ ɨɣƔθ C§θ < Ê­θ ͅ! θ &q θ b θ θ !θ  θ + ̴6θ IĬθ /  << ďõĉŊ>î{Ŧɾ7θ ĮįAö>(θ  Α θ ½sEθ ʪɜ'0θ  ȝšθ ̚θ θ Q̛ ɿθ .; /Ę$üð?=ŧ]"5(θ Ĺθ , t θ  θ ʀθ ! θ *Ğθ  * θ  Oθ ǘƿ ̜θ 6Ʊθ Mŋʁ  çθ y Íθ Ÿǭθ * (θ * θ ) / ͆ Áƾθ ΛȞœθ ´̝θ Ó Gθ θ θ ȟǞǮÜğθ ƕθ Ōˆ iθ  Ʋ θ Oθ _θ / θ  Ţθ kθ ƒʂΥ<θ θ % θ “θ Ƞθ θ θ Ź WPVΦθ θ  θ ˪΀ ]θ θ Oθ 31ɝˇ'cθ ljΎȡĔθ &/ θ ¨θ θ Β›θ V!)0θ NJáθ ˈ3θ ®Χθ %θ 'Gθ & ʃθ L# θ θ ǯθ §θ ˉ4θ θ ̞θ θ θ ʄθ ɩθ / ,“qθ ͻθ Iθ @θèý=9@Ċ7"ċ\zZθ ĺθ θ ̌ƖÉθ 4θ θ %θ )θ θ ƗȢ ȣźȤ'θ Ώ ®θ ”θ ,ʅ‡TĠθ ͇θ ,ȥΓδθ ͈! θ %θ ǰθ ʆΜ θ /ġθ ¯4θ Îw ɞΔͼΨθ Njθ ΁θ θ J³3θ Ν£DZθ ¾†ɟʇθ +Ȧƌɠ̍θ Iɪō͉θ ¿θ ˊθ Ξȧr!˫΂͊θ ̟͋Ŏ*θ +ɡ+©Hθ  <<$2ĕY8Ýθ uŸK͌θ θ * ,< Aθ  ΃θ ʱθ 1θ ǖ˾/ʈµËθ %̬kθ ͍DzȨθ ̵Żˬ3θ . ʉθ n¾f&,θ dz θ ‚3θ ŏθ ˋθ ȩͽ&ż͎gΕθ nj-ˡθ ˌθ ‚x θ EȪ•θ Žm­) θ  ̠©Gθ F%θ   ȫ θ ž͏ȬΖ͐vθ θ ſɦ'ȭΩθ θ ΟǴȮeθ  Őθ ǵ̡cθ ÔŁZę$÷25ĚŨ5"ā7<θ ĴƳθ /@}ñ@ĂũʊČ"7[($θ Ļ¤θ g6θ  ˭ʲθ  θ Ž4θ ͑θ #θ _M4N cθ °θ Aθ ʫθ ͒θ θ  θ ļ4Ϊθ θ ʳʴθ θ < ɫ4θ '/ θ :͓θ ,Ǎ ʻθ rǶθ Dȯ aÇ'‘θ ǎΐƀ˿θ F–θ Ȱ1̶θ ɬŒθ Πʋʌθ Õ̎` θ -"+/ ˮ͔ž¿θ  b θ —θ ¡͕θ ¨zθ<@θ$ø=€ě"2ă(θ Ľ΅θ θ ǡ¶·ƙθ őθ ˍζ̣(θ Ȳθ °ƴθ :̷θ *‘θ d'̮ƚθ tg'͖Gθ Ɓθ ΡȳǷθ Τ#ʍjNƂθ ×2=98 ʎ>"}?($θ ^ ʏΫθ  θ •̀¼|{͗Ǹθ θ ͘θ vθ  θ -͙ȴÄθ ƛθ "" < #Ṳ̄θ Ǐθ θ ɭ¤lθ θ Fθ ūθ ; ǣ˯3θ ʵkL θ %/ P1θ ɮȵ²θ Ķž-θ  Ƶθ .µθ ǐF θ < +Œ ;œ̥θ <θ θ  ̸θ ! ȶw ¸ǹάθ Dθ θ θ θ _θ .θ  ˎ$θ ľhθ  θ θ ¹#̖-ƃθ -͚θ !‰ θ θ ȷ.Ǻsθ / Ƅ,ÅȸKʐĜθ ȹ&‹θ ǻθ θ ‹²θ  %θ θ . θ Ŕθ ¥0 Æθ Ŭθ ŕʑMθ ̐˰ˏθ θ 6PǙȺ͛θ Tθ Ǘθ Iθ 8ùú~9 j8Y>]Þ$θ Ī-θ Ÿθ ` θ ,+θ ǼƬʺ.!θ oˆX ʒ Ŗ Ȼθ θ ŭ j-͜ʓvθ C -ʔθ θ ǽθ  0΋͝éθ ^Àθ  θ %Ήȼ ±θ 0Ό&θ θ  β ƜMθ ͞θ š¦Ηθ  ː͟#θ uθ Ǿθ   CSΰθ θ ǿ,+Pˑθ ŗθ H  ÅȀȽ.θ ˜ȾKθ θ 6ʯǚ|;%%ƍ¦¯θ ȿ.θ  θ Ɲθ ˱θ ‰͠hÏθ  <5θþ[9ĖŮĄ["ą?ßθ ĩ3θ ɥ;ȁ;θ ͡Ȃ θ %ɤŘ*θ +C,ʕθ ͢  θ ɀʬʭθ θ &˲θ ŽŠ1Ɂ&θ !%79%%-<  %< 0-&θ ˒ƞθ ȃθ  J½ γ ɂαͣhθ / ŠɃ¶θ Rθ ʮ˳΢θ  θ uȄθ . θ –́ θ ‡θ Áθ ̑ͤ¥ªθ BƟθ O̦Vƅʖθ Ɔf'έθ ͥ θ  »Ơθ ȅθ Ì//&θ ĤɄ˴ʗxθ ˓θ Çͦ˔sεθ $/ .; ʘÉ̹˕"YHθͧθ ›Œθ Ǒ êθ ř˖θ ͨ;̯θ ΈÈθ ͩθ Lθ ͪ'Ãήθ ǒθ ·ʙθ  ƇƈX ơ’θ  Ȇθ 4  ( ; Ƣθ ¢θ   Nθ ̧θ '# `ʚθ Ì*θ &θ ̨ŚƉθ Ʌ θ ͫ!θ ů θ θ θ Ǔ/Ðθ Ø2=98śĒ"2ĝ(""ȇʛDθ ™θ ̒ÂɆªθ / ˗̓ ƣθ θ ̺Ŝί˘0θ  ɇθ ̂ θ ĥɈ ͬ˵Uʜθ Ű'ΆGθ ɉͭƤθ  #θ Ɗʝθ R%θ Ȉ)θ ̩0;˙θ θ űθ ˚ )ʞ3θ 5; θ o̪ƶ  $θ ƒ<θ  θ  ; 2; ÂƷl<θ Ɋθ  θ ̔˶ ɋŲʟθ  ͮ ɯθ ĦpɌͯ˷Ͱ/θ θ θ ǔ’ ˛Ǥθ θ θ / ͱθ ,ȉ  θ ¹θ Ä Ƹθ ʶɍ& )θ Ǖθ /θ !ƹθ W)À θ θ 4 $ ( +; &ƥθ θ ħp˸ θ Ʀƺθ ͲƧθ  θ ŝ θ θ  θ  θ W ʠθ Θp âθ Ȋθ aʡ̻θ 6 θ θ ȋ Æθ ͳȌθ 0̄Dθ ˜RSθ ˜θ )6θ .3/6; %θ -ʢθ θ ƨBθ Ɏ ȍθ ʹȎθ $25< BƩθ ʷθ ʸ,* θ Ú ʣ˹  η(θ 1*.09' %!7:;  ƻθ  £ θ θ Eʤθ V θ WS·Ƽθ ´ *θ J˝ƪθ  *ʥ  ʦ$θ  Ḛ̀θ ¸θ θ eθ ̕˞θ ȏŞ θ ʧ3θ θ :ɏθ "(,8; ɐ  ɑFθ ˺θ !θ ”-ɒθ 0Ql ãθ !) θ bʹθ ͵θ ˻˟  ɓaθ Ĩ  ƽÑθ ̫ ɢθ θ Ͷ!θ ͷˠt:θ ų˼ɰθ ͸:͹θ ,—ͺθ ! onɔ±Tθ Ù θ ʨθ ƫ ɕàθ ɖθ Ȑ# ʩθ /1-6; †θ - 4 -

II

issu� raised by the apparent conflict of Aristotle's remarks in the of the.Nicomach�an Ethics with those expressed earlier in the treatise 9 irt other works is that of the relation of the life of practical wisdom and virtue t o the best life for a man--the relation of moral action to happi- Does Aristotle abandon in Book X the view of Book I and elsewhere that nibral activity is a subordinate end, a component of happiness, in favor of the view tha:t it is merely a subservient end, only a means to happiness?

The difference between a component and a means may be iilustrated by the difference between the activity of an ancient choregus in selecting the members of a chorus, outfitting it with costumes and masks, and providing for its training, · which is one of the means to a dramatic performance, and the activity of the chorus in the performance of a play, which is a component. though perhaps a . secondary component, of the dramatic performance itself 10 This distinction is similar to one that Aristotle himself draws between a part (meros) and a neces� sary conditionll that is not a part (E.E. I.2.1214bll-27, Pol. VII.8.1328a21-b4, - 9.1329a34-39). A citizen� for example, is a part of a po li"S"'(Pol. III.Ll274b38-41) whereas property is not a part but only a necessary condition (Pol. VII. 8.1328a33-35). Eating meat and taking a walk after dinner are for some people necessary conditions of health without being themselves parts of health (E.!. I.2.1214bl4-24).

In Book X Aristotle seems to be espousing the view, which I shall call ''strict intellectualism," that theoretical activity is the sole component of the best life for a man and that practical activity has value only as a means to theoretical activity. Some scholars have attributed this view to him without 2 hesita£�on: Alexander Grant, 1 for example, in the nineteenth century and John Cooper today . But some hesitation is in order. For strict intellectualism, as 14 is well known, in addition ta being inconsistent with the doctrine of Book I, has unpalatable moral consequences, which Aristotle (at least in his more worldly moments) would not accept;. According to strict intellectualism it would be right. for one person to steal from or to defraud another in order to obtain the wealth required to have the leisure for theoretical activity, for Qn this vitlw the end justifies the means. But Aristotle says that theft is always wrong: "It is not possible ever to be right with regard to these things [namely, such things as adultery, theft, and murder], but to do them is always to be wrong"(II.6.1107al4-15). Aristotle may be espousing strict intel'le.ctualism in Book X without being aware of its unpalatable consequences or in spite of them. Still, it niay be worthwhile to try once more to rescue Aristotle 1 s ethical philosophy from inconsistency and immorality.

One possibility is that Aristotle is embracing a moderate rather than a strict intellectualism in Book X. By "moderate intellectualism" I mean the view that theoretical activity is the primary but not the sole component of the best life for a man, moral action being a secondary component. Moderate, unlike strict, intellectualism is consistent with the doctrine of Book I. But there are several versions of moderate intellectualism corresponding to the various ways of com­ bining moral and intellectual activity while preserving the primacy of the latter. And some of these have consequences almost as unpalatable as those of strict intellectualism. So it will be well before turning to Book X to sort and grade the various possibilities.

Suppose that moral action; as moderate intellectualism affinns, has value in

· . .,-, ,, ,., . ' - 5 -

itself and not simply as a means to theoretical �ctivity. The value it has 1 independently will then either be commensurable with the value of theoretical

activity or µot. Suppose it is commensurable. · In this case the independent value of moral action can always be weighed against the value of theoretical . activity; and when a situation arises in which one must choose betWeen engaging in contemplative activity and performing some moral action, the activity of lesser value can bes.acrificed for that of greater value with the aim of maxi­ mizing the total value in one's.life. I shall call this the "trade-off" view. According to it, the value of theoreticaLa.ctivity, which for Aristotle resembles the activity of God, is related to the independent value of moral activity, activity that is wholly human, as the value of gold is to silver. The details of this view--namely, how to measure the value of moral and theoretical activity and how to balance the value of the one activity against the value of the other-­ are difficult to envisage, but the view is sufficiently precise for one to see some of its consequences. Since on the trade-off view the value of a morai action can sometimes exceed that of a competing theoretical activity, an adherent of the view will sometimes sacrifice theoretical for moral activity. He wight, for example, trade an hour of contemplative activity for an·act of liberality or munificence. Similarly, the owner of a silver mine might pay his workers in gold. On the other hand, it would be right according to the trade;..off view for a person ·who is poor but intelligent to steal from or to defraud another person if this were the only means he had to obtain the wealth required to have the leisure for theoretical activity. For the value of an act of honesty (in this case refraining from theft or fraui\) can, on this view, be outweighed by the value of a certain amount of theoretical activity. An adherent of the trade-off view will, of course, have scruples in many cases where the strict intellectualist will not since the former, unlike the latter, needs always to consider whether the end of theoretical activity can be achieved without acting contrary t.o the moral virtues and, if not, whether the theoretical activity sought is worth the moral cost.

Suppose, to take the other alternative, that moral action has value in itself and not simply as a means to theoretical activity but that the value it has independently is incommensurable with (and thus cannot be weighed against) the value of theoretical activity. One will want to consider in this case whether theoretical activity is absolutely prior to moral activity or not. If it is, we have the "absolute priority" view. An adherent of this view will act on the precept, Maximize theoretical activity first; then maximize moral activity. Thus he will perform moral actions for their own sake but only when they do not interfere with his theoretical activity. He will never, for example, sacrifice a moment of theoretical activity, however uninspired, for a disinterested moral action, however noble. The consequences of this view are only slightly less unpalatable than those of strict intellectualism. Unlike the strict intellectualist, whose attitude toward any action that neither promotes nor hinders his theoretical activity is indifference, an adherent of the absolute priority view will act in accordance with the moral virtues when unable to contemplate or to do anything that will promote his theoretical activity; but, like the strict intellectualist, he will do anything, however base, that promotes his theoretical activity.

Suppose, to take the final case, that theoretical activity is the primary and moral action a secondary component of the· best life for a man, that the value that moral action has in itself is incommensurable with the value of theoretical activity, but that theoretical activity is not absolutely prior to moral action. There is a view that fits this description. According to it, - 6 -

theoretical activity is more desirable .than moral activity--one would spend all of one's time engaged in it if that were humanly possible, which it isn' t--and is in :this sense the primary component of happiness. But what is most desirable must be pursued within the constraints placed upon a person by his bodily nature, . by his family and friends, and. by his polis. The idea is that theoretical ac­ tivity is to be maximized but only within the constraints of the life of practi­ cal wisdom and moral virtue. Moral activity is the foundation and theoretical activity the superstructure of the best life for a man. Moral action will not, on this view, be absolutely prior to theoretical activity. This view is not simply the converse of the preceding one. The demands of civic and domestic life are so indehni te and potentially s.o all consuming that there would few, if any, opportunities for contemplation if moral activity were given absolute priority over theoretical. Such a priority would violate the primacy of theoretical ac­ tivity. According to the "superstructure" view, the moral life sets certain minimum requirements that must be satisfied before one is· to engage in theoretical activity; but the view does not demand that one should riever shirk a duty, how­ ever trivial, for an opportunity to contemplate. Where the line is drawn will (ho presumably be determined by the moral intuition of the practically wise man - phroniinos).

The fol1owing table displays the various possibilities:

Moral action

component of happiness� not a component (moderate in (strict intellectualism)

F - value of, commensurable with � that of theoretical activity not commensurable (trade-off view)

theoretical activity not absolutely absolutely prior to prior to (absolute priority view) (superstructure view)

III

Ackrill's and Cooper's acute but divergent discussions of Aristotle's account of eudaimonia exemplify in various ways each of the four specific possi­ bilities.

Ackrill maintains that "the question [how theoria and virtuous action would combine in the best human life] is incapable of even an outline answer that Aristotle could accept" ("Eudaimonia", p. 357). Ackrill reaches this conclusion because it seems to him that Aristotle's theology and anthropology together - 7 -

yield a consequence that is irreconcilable with his respect for ordinary moral views. Ackrill's argument, as I interpret him, goes like this. According to Aristotle's theology, the divine is incommensurably more valuable than the merely human. And, according to his anthropology, man is "a compound of 'something divine' and much that is not divine"(p.358). Theoria is the activity of man's divine component while virtuous action belongs to his earthly nature. Therefore, theoria is "incommensurably more valuable" than virtuous action (p. 357) and in the best life for man must be given absolute priority over it (pp. 357-58). Aristotle's anthropology and theology thus lead to what I called the "absolute priority" view. But this view, Ackrill points out, has the consequence "that one should do anything however monstrous if doing it has

the slightest tendency to promote theoria •••"(p.358)--a consequence that Aristotle must find "paradoxical" (ibid.) since he wishes to adhere "reasonably closely to ordinary moral views" (p. 35 7).

"The only way to avoid such paradoxical and inhuman consequences," Ackrill believes, "would be to allow a certain amount of compromise and trading between theoria and virtueus action, treating the one as more important but not incom­ parably more important than the other" (p. 358). Ackrill thus for his own part endorses the trade-off view. But he seems to be mistaken in supposing that this view does not share some of the paradoxical consequences of the absolute priority view and in supposing that the trade-off view is the only alternative available.

Cooper, in fact, attributes to Aristotle a view different from any that Ackrill considers. He finds what I have called the "superstructure" view in the Eudemian Ethics, in Books VII and VIII of the Politics, and in the middle " books of the Nicomachean Ethics--namely, a conception of human flourishing [eudaimonia] that makes provision for two fundamental ends--morally virtuous activity and intellectual activity of the highest kind. Neither of these is subordinate to the other; moral virtue comes first, in the sense that it must be provided for first, but once moral virtue is securely entrenched, then intellectual goods are allowed to predominate" (.£E._. cit., pp. 142-43). Cooper believes, however, that Aristotle adopts an intellectualist ideal of the best life in Book X of the Nicomachean Ethics and that he paves the way for this ideal in Book I (pp. 100, 14 7-48, et passim). By "intellectualism" Cooper means "the view that human flourishing consists exclusively in pure intellectual activity of the best kind" (p. 90)--the view that I have called "strict intellectualism." What leads Aristotle to embrace strict intellectualism, according to Cooper, is his doctrine that "one is his theoretical mind" (p. 168). Aristotle does not, on Cooper's interpretation, completely abandon the superstructure view; the life described by this view is simply downgraded in the final book of the Nicomachean Ethics from best to second best (pp. 177-80).

Cooper ·is led to this interpretation of Book X partly by a philological consideration--namely, by what he thinks Aristotle can and cannot mean by the Greek word bios ("life"). This matter needs to be examined since it raises a fundamental issue of how Aristotle is to be read.

IV

What does Aristotle mean by a "life," a bias? The traditional answe;r · is 6 that each of the various "lives" that Aristotle mentions--the apolaustic, 1 the  - -

- #Z » ɬ!õ  »=וЙ¶ »)וZ  Z . ϩוłӕ  וϕו_Ñē וו 0 » ו » ו« Ӻғ Z « ««וˎ­Bɜ ווו וÑ ו»0M« 0 « L«S « וӾɭǵǶ וȸ וǴ М וŸ ˑϬѬҕӼ9ӽ ו Hː וķ וӻˏЛcҔe¿ / ו# וК וӘϪLȷŽƞ#լMϫ Cˆ« 0 ו˒Ơշͦfҗ ѭҖ ו' ו+Ƈ וNJͥ וBͤ וxB« Ԁɯ וƟӿ Ń וНQ וɮ@ וǷ וƆ וlj ו β̻֋ וV4« -˖ͨ˗ԁӖ• ו˕ơОϧ ו†˔ɱ ϖ Łġ ו͗˓ͧ וѯ0Ϯ ו וƒ ו'γPȹ וɰ וÀɲǸ וד Ĕ Ľ* וϭü ѮW וý וղҙCӗc–ͬ וs.« ԃɴ ו׉*ͫÁ]ҘŅɝ®˚ וԂɳ ו˙Ƣńͪ ѰTͩ˘ Z וþ

וԄǼ »]œ ו ǻ ǍǺ וZ Ĵ 7F:#( » € וNÿ YZ ו:i‹« ˛nj\ž וǹNj źδͭ: וņә‡ וĪПѱҚ וԆСňͮ וѴқAӚ׊ ו ו ו ѳC וW וѲƣX וϯ וР ו¯ƒ; וԅ וı͘ ו˝ וy· וƉ »' וƈ˜Ň »/†{¦ וÐ  ו N וmǐ וו×'Ȼ̼) וФæ ו7ϗУǏ  ו gͯ֩ וϱӛ(& ו ו' ו īSТ ו Y וҜǎMϰɞו"ϋ͏Ⱥ ו?ƤƥͲǓ וɶ וǿÔ ÓdǾ ו&"ͱ˞ɍ וUȽ וǒ¡- וЦ וɵŊ֌ וͰ֪ ו qʼn וХ וÏ וȼ וǽҝ͖Ǒ וĒϲ b ā Z NSKW וͷˡȿ וÚ)ЧҞŋͶ - וԋɸ ֖ וàƊˠhçÙ וȾ<͵ וʹØ˟εζƦÄո וϵ ו Ԋ Uϴԉ וĢ ԇ¢Ԉͳ וĀĈוɷȀϳ&

וѵȂUV וӜˣϷɟͺ ו ו͹—Ɏȁ ו)ҟe£- וɺG@וŎǔb וη̽ȳ וˢԍœϑ1rԎչō͸ וԌˆ וFſ- וÅ ϶ ƧŌ וɹ וЪ וǗ׋ ͚˦ ו D„°ԑϘ ו֢ »¨ וͽǖ ו}ͼ˥֍ וǕˤɀԐ וԏ֗ ו> ו^ͻ Щ וϸ וPѥ z֣Ѷҡӝ וIJҠȃ͙ וž˪ƨ;ő וȄ͜ȅ֘ וǙ Ő וɏ̾Ʊԓ וľ ו"¸(˩ǃθŏ וǘ˨ն$Ԓ ו וϙ͛L ו˧ ו}ɻ ו  Ĭ וҢӞЫϹ"Õ% וF¹ »‘Ÿ! ו]Ϳ֬ ‰f|e« ӟ֫ϻ% וD ZˬϺƪÀ ו 0" 0/ וι™6 ו Ʃœ ו ¤> וЬ ו4ɼŒԔ וǚ ˫Ȇ »+ וˮϚG .¥ ו]i ו ƌ ŕ ו Ю וGǛ ו  וѸ%Эϼ 0 וɾŔԙ וԗɽ וԖ ֈšĂ וԕ ΂׆ŗҥ˰ 0 ו΁t ו=žѹ΀֤% וҤ ו ɠI˯( וȇ²Ͼ 0 וTɿ וԚ ו ƍ וjϽ¦Æ,ң »P2 ו"ʂȉҧ ƁЯ וǜµ˳ ɡ ו%ύ͑Ɂ ו+ӓ ό͐˲- ו וƀ וř֮ ו;Äʁ ו וѺԜ וȈ ו˱ ו4ҦŘ΃΄“ə 0. וΆ˵֎ וЀ$ וҨвϿ ו. ו5ʃŚ ו֯= וԝ ו 0  ו=˴u ו( ΅ƫ וб  וn וȊаt¸ וȌ˸֏Έֲ"׌u« ]q וֱ·?§DŽˊҪеЂ ְ? וʄȋ˷' ו˶Ǝ д וD‘əЁÇ וг וҩ

»Ua‰ »‡ והΊ ϛӡ וƏYŠ ו>պԞ„~³ וb5« ʅŜ˜ו4зו ˺ģҬ וǝ  וĸΉÃж ו ˹ וś3 Ӡ ו{ҫ »> ; וλ˜Ӣӣ וĤӎ́»@л΋ ו Ĺкώ͒ԡ˾Ƭ וԠʆ וй ו͝ ѻ וɂ˽ԟ ו ו˼ וªЃ¨Ϩ$ ו$խ’ v@« vиϜȍ ו Ǟ˻ջ3º »S“ וҰŝԦʉȐ ו͞±Ï וн֙ וԥʈ1́ү ו_ Ԥʇɢ‹ וЄr ԣ* וԢȏ̀ וѼҭм$*Ү ו‡ וá/PѦ’è וμ֑͂Ȏ וɃ˿֐ ו -"'%# וÂʎ ו)ұO΍*Ҳ וʍ וѽ©Ό וʌȑ!! ו ו$֥ ו:ʋ וɣʊ 0, ו וɥ'ӥ ו+19=L5$PT Z ĥӏ̓ӤÈ\Ύ IE וʐRЅɤ וohH:« Ʉ ו », וʏN ï̂ וо וɐȴ š ռɅׇ ̄ ו “ וЇ וʕ@ וʔ֚ וo¢ԩʓ וngG9« ̃Ԩʒ ו  וVv׍ וІ ו ƭƐO וѿΏȒ Ѿ וϝ וʑŞԧă וֳ¼ וϏ͓Ɇ ו҂•¯̅pi וǠ וҁkпҳΒ 0 וΑ‘6 ו `` וҀΐ1֦ וǟ÷øɒѧ וDy‚« ԫʖ” וɑ̈́DžͅԪ ו׎Ԯ֛̊ ו+Δšҵ<3̉ וmdJ« Њ וʙ֊̈Љɧ וoǡ ו²ΓսBɦ̇ וfЈ ו TԭʘҴ וâʗϞŠé ו0̆ וӦ וԬJȓ »Z8 ªš וŤƑVËԱ וϟ̋ ו°; ԰Ҷ וʛ וHţԯ ו¡J וŢɨ ҃ ו Z ĿO0<;8/* ו& р‰Ȕ וʚ¿ ЍLJҹф׈ִ וԴʝ̎€ ו ƒ–у ו ЌÈ ǣ̍ וҸ ו lc¥7« -0 וƮnтÉאс.׏ ҄ וЋȕ וԲʜԳ ו·ȟ/ וÏҷǢ

»u?« R3 וUsƲËҺ´ЎƳȖבԶʞ ו2 וӧ҅̐Ե ו ו*ĩוΗ וƱΖӐνַ ו ̏ וֶƯư 6* ו וхÌΕֵ וĮ וξć› ו וƴΘ̑Ϡ ו0³͟ וʟz וɇվȗ® וцԷ וǥSӨ וָ›/#Y« j« ҆һƓ וǤ ֜ וq« #¡–« ҽ#ԻʣҾĄ~ ו+ʢ וT¤”« ֝ʡ ו҇F҈Κș וө וʠŦԺ ו+ť 0( ו וQԹ וwш ו։ŻƜΙֹ Ҽ וΜĉ וW« O£« Ƃx—}$ וֻ{ˋӪ+ùĐđծ ו­ֺŨ וגԾŽy!8 ו וQȚ֒Λ̕ 0  ' ו ԽK̔̓ וԼʤŧ

ו ĺΟCÊщA ו ̘ וlӫ 0 »§ וǦȜž¨ЏՁ9Ղǧ ו̗ וɈ(1 ו9Ξ ו̖ וƵΝ ϡ וț͠ҿ֞ וՀʥ וļŠũԿ וWū6/ וH] ו#5ȝð ċ Մ-ו7Ɣ̚¦̛êĞğĠĊX‹ וÍ̙ וɓѨտ וƶ ”x0Ӭ ו Z ĻΠՃ JZA23GAZ!"ZB34H- וĵŪ֟ וՈʫ וÐƷE ו~ʪ ו†<ο Ӏы וъ҉Ҋ§̞Շ!ûÅʩ1 וʨ̝ וȞŬΡՆ^88j וʧ »* וß̜Ĝ וՅʦ וƄӂ Σ ו½̢ וրӁ K„Š›« 2 וʭȟ וь וʬ$ ו5lՉ וŮ̠А9̡ӭ וu!aƃǪ ǩ̟ ו=,5 וǨ ŭ ו΢ I ɘѫ וճʱ͌ ו'wA« ֧ƹρςȡБƺ וπ͇ɉ וՍʰ וՋʯ#Ռ וʮ̣ ו¤ɔӒ וsΤցǫ Ƹ ו:d ו"Ƞ ¬юэ וկ͆ ו ŒՊ ווmÒ ו½Ɩ̤  וʵÁ k`I« וՐʴ וӮ#ֽñ 0* ו_ וՏˆYוւœ!Čč  ו|ʳ #0 וƕяwּ וՎʲ ו 4 ו ҋ´ וɚȣ͋) ו« ÊʶQŽ וď ҌΦ'#»ƅו̦!σ͈֓Ȣ?Ď וɕѩօ ו Ɋ̥ וՑ וò־ӯ^ВLjªքΥ וϢƗ R¥ וƻѐփӃ ו"τOÎȦ ו̩Ւ  « Ez¢ƒ« וʷ וƽϣƘ̨.ȥӰ וƼJ̧,֠ וǬȤ¬ӄ6͍մֿ וɋ

וѓ.Χׁ וՖ ו׀ɩ. ɛ  וZ וǮ; »1 »& וƙ•ђ וёǭ֡ וijӅ͡ וՕʸ וՓŒůՔ וdžωȧ ו¼— »Œ[ וįֆձʺȩӔі »_ וV וȨՙ 0! וű‚ʹ וҎŰӆXL$Ϋ וГ וΪ¶ѕ »’ " וΩ>ɖȵ ו՗є՘Ψ ווÛ ҍ 0 0 ו º ו g ו՝Дǯǰó ̭ וĦӈ Ӳ՜ј\ά ו՚ʼ՛ וƾ#͕ї 3̬ ̫ וÇ̪ÎȪ  וŲ וʻӇ »ǂέή֨ וդ˂Ӌ וŸև[џ ו ȯ +0 ו RQZ ը˅͊Ѫ ו&% Dz̴Í̵ ו3ў)Ȯէ˄ Rɪ ו2 וґѝӴµ וŷ & וϐ͔€ ו וI ߘ֔ וą ו, 0&  וˈ ѡ וKȱ וȰ̸֕ וˇ וdz%ϥ̶ɫѠE!8ˆ̷ΰ וӶ וӵׄô וZ %0 וN0« åA¾ÞÒ ו ˌ וӸӹ ו%C,>Z '(?DM6XZ -« ħӍ̺¾իѤÆα@&% וî ӷժ̹ וȲ,7 וÜÝ Ϧ $0 - 9 -

'qua') locution as part of his standard terminology to signify one aspect of a .. . thing in abstraction from all others. He says, to take a simple example, that "the infinite qua infinite is unknowable" (Phys. I.4.187b7; see also III.6.207a25..;. 26) meaning by this that an infinite object need not be completely unknowable but only in the respect in which it is infinite� if a surface were infinitely long but only an inch wide, one could know its width but not its length. Or, to con­ sider another example, speaking of natural science Aristotle says that "there are (he many statements about things merely qua moving kin()umena), ,apart from what . each thing is and from their incidental properties" (Met. M. 3.1077b23,....24). .

There is now an answer, or a sort of answer, to a puzzle that arose in ana- lyzing the function argument. It seemed that of all living things God alone . lacked a distinctive function since his only activity, contemplation, is an activ­ ity in which man can share. The answer is that man does not engage in this activ­ ity as man but only as possessor of someth ing divine--namely, reason or nous.2 3 In so far as man can contemplate he is a god himself.

v

The way is now clear for an interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics X. 6-8 that minimizes· th e co nflict between it and the rest .of the work. Aristotle begins his final and consummative discussion of happiness by considering whether happiness lies in play (X. 6). This preliminary discussion raises at least two interpretive questions. First, what exactly is the view that Aristotle is considering? And, secondly, what contribution, if any, does this discussion make to Aristotle's ultimate conclusion that perfect happiness is theoretical activity?

The word paidia, along with two other words that figure in the .discussion in chapter 6, paidikos ('childish') (1176b33) and paizein ('to play like a child'-'- ' then: 'to play', 'to jest', 'to dance , 'to sing', 'to play at a game') (ll76b30, 33), is derived from the word pais ( ' child ' )(l176b22, 23). This derivation undoubtedly assists the conclusion of chapter 6 that happiness does not lie in play (1176b27-28): since a pais is ateles (undeveloped) (see Pol. I.12 .1259b3-4), paidia Gan hardly be the telos (end) of a man (see !·!· II. l.1219b4-8).

The ran ge of application of the word paidia is very wide. In , for example, paidia covers among other things children's games (Polit. 308D3-4, Laws 64 3B4-D4, 793E3-794A4), war games (Laws 829B7-Cl), singing and dancing (Laws 803El-2), the mimetic arts from dancing to drama (Soph. 234Blff., Rep. 602B6-10, Polit. 288Cl-10), religious sacrifices (Laws 803El), puns (Grat. 406C3-4), and carousing (Prot. 347D6, Laws 673E8ff.). Human life for Plato is divided into just two ph�--play (p"rldia) and seriousness (spoude) (for the dichotomy s ee Rep. 602B8, Polit. 288C9-10, Laws 643B6, 647D6-7, 732D6, 797A7ff., 942A8).:...;.play being a prep arat ion for, a means to, or a relaxation from serious endeavors (Laws 643B4-D4, 796Al-D5, Phil. 30E6-7). It is not so clear what act ivitie s Aristotle counts as paidi ai , for he is not as lavish with examples as Plato. But a few examples may be gleaned from the Nicomachean Ethics and the Politics. He mentions children's games (Pol. VII.17.1336a21-30) and urbane and witty conversation (eutrapelia) (!.N. II. 7.1108a2 3-26 and IV.8) and reports the common view that the purpose of sleep, drink, music, an d dance is play and relaxation (Pol. VIII.5. 1339al4 -21) . Interestingly, in chapter 6 Aristotle alludes to the things valued among boys (1176b22), to those who are ready-witted (eutrapeloi) in the  E 

 .ʪ  ʪ ȯ ʪ *(7A (L !ʪ Ǹʪ űʪ $ųrʛʪ ȗ ʪ  ±(è   $*'(), "  ʪ "Mʪ ƶ-ʪ ‰ ʪ  ʪ ǹ ʪ Ʒ ʪ /ƱŴ/ #ʪ ʪ Ĉ Ŀ)'ʪ

  ˆ  // Įʪ Ș4Îʜʪ %ŵ+,ʪ  ,ʪ îxƸ•ʪ 4A‘KĖˆʪ !ė+7ʪ ,ʪ ĉY‘7;ʪ     N,ʪ  ʪ įʪ ,Bʪ ςǺ ’ɇɔ(ʪ ƹ ʪ ʪ #L E   ɕNʪ \7ðŶ7ʪ Ȱʪ ƺʪ ñxǧtĘò+ę\ʪ $ʝʪ ʪ  ʪ S+B—ʪ  !ʪ İʪ ! ʪ ņʪ 0ŷ%ʪ  ʪ ЁǨʪ 4ŸB7ʪ ;tʪ ‚4 ʞ22âʟʪ  ʪ Ňʪ  ʪ  ʪ  ʪ ʪ ǻʪ $ʪ ,yʪ Ǽʪ  ȱʪ z%ʪ     Åʪ ɖʪ ʪ »ȲŹɗǽƻ1ʪ ʐ%ʪ f ʪ ɘ ʪ 4DC=4JFI<:L Ǟƨ _ʪ  ňʪ ǾƼ–ʪ ľĚʪ %;/!&

½ƂɦDžʪ ȃ ĴĜʪ +%ʪ Öʪ ʪ Ȟ!łʪ ɧŖ ʪ ȟƃ!ʪ džEʪ ʪ  ʪ  †ʪ ĵʪ ƒ4 •·ʪ ɨ ʪ Ȅʪ ƭʪ 5ǫ*]¤ʪ ŗ ʪ ɩ ʪ ʪ ʪ $ʪ Řʪ ʪ fʪ "ʪ ×<ʪ Jʪ Ķ‡ʪ  `ʪ  <ʪ Fʪ Ø!–ɪ  ʪ ?ʪ  E ÷vLJ#ʪ  ʪ  ĝʪ ȴʪ ʪ $ʪ Ɍʪ ǡĎʪ ʪ lʪ ʪ ʣ ʪ ʪ řʪ Ƅʪ ʪ ķʪ ʔ:ʪ  % , ÁŚʪ ȵÙɍ6ʪ « ʪ Ʈ(¸ʪ ȶãʪ ʪ ~ʪ ɫ„Ɏ”śʪ Ư ʪ DE zȷʪ  Ƿʪ ›Ǧ ɬ)ʪ êȅʤʪ &>>R°ï²29R¡ºʪ vʪ ʪ  ʪ ȆĞ ʪ  ʪ Ljƅ ʪ lj ʪ Ɔʪ   ʘÚʪ ȹ=ʪ Ƈʪ 6ďʪ ʪ Ǣ ʪ ɭʪ ɮ ʪ Pɯƈ#ʪ 6ʪ 6ʪ `ʪ Ɖʪ Ɗcʪ ,(9. --6>'L ¾ɰȇʪ †“^ʪ  ʪ Ƌʪ ʉȖʪ cʪ Ûʪ "ƌ ʪ ɱ Eʪ NJNj” ʪ G=ʪ ɲŜaʪ 5VpȺʪ ȠCǣʪ  ʪ % ƍøhʪ ȡnj ʪ  Ǎ: ĐǬ ʪ Ȉ-ʪ ʪ  ʪ ]oɏƫǭʪ ʪ ŝ ɳğʪ E åʪ E QÊʪ j Ȣʪ ǎ ʪ Ǥʪ ɴʪ ëʪ ʪ  Ġʪ Ǯʪ Üù~äʪ "ƎLŞʪ 3ʙǏǐǯ(8Qʪ "E Z=K Lʥʪ ĸʪ ġ˜ʪ şGŠʪ úMɵƏʪ ûʪ ȉȻʪ ʕƐšʪ ĢʚüģǑĤYĥʪ ǰʪ Ƒʪ ɶ ’ʪ =ȼĦʪ wʩ đʒʪ Lʪ Ţ ȣʪ ţ ʪ ɷ ɸʪ Ȋ ʪ 1ʪ ǒ%ʪ ýǓƒɐ'ʪ Âɹʪ Ȥ ʪ ȋʪ ɺʪ ŃÝGʪ DZ1ʪ ń ʪ dÞ(ǔ8ʪ ËeȌȽʪ ßƓaʪ  €ɻʪ Ƭʪ ʪ - ʪ &®>µ¶ 2Ǖǖ)8ʪ

@Ųʪ ɼ ʪ ʪ "ʪ ʪ Ⱦʪ mʪ ^Ɣʪ Ĺʪ [Ť ʪ  Ēʪ E Çʪ ȍ ʪ ťʪ Ž ʪ ƕDzʪ ȿʪ ȥɽʪ Ǘĺʪ Ŧ ʪ Wʪ 3ǘ.Ɩdz ɾ'ʪ É ʪ Fʪ !ʪ  ʪ  ʪ ʖʪ ħ ƗǴǵ ʪ æƘ ʪ çʪ ìʪ  %ʪ ʪ Xʪ ƙʪ  ʪ ɿŧʪ ʀŨʪ Šʪ ʗƚIʪ er"ʪ ʁũ ʪ ‰ ƛʪ /ʪ Ɯʪ Ȏʪ  Ĩʪ Ū Ȧn ʪ Ļʪ $-'ʪ

ÍUʪ

Uʪ ū Kʪ  ¿K+ʪ Ɲēɀʪ !ʪ Ɇʪ Oʪ ƞíʪ  ʪ 3ʪ œ*#E Ŭ ȧƒʧʪ ǙƠ 8ʪ Æʪ ʂ Cʪ Fʪ  ʪ ŭ:ʪ ʓ ʪ p“ʪ } ʪ ʃlʪ  ưʪ Ȩ*ơʪ  ʪ ÀɃ{I1ʪ  ʊ./ʪ ʪ  ʪ &, @ ʪ Oʪ ʪ (ǚIʪ ʪ ĔƢļ E‹ʪ ʋā­ʪ @ ʪ Ľʪ ʪ 5ʪ  ʪ (Ǜʪ  ʪ  ʪ /ʪ ŅǥĪʪ Ƕʪ  īʄʪ ʪ ȩmƣǜɒȪŮZàǝʪ ůƤ?ʪ  ʪ kʪ „d-*Ăʪ 0 ʌʪ ăȐʪ ȫwʪ $Šʪ Ű ʪ  E ȑɓ'ʪ Ìʪ  ʪ Œƥ0ʪ  ʪ ĄȒʅʍʪ Ȭʪ .ʪ ʪ $¹ʪ

L Ʀʪ ąáĆĬʪ "Ƨ ʪ PǠ/ʪ &ƴ ʆ1ʪ D 103#ʪ E ć5ȭ Ʉ3ʪ E  . 2(  L L ȓʇMʪ Ÿʎb ĭ£&³´ 9¯¨9 9?ʪ [Ȕ=Ȯ Ʌʪ 1?@338BB L "  #, 6ʪ Èʈ'ʪ !  & + ,  9 

  L ˈɒßþǢ˴ S°¶,,@·¸AË˴ Ⱥ˴ HbBU®ÇȺ+˴ ÝWÖ¬¯A±²ÀAò»+½˜˴     9 ( 8Ê  .˯ˬ˴ Hb>.94L(/ b 097MWXb  ¨VxY ¨ÁZZi>qVˆ«Ê 0Á¬1­uJ¨„x$%8! '*Ê #7˴ H>#DBP9#: b GIDb &.˴ Ú3˴ >  U 9 ˴  (.˴ śȹ˴ Nj=Ǥō˭˴ ‰‚˴ YˊOIJ ˴ '>:P(8 b ?CU)Eb  8˴ &D@K15N;b 9 ÙŤ¤˴ H: 2<(J* +, b A!396KY7b 9b ǥ ˴     "& Ê -(b

9 ij˴ J]^[TO`_Rb ˋęĴ˴ Ě0ƍʀɳ˴ Ŏ˴ ě/ŝ?˴ ÌɓȦǦ˴ K[SaQ\b ʁIʂ˴ āʻ˔ ˝˴ Š;ŦĶȨɬì‘˴ ȼ:ķɴɵĸ˴ !39 ®Ê  " .9 CV[žKLÊ 4 '9 -/ 5# &9 ‹u ˴ Ǝ ˴ #Ǩ˴ E ˴ ʼnjĂǩ*˴ (d˴ 2++,Æ@"Ǫ“¥˴ Õ˴ ŧ˴ v<óˌʄ]˴ Ĝ˴ l ˴  ˴ ˴ ! ˴ Rb ɖ!| ˴ ʅʆ˴  ˴ Z€F˴ ¯]W‘ŸV¾r?8yÊ "P˴ ˴ Ⱦ8 Ə Y˴ (  ˕ǍQ˞˴  #:x Ê D ˴ Ũ ˴  ŗ˴ 2+³,,"V@V*˴ ũʇ˴ NŏĹ ˴ 2ɗ˴ ăȩ0 ǫ ”˴ a Ȗ ˴ Œĺ˴ Q^Ɛ˴ ĝƑȓ' ƒ•˴ Ɠ ˴ ¿^Wš¤M¾r?8{Ê Ąǎ$˴ o í Ļɰ- Ǭ˴ ˰à ˜ȿ ˴ ʈ ˴ ˴ ǙŐ˴ ˴ ɘ MʉŪ˴ ąâǭ˴ i˴ ˴  ɀƔ˴ Ǯeő˴

Í ˴  ˴ -n œ˴ ū˴  ˴  ˴ ˴ $Ğ˴ ə!ȏ ȐȑȒ ¦˴ .š¤Ê šŽWÊ °_rŽ\Ê r¾Ê HšV¨Ê ‰š¾Ê ¤ÁxWÊ ˍʊ˴ ˴  ô6;˟˴ ʋ˴ ˴ ƕ˴ 7˴  ˴  Ɩ ˖Ɨžh H˴ Ɂʌ˴ Ĥr±jŽ\Ê ğɚî-˴ p˴ ɛ$_ȍ !˴ 5˴ ʍF˴ õǯ˴ rɜ ‡˴ ¨ÁœV¤k’¥Ê Ȫ˴ öa˴ wŬ ƘĆ˴ &Ġ˴ ć= ˴  ǜ(˴  ˴  ɂ˴ ȫ˴ ʎ ˴ %˴ Oɝf÷ ɶ˴ ˒N˴  ǝ˴ .š¤Ê 2Šš²`N¤Ê 29 8z{šÄ¨Ê ʏ˴  ƙøǰʽ˴ xŭ˴ ˴ DZg ʐ˴ Ȭ ˴ 8³´¤r=ÁµV¨Ê ˴ ƚmĈ ʑ˴ =Ů˴ ʒů˴ %˴ A•Ž¨rDW¤VHÊ ġ˴ ȗ˴ lŽA|ÁHWÊ Dz˴ J˴ ˴ ļ Ǐãdz˴ ʓ˴ Ș˴ Ėƛ˴ w äʔ˴ ' Ɯʕ}˴ f8œœrŽW¨¨Ê .Á ¶aO¤‡š¤V Ê ˴ ?šŽ@{¨ršŽÊ ˴ >Ş¡)ÜƉ˴ Ǵ˴ *9 ` ˴ Ɲ˴ I˴ Ű 7K3 ˴ ǵ5G)˴ 2´µÄBÅTB*Ÿ£ɞ[˴ ű˴ șǟ˓ʖ˴  ˴ b˴ Ǡ˴ ˴ ɮ˴ ɐ~eŘǐT)Xƌ˴ ŲɃ ˠ˴ ƞŒ3˴ ˴ ʗ˴ ù˴ ˴ ǚ˴ ˴ åĉ8. ˴ Äm³fÊ %Ț\Ľ)˴  #8}Ê X˴ ¨šxÁ¾rš‹Ê šXÊ ʘų˴ Śǘ ˴ ÄV8vŽV¨¨Ê Ɵ˴  Ģ.˴ ˴ Ơ Ƕơ ˴ Ċ ț˴ šYÊ ċ ;˴ 9 Àb3¾Ê ŴɄ  ɷɸ˴ ȜtƢ ˴  ˴ Wr¿`P¤Ê >ʙKǷ˴ q9˴ ɅɟČ> ˴  $ ˡ˴ ɹ˴ ȝ˴ 8EIr¿r“8xÊ Ɇ#ƣ §˴ Î˴ GN˴ ˴ o ˴ ˇ˴ 1[h :˴  ŵj˴ Ƥ0ɇ˴ æ˅™˴ˆ Ȟ˴ 9ģɠ˴ ˴  ˴ ˴ #˴  tm!˴ ÁV¨´n”ŽÊ 8=šÁ¾Ê ¾cQÊ ş ʚ˴ c˴ Ïɡƥʛ Ǹ˴ Ʀ Ĥĥ˴ Ŷ ˴ ǡ˴ #Ƨ ˴ ʜ˴ "/˴ Ħ˴  ˴ ˴ ľȟ!ŷĿ ħ˴ Y˜¦ ¾f8·Ê J˴  u Ĩ^ĩ˴ ˴  ˴ Ÿy˴ z˴ 4¾¿¡r;Á¾V¨Ê ˴  Ī˴ 8A¾Á8x~ÆÊ )9 čç Ps€4˴ ˴ ŹȠ˴ ɢ˴ ˴ ʝ˴ 8 <˩˴ 79  ʾ$ƨ˴ ź ˴ Ď Ǒʞˎ;ŀ˴  Ɉ ˴  ˴ c˴ ¾_RÊ %˴ ]˴  5ī ˴ Ʃ ˏĬ˴ 6˴ ʟ˴ ˴ / ʿǹ˴ {˴  ˴  {(ˢ˴ ŻZ˴  fːŁ ˴ ɉɊ 4 ¨˴

 ©˴ ƪ  <ǔ H˴ ɑ' ˴ ȭ łɱ˴ ˴ ƫȡʠr=Ƭ ˴  ˴ Dɣɺƒ ˴ A•ŒAÁ¨r–Œ ¸d8¹Ê J˴ Ǻƭ˴ è#ȢƮ˴ Ư˴ ¿fW—¢W¾oB8€Ê ďʡư˗yˣ˴ ˴ 0¾V§8ºoÃV ÇÊ %  ˴ ¹f8¿Ê ż˴ ʢŽFǒ ǻ˴ =r5¨Ê Ʊ˴ ˴ ɋ ʣ˴ "ƲȮɻ˴ Þ ˴ VÅ3A»xÈÊ g˴ ʤ˴ ȯ\˴ ,9 ʥ ˴ é ɤ˂ȣC˴ Òq˴ D Ǽ˴ 0&˴ ˴ ɥʦš˴  Ñp Ń˴ ǽƳ˴ )ž ˴ ſ˴ "˴ 6 ˴ œ˴ Ǿƴ ˴ ˴ Ȱ˴ Ɍ~˴ '  ˴ ˴ ƵȤŠǿ3˴  ĭ˴ ȱ˴ ɦʧdĐªȸM˪

Ȕ kʨ ˴ rŽÊ G˴ ˴ 6˴ V{¨WÊ  ėǗ ˴ ˴ "79Fb -šQ¨Ê ˴ ȕï˴ ƀv˴ ˴  úń ˴ '˴ ƶŔ˴ ˴ ˴  ˴ ˴ ˴ ȥ˴ ˙Ʒ ˴ ʩʪđEȀ˴ EĒˀ˘Ƹ˴ ɼ˴  ʫðzjˤ˴ %ȁƹȂ˥˴ &˴ ŕ˴  –˴   ɽˑȎ˦˴ ɍ|­˱˫ĮC˴ Ø˴ ƺ˴ Ɓ˴ Ƃ/˴ ɧŅ˴ ˲:˄˴ - ɾ/9ʬƻ ?˴  ˴ Û ņ˚ɨʭ˴ &˴ /8Á¼erV£Ê ȃƼ?˴ Ƌ˴ ûɿx˴ ˴ ʮƃ˴ üŇ:ʯ˴ ʰȲ -Ȅ˴ ȅƽř˴ 9˴ ˴ ñ˴  ˴ 5˴ ʱ ɩ4 ƾ ˴ Ð˴ W˴ Ƅ(˴  Ţ}˴ ǁ˴ ©VB»s™Ê  ÿ$˴ +¤r¨¿•¿‚V¨Ê Á¨WÊ šYÊ ¾gWÊ Äš¤FÊ

#b Ɔ(nţ˴ LL˴ ȶ ˴ Dž> ˴ Ê˴ 7ʶ˴  ˴ Ó !kǓƇ˴ ý˴ ˴ 1į˴ R 0 ȋR˴ ˴ ʷ˴ A•‡œƒV½WÊ ˁ#˴ Ž  ˴ —˴ ˴   džH˴ $)YPV(%5b (b =VpŽ\Ê :V¨®Ê ˴ LJ˴ wrŽI)Ê ?7œ¿Á¤WHÊ M˴ Ô ! ˴ 89 ˴ 1˴ „ɏŖʼn  ›˴ ˴ ˴ ›V ZVA¿Ê ȷ†˴ʸŊȌŋǖ ˴ Ljʹ*˴ Ĕ˴ <ƈlj ˴ ɫ˴  ĕʺ˴ NJ iŌ˴ - 12 -

(102lbl4-23, Phys. VII. 3. 246al3-16). (3) having reached its end (telos): captured in English by such expressions as 'fully realized' and 'fully developed' and predicated, for example� of an adult in contrast to a child (102lb23-30, Pol. I. 12. 1259b3-4).2�

If teleia has sense (1) in the expression he teleia eudaimonia, then Aristotle's conclusion expresses the strict intellectualist view that complete (or total) happiness is theoretical activity. If teleia has either sense (2) or sense (3), then his conclusioh can be given a weaker, moderate intellectualist interpretation-­ that perfect or fully realized, as distinct from complete, happiness is theoretical activity.

Both formulations of Aristotle's conclusion will thus bear a moderate intel­ lectualist interpretation. Although such an interpretation even seems indicated for one of the two, the perfect ambiguity of the other makes one hesitate to claim on the basis of an analysis of the verbal formulations alone that such an interpretation of Aristotle's conclusion is demanded. One must also consider Aristotle's argument. What sort of intellectualism does it entail--moderate or strict? If Aristotle's argument entails one view but not the other, this is a 3 good reason for attributing the one rather than the other to him. 0

On one interpretation strict intellectualism is entailed by that part of Aristotle's argument which is based on the philosophical idea that the activity that constitutes happiness is activity in accordance with excellence. This subargument opens (ll 77a12-21) and closes (1177b26-1178a8) chapter 7, though its leading ideas are introduced at the end of Aristotle's discussion of play (6.1177al-ll). Most English translations of these passages obscure the simple relations between the key terms of the argument and make it almo,st unintelligible, so a few elementary comments about its terminology are in order. The argument is based on the noun arete ('goodness', 'excellence', 'virtue')(see 1177a2, 10, 12, 17, b29) and three forms of the comparative and superlative of its simple adjective agathos ( 1 good'):

comparative: 'better' superlative: 'best' belti�n (1177a3, 4, 6) beltistos kreitton (1177a6, b26) kratistos (1177al3, 19, b34, 1178a5-6) ameinon (1178a3) aristos (1177al3)

Rendered literally, the argument of ll 77al.-21 runs as follows:

1. Happiness is activity in accordance with goodness (al-2, 12). 2. And the activity of the/ better part of a man is better and hence more conducive to happiness (a5-6). 3. So the activity of the best part is best and most conducive to happiness (see al2-13). 4. Reason (nous) is the best thing in us, and its objects are the best of knowable objects (a20-21, see Stewart, ad loc.). 5. Therefore, the activity of reason is the best activity and the one most

conducive to happiness. As Aristotle expresses it, " •••the activity [of reason] in accordance with its proper goodness will be -he teleia eudaimonia" (al6-17).

The premisses of this argument entail, not that theoretical activity is complete happiness, but only that it is perfect or fully realized happiness. - 13 -

But when Aristotle returns to this theme at the end of chapter 7, he seems to advance beyond his earlier c laim that reason is the best (but not the only) thing in us and to claim now that a man and his reason are identical: "This [viz. reason] would also seem·to ·be each man, since it is the authoritative and better part. Thus it would be-;ddif he were to choose not his own life but that of someone else" (1178a2-4). Similar assertions occur in two earlier passages in Book IX (4.1166al0- , 23 8.1168b28-1169al8). However, the element or faculty with which a man is (or seems to be) identified is not the same in the two books. In Book IX the thinking or reasoning element (to dianoetikon, to nc;>oun, nous) w:i.th which a man seems to be identified (1166al6-1"'7," 22-23, 1168b35), since it1i"as the abilit to guide action 31 and to control the passions, must be either his practical reason or his intellect as a whole32--practical, productive, and theoretical. In Book X, on the other hand, the reason in question must be the theoretical reason alone. 33 For its activity is said to be theoretical (ll 77al7-18 et passim), and practical wisdom (pronesis) is explicitly distinguished from it (8. 11 78al6-22). 34 But, in spite of these dif­ ferences, the passages in Book IX, as we shall see, provide the clue to the proper interpretation of 1178a2-4.

Now, if a man is strictly identical with his theoretical reason and if practi­ cal reason is not a p.art of theoretical reason, . then practical· reason is not a.· part of a man. On the strict-identity hypothesis practical reason will be merely something without which a man cannot exist, like food (Met. b..5 ,.. 1015b20-22)--not a part of man but only a necessary condition of his existence. 3:> Practical and theoretical reason will be related as the lower and higher order in Aristotle's ideal state (see Pol. VI. 4.129la24-28 and VII. 8-9). The warriors, officeholders, and priests who compose its higher order are its parts. The farmers, craftsmen, and tradesmen who compose its lower order, though the state cannot exist without them, are not parts of it: their role is to serve the members of the higher order. On the strict-identity hypothesis practical reason will be subservient to theoretical in just the same way; and Aristotle will, as Cooper claims (£E_. cit. pp •. 162-63), · be embracing strict intellectualism.

But does Aristotle really mean to claim that a man is strictly identical with his theoretical reason? There is good reason for thinking not since his statement that reason "would also seem to be each man" (ll78a2) is immediately qualified: " •••for man, then, the life according to reason [is best and pleasantest], since this ·[viz.· reason] most of all (malista) is man"36 (a6-7). To be most of all man is t� be less than, and so nonidentical with' man. That this reservation is seriously intended is indicated by its earlier appearance in the two passages in Book IX where a man is identified with his thinking faculty. In the first of these Aristotle says that "the reasoning element would seem· to be, or to be most of all (e malista), each man" (4.ll66a22-23); · and the reservation is repeated in almost the same words in the second--"That this [viz. reason] is, or is most of all (e malista), each man is clear" (8.1169a2). But to claim that reason is the�st-important, but not the sole, part of a man is simply to reiterate a premiss--namely, line (4)-.;..of the argument of 1177al-21, an argument that does not entail strict intellectualism.

Other parts of the overall argument of chapter 7 that need to be examined are those in which Aristotle tries to show that theoretical activity is leisured and alone loved for its own sake whereas military and political activities (the pre­ eminent practical activities) are not chosen for their own sakes and are unleisured (1177bl-24). Aristotle offers the same consideration in support of both conclu­ sions--namely, that military and political activities aim at an external end but  

 } 

֫ In͒ʦх֫ ֫ լ¤Ҭ ֫ Ɋʥ (ʤ֫ Ûɉ&Ò֫ ?±ҍ֫ ÓÁ֫ Ɛλ ͑ ʣҪ!֫ O֫ ֫ ҩ ĠŁ֫ ł ˏҨʢ: C ¤Z֫  Sk Ľ֫ †ƒ͓ ǝцʧϯμ֫ ɋ֫ ê0Ƶ֫ Ƒҭ̪Ф¶֫ ʩ֫ ֫ ƶë֫ ^]J-.F"eR ֫ ʫ֫ ֫ ֫ Ņ̀֫ ¥ν֫ Ɠ̼áξҰ ֫ ͖իƷ֫ ȹХ֫ ʪү y֫ ń͕Â7֫ ͔֫ Ń"Ց Ү3֫ ɌϰԳ̫ ֫ žŇЩЪʰÑ֫ ĥчʬÐϱ͗-zҎ֫ 0UeOI1f} тԺʭшǞΪǟ·ұ֫ p?q} ɍǠ֫ ņƔҲ' Ւʮҳ։֫ tAu} ƕÃ@ʯAâ ֫֊12UOf=K k πҵňʱ͘Ґ֫ r@s} AɎϳi'͙֫ ƖԷ̶ՓʲҶ} C`l/T} 7]b} 'Ҵҏ֫ ϲο֫ kL,} `k {( #  * ĴʴՔ֫ Ҹǣ֫ ҔϷ‹̭J֥$    Ôɏǡ֫ ƗϵΫ϶Ǣρ֫ \6} ɐ+Ыʳ.Ғғ֫ ú?Ôѽ̬Ƙҷ֫ # щ֫ , ֫ ʸ͛ʹŊҌ֫ + ֫ Ьϸ(ʺʻ‡֫͜ 4ƚrʼʽԸ̸1֫ һ'ՕʶҼ֋֫ ¦ҽŸ֫ ­ǥʷ ς֫ Z4} ҹɑPǤҺʵƙ͚֫ ʼn̷ ֫  ͞ ҾϹq͝Ǧó@֫ ҿǧ¸s֫ n>o} ʿôխ֫ %ъ͂֫ "[֫ cыƸ.)֫ AA֫ ֫ Jè֫ ɓx֫ ʾɒ֫ cÌ́֫ H #§σӃю֦  õˁ֫ '(PVELk =Ϻ˂[2֫ Ӂ֫ ӂɖ֫ ծKȽǨ֫ ,ь֫ ˀ¹֫ э ֫ Ӏɔ}Õ֫ կ֫ ſ֫ ɕ&ǩ֫ ЭǪŋ {% L֫͠ ƜӈUՖ˅ Ӊ֍֫ ɘ֫ ͡Ի‘֫ <τ͢!֫ ֫ # ά8ƒ֫ ӄ֫ ǫǬ²֫ # ˃Ю͟֌֫ Ӆɗćӆ֫ ЯƛӇ˄ ϻº{֫ 9_d} ÊԴ ͣF֫ Öϼ֫ əOˆ

֫ Ӌɜ֫ ӌɝ֫ „jՐ֫ ɛ֫ ̮lҕ֫ ÖVυ֫ d֫ ӊ"’֫ ©  »Ⱦ֫ ɚ֫ ×%#֫ ķ֫ 矨 ֫ Y̓֫ \֫ ōƞӍˉϽZ֫ ˊ@֫ \ͥy֫ аÍĈ֫ ĵeƹ֫ ֫ „ր֫ Ħˇͤ“z֫ ՗Ōяˈ Ɲ#ț' ֫ ]ǰ֫*ƁjǭͨǮƻā֫ ɟǯ֫ Ø֫ < ͧ֎֫ ƺ @֫ é$ˋ ӎϾͦD֫ ӏɞÄ!֫ Ե̯¸֫ #֫ Hѐˆ ֫:֫ ªÙ  * Ȝ֫  ֫ ɠF֫ } ³¼֫ έK!֫ Ɵӑ֫ ˍ֫ ƽ^ ȿ֫ ƼˌȻȼӐ֫ ֫ # ƂŎёQ/֫ ƃ ӔWR֫ ȝ֫ ¡dz֫ 1Ŷ֫ [5} ɢǴ֫ DZ֫ ?Լ‰ɡ֫ ӓ”б•ŹơDzĂ֫ Ƅ ՘Í֏֫ ֫ ̽Խ ӒUƠBͩ ֫ ˎÎq$ ֫ Ƕ֫ '* ͫ֫ Nӗ֫  ֫ # ˑή֫ ĉģ֫ ź ֫ ӕ֫ ~Ƣ֫ ːӖ вђÒˏԾͪM֫ ;г9ѓÓǵ֫ є֫ ̾ ͬɤ֫ Å֫ Ә˒ϿҊ**Ő֫ ә֫ ӚǷ½֫ ֫  φ֫  ֫ ŏ֫ ֫ ×ɣ֫ 8̈́֫ Թ–^֫ ω֫ ӟ"ψ֫ ՙ˔ƣӛ#ѕ֐֫ і֫ Ӝɥ֫ їĊȞЀ҂֫ 0֫ ֫ հ)e½ɀƾfnG֫ ħӝɦÃCɁɧ֫ Ӟɨ˕֫ ƿ˖s˗χ Ӣ֫ Կϋǁǹkͱ˚Ǻ֫ ӠfӡͰ-֫ {} Ĩª Ț̰t֑ͯ֫ &} ¶֫ Ǹփ҆®  ֫ ˙֫ ՚7֫ ǀž֫ “քжͮ ϊ҅+ͭ֫˘ Ęİ {"# җl&Ͳ֫ C֢֣ͳǼ֫ FS # ǃњŽ_֫ $Ё՜˛֫ ֓֫ͅ  ֫ Ŕίǻ¾ӣ֫ ֫ Ɔј՛љ֒֫ όǂ֫ ɩ Ҙ¢֫ ֫ DŽ֫ %֫ ɫ˝ɂġ֫ ǽ֫ ,`֫ Ђ֫ vB-} :H.N'} ȟ֫ ƇLӥ͵Ǿ֫ ձ H̱2Ӥʹ—Do֫ ɪ˜ƤpG֫ (} {|͸ǿ֫ ժЄ˞Dž˟[֫ ӧɬ’֫ z;M ß̹ȠCͶ֩֫ ûЃ֫ ͆ŕͷ_ý֫ ղS + ¿֫ ֫ gћΣΤ֔֫ mX} ÚӦ {$ ¾ljF֫ Ŗˠɭ>0ÿ֫} 6dž֫ ֫ LJȡӨ֫ ɮˡ֫ ˜Pκ֡֫ %Sˢ͹Ȁ֫  Č֫ ճg } üij̲Հў֫ ӭ֫ ϐdu֫ Ӯɲ֫ ЇuɳÏč֫ ΥΦȁ֫ ž֫ ֖֫ Ӫӫˤώ֫ Ӭɱ֫ ІϏš֫ ɄÅ ͺ֫ ƈ ƥөѝ֫ Ȣƴ"a֫ ĩƦɰ™| # ĶƧЉj֫ ƒNj֫ =Gj} ȣ,¨ͼ֘֫ vɵȂ֫ g֫ ŘӯӰřV·֫ ɴ֫ օ҇Ś/֫ Ј&ͻ֫ Y&֗֫ 7֫ # ˥֫ ˦NJ֫ ֫_֫ ŀȄš֫ :9% 56#$hBAZ[78&jcYa!k Ī˧tЊӱͽö1֫ ΰ>͈֫ Ћ Ü̺֫ Y3} SMзU njȃo>á # ӳɶ-֫ KVx2hWQ} ´֫ vЎ֫ Ӵɷ֫ ֆӵȆѾϮͿ֫ Ќϑ֫ śи&џ֫ ӲÂ֫ ϒȤ;˨ƨ֫ ƉƩŜՁȅ֫ Ѝ֫ mȥ֫§  { ȇ` E֫

{Ûˬϓ֫ ƪ΁ŝ΂֚֫ DR ˩֫ Ǎ˪Ӹ˫ӶX֫ ֫ ֫ X%!ҙ֫ ͉•֫ ӷ ШѠå ΀֙֫ īĿ ӻè֫ ì,ϕ7ěę֫ ՟ Ӻ  N֫ ՞֫ ˯ϔѡѢ—ǐ֫ ɹӹ֫ wɺЏl̻ ҋˮp֫ ɸ֫ %B΃Ǐ֫ ¿Ü֫ǎE֫ ĺr[˭ ֫ p ֫ TŞ֫ îbɼ˱ϗ֫ ş ѣА;֫ ɻ֫ йn˰ Қ֫ յϖ֫ ŷȉí֫ մՂ΄Ǒ֫ –֫ Ú֫ Ɗ֫ ΅Ȉǒ֫ ֫ ӽ©֫ æȊ֫ Ţ˵֫ β֫ ՠ   Ѥ֫ W֫ J$Š֫ ѥÆ;֫ 3ɽ֫ ɾÇѦ˲֤˳Ϙ֫ %ɿ8iқ֫ ȦБα֫ š‡Ӽ˴ƫΆ֫ Έ֫ Ԃݵ֫ ԃʂţ3֫ Ԅʃԅ˶ k IJ9֫ ԁʁ֫ Ԁ̳Цaï֫ /0TXiH ֫ $Ӿ֫ ȧkВ֫ ӿʀ֫ 4 ѧ֫ · {*> ֫ !Ҝ֫ Ei} òտʅŦ֫ ֫ |Ԇ˷ա˸֛֫ KΉГ֫ ˹֫ ΊÆŽ֫ ȨÁ֫ V3֫ !# Ť¬֫ ť΋¹֫ նʄ˺ M ֫-{֫ Д֫ ˜֫ Ѫ } Ǔh2֫ ԉ֫ ȩ0Ό΍<֫ ȪѨ´֫ ʆȋ֫ кѩγ Ԉ֫ Yϙ֫y  ÈՃɅTԇ֫ Õ֫ o}֜֫ 6 ֫ ˻ϚɆ֫ ǔÙ¢֫ Ȭ#δ֫ 5֫ ҃˼ϛŨΏ֫ ˽ΐΑ\֫ uʈũԋ֫ ʉգ֫ Ϝ֫ 9ևԌϝ֫ ʇ֫ ‚֫ ƋѫNբΎ֝֫ ȫ ŧƬԊ'0b֫ ҝ ֧ ԍ֫ Ѭ֫ ѭȭ҄Ȍǖ֫ ¦mOΒ֞֫ 8^c} wʊ˾Ѯ֫ <ց֫ ‚͏GĜĞ֫ ľՄ֫ Qդ֫ ÞʋՅʌ֫ 3ʍ֫ ҁǕ֫ ƌ ֫! Ԓ̄ե ֫ ѰȍуՆ̃ѱԐ֫ ԑ£Ū֫ ʐ֫ ūŠԏ́ÄϞ֫ շ̂ʏ֫ Ý ‘ÀԎ֫ ̀֫ ƭЖ̿ ѯɇ֫ B Γâ2˿Е֫ É֫ ʎ ֨ ­֫ ̉¼Ԙ ԗ̈ * ոa֫ ҟ͊֫ ”̇1֫  !* ƍ֫ Ʈ¡Ç›ϟ֫ ȮѲ֫ԓʑ֫ ºԔ̅ԕՇԖ֫ лм̆8Ҟ֫ % ԛȏĎ֫ нԚ̋Ɉ֫ ֫ ‰ЗϠƯΖä̌Èϡ֫ ̍ß1Ȱ֫ ̎֫ ̏Ϣ ǗRф ‹֫ ѴȎb֫ ȯ֫ ~ tՈΔ̊֫ Ĭѳ«ԙΕ÷ ҡԞКԟ֫ 5kՊœϤ֫ W֫ T֫ ֠֫ ƎŬ̒Ñ֫ ĭǘĄ֫ ԜʒQ֫ &* ư¯B̐Иϣ֫ Й֫ ԝʓ̑֫ ҠՉ Ļ֫ ³֟֫ ε `ԡȐ®ΗƱԢãΘ̔Ңw֫ ȱ֫ Ʋ:€Ê֫ Rk ֫ ȺЧÌ֫ # Ѷ̓ŠԠ֫ ѵզ"Ǚ.=

Л֫ Ϩ֫ ̗֫ Λ   ֫Ϧԣ҈5Ι֫ Ż ֫ ϧ֫ ֈÞȑ҉Κ֫ ȒŽ֫ # չ]֫ ŭ֫ ļʔ.֫ ՋΝ֫ ̘֫ ̙à)п¥֫ Į"ԤÉΞø֫ ˜±ŮҀ͐֫ ʖ֫ ð֫ պ͋֫ # Ǜ֫ ԥʗ֫ ջ֫ µƀ֫ ʘէ֫ʕΜ= ֫ˆ À֫  ֫ ֫ űk ĸ ñ֫ +,RWFN ֫ cѸ ֫ ʙ֫ ֫ ζ+y֫ £Űը֫ $ ңՌѷȓ֫ ů ֫ ֫ ֫̚.) ԧ̛d֫ Ԩʚ֫ ւ֫ ¬֫ ֫ Ο֫ Ҥ֫ ȲМ֫ Ų^֫ ϩ ֫ =ų)Ԧ֫ ȳfη֫ ֫ I ֫ ֫    ֫ {+ Ȕ/ȴ֫ ŵϪ ֫ I2֫ 5֫ ;ż֫ ԩ֫ рȕƳ9֫ #} (Ȗ̜ҥՍmď֫  ֫ ֫ ֫ * ʛŴթ֫ x€Π ռ)͌֫ k ԪʜОCʝ֫ 34>>b?Ik g@D> ֫ ¯Ÿ֫ s֫ НՏȵ̞r֫ ֫ \_  ֫ Վ֫Œ֫ ²6֫ ս θå̝ ͍֫ ȷ֫ ԭʠ֫ hѹ֫ Ԭȗ֫ * Ρ̡֫ Ҧ֫ °П֫ ֫ ԫ™֫ é֫ #ȶ֫  Đվ̠ʞ֫ Ø֫ ʟ/$֫ ֫› ̤ϫŒԮ̥֫ eXD?֫ ụ̈̀ } ĹѺxѻą֫ į>̢ (֫ )*<;dMQk ĒēĕĚėĝĆĖğþE֫ ̴ Ə- ֫!°( {șԲϭ֫ ag!wJ"P "()*ĢĔı̩»֫ ֫ ʡù֪ԯ̦ĤđѿȘPϬ֫ æ͎֫ 6 ֫ /̧ä֫ Р֫ С԰֫ †ТѼҧсУZ ֫ Ա֫ :̨ - 15 -

and theoretical activity• The moral virtues have a role to play in both phases of life: "Bravery and endurance are needed for work, philosophy for leisure, temperance and justice at both times, and more especially when men observe peace and have leisure; for war compels men to be just and temperate, whereas the enjdyment of good fortune and the possession of leisure accompanied by peace makes them rather insolent"

VII

Chapter 8 contains three additional arguments for the conclusion that perfect happiness is theoretical activity. (1) The gods are paradigms of happiness but their lives consist entirely of theoretical, rather than practical or productive, activity; "so of human activities that which is most akin to this is the most conducive to happiness" (1178b 7-23). (2) The whole of the life of the gods, con­ sisting as it does of ceaseless contemplation, is blessed (makarios); so too is the life of man in so far as it is spent in such activity; but none of the lower animals are happy since they in no way share in contemplation. "As far, then, as contemplation extends, so also does happiness; and to those to whom contemplation more fully belongs happiness also more fully belongs, not incidentally but in virtue of the contemplation." Therefore, happiness is a kind of contemplation (b24-32). '3) He who exercises his (theoretical) reason is most loved by the gods; those most loved by the gods are the happiest; therefore, the wise man is the happiest (1179a22-32).

The second argument requires examination, for the part of it that is directly quoted seems to identify happiness and contemplation straightforwardly and, con­ sequently, to be an unambiguous expression of strict intellectualism. But the argument will, I think, bear another interpretation. The second argument follows

directly upon the first and begins with the words "A proof, too, is that ••."

(s�meion de kai •••) . This indicates that it is intended to establish the same .conclusioU-as the first--namely, that he teleia eudaimonia is theoretical activity (1178b7-8). Now, if he: teleia eudaimonia means, as it seems to, perfect or fully realized rather than-Complete happiness throughout X.7-8 and if makarios and eudaimonia mean teleia audaimonia in argument (2), then Aristotle's statement that happiness and contemplation are coextensive will mean simply that perfect or fully realized happiness is coextensive with contemplation. But this assertion is com­ patible with a moderate intellectualism that allows a place for the secondary happiness of moral and political activity. This interpretation also resolves a small puzzle about the argument--namely, that Aristotle's explanation of the fact that happiness is not attributed to the lower animals seems inadequate. They are incapable of happiness, one would suppose, not simply because they are inca­ pable of �ontemplating but also because they are incapable of practical thinking.47 But if Aristotle is thinking only of perfect or fully realized happi­ ness, his explanation is completely adequate.

VIII

Thus with the exception of the one statement that theoretical activity "alone would seem to be loved for its own sake" (1177bl-2) there seems to be nothing in X.6-8 that is inconsistent with a moderate intellectualism and with the rest of - 16 -

the Nicomachean Ethics. This is a fairly weak conclusion. Can it be strengthened? Is there anything in these three chapters that can be taken to be an expression of moderate intellectualism? In particular, can anything be taken to be an expression of the only reasonable version of moderate intellectualism;...... ,namely, the super­ structure view according to which theoretical activity is to be maximized within the constraints of the life of practical wisdom and moral virtue?

Aristotle's famous injunction ''as far as possible to inunortalize oneself and to do everything with a view to living in accordance with the best thing in oneself [viz. the theoretical reason]" (7 .1177b33-34) is an expression of the superstructure view if the restriction signified by the words "as far as possible" includes moral restrictions as well as those of mind, body, and estate. Does it? The answer to this question can be gleaned, I think, from a passage in chapter 8 where Aristotle is discussing the extent to which the theoretical life and the life in accordance with practical wisdom and moral virtue need external equipment and where he seems for once to combine the two lives: "The person who contemplates has no need of such things [viz. external goods] for his activity; but they are ao to speak even impediments-:Bt least to contemplation; however, as he is a man and lives with a number of others, he chooses to do those things that are in accord­ ance with [sci!. moral] virtue; he will therefore need such things with a view to living as a man" {ll 78b3-7). Here Aristotle states explicitly that the person who contemplates {ho theoron), qua man, chooses to act in accordance with moral virtue. 48 Arthur Adkins in a recent article remarks, however; that Aristotle "does not tell us when he chooses: he may well mean 'chooses when theoria is not available. 'n49 On Adkins' interpretation the author of this passage might without inconsistency condone the conduct of a man who refused to interrupt his theoretical activity in order to rescue a neighbor from a burning building. Thus Adkins believes the passage to be consistent with what I have called the "absolute priority" view-- the view whose precept is, Maximize theoretical activity first; then maximize moral activity. But there are at least two reasons for rejecting Adkins' interpretation. First, Aristotle says that the person who contemplates, qua�' chooses to act in accordance with moral virtue. But a person is not a man--that is to say, a human being--at one moment .. and at another not. He is a human being all of his life just as he is always an animal and always a living thing. Thus once the moral virtues are acquired he is always prepared to act in accordance with them. Secondly, possession of the moral virtues would seem to be inconsistent with their erratic exercise. The brave man defends his polis whenever the enemy attacks, not just at his convenience. Thus if the person who contemplates, qua man, chooses to act in accordance with bravery, he must always be prepared to sacrifice theoret­ ical activity for battle. So this passage does not seem to be consistent with the absolute priority view. It seems better to take it as picking up the theme of the function argument, the centerpiece of Book One: namely, that the various aspects of a person's total life...,-his life as a living thing, as an animal, as a man, and as a demigod--form a hierarchy with the higher aspects resting on and presupposing the lower.

If my interpretation is correct, Aristotle does indeed subscribe to the superstructure view: one should seek to immortalize ones�lf but only within the bounds of the life of practical wisdom and moral virtue. O ~ ǪU

[jǪ

‹ Ú Ǫ Ôʼnǂ  Ǫ /+Ǫ Ǫ ƌǪ "ĢǪ îďhŽþĐĸģÿǥ) ǃĹŊđǪ ǛŭǪ DŽĺƷŋǪ DžŌ/̐Ǫ

 Ǫ ƒ‹ 5‹ A‹ äě Ǫ $ö ŇǪ 4`oEh‹ \JǪ ƁǪ !NJdžŮsƸǪ )LJĻFĒ $Ǫ  v3(&º0%Ǫ Ǫ È.Ǫ =ęǪ AƋa=Ǫ BǪ @L ƨ{Ǫ õĤĀƹƂǪ IR‹ ãǚžƶǪ áh ĜǪ Ǫ Õ-ōmGǪ @<ƩŎİǪ BĎanǁSǪ 5  0SǪ Ǫ 55 ™–‡Ǫ

Ǫ =‹  Ö+ũưŠ Ǫ Ǫ ÞĝHƃŏǩ$Ǫ įǪ ~[W‹ ÛƱŢţƺ Ǫ   ÌÅ´QǪ ƚ VǪ » Ǩ®4Ǫ

% ‹ 6ƀǪ  Ǫ ;k Ǫ 8Ǫ  /ŷŸ#;Ǫ ×,Ʋ ftǪǪ ů Ǫ

+‹ àƪǪ LjļǪ gǪ Ǫ ÝǪ 2 ‹ å7ˆµ›û3T¯ª%Ǫ #) ,F.! ‹

&Ǫ 5uw‹ NĽǪ EƧāƄǪ :Ǫ   _Ǫ ĦǪ 6Ǫ.‹ .(' ±‘Ǫ

ĄǪ ëǖǪ ő9Ǫ ]ƍ Ǫ 7艼 &ü¶—RǪ Ǫ `ŒŨƆ+ljǪ :ƳHǪ MǪ ,ƇĂǪ  ;‹Ǫ  ˜€ xǪ

' Ǫ *ħǪ ^ Ǫ \dƻǪ /‹ 4FijFN†‹ Ǫ !-œƎ uǪ ØƬĴ<ƈNǪ ČNJǪ ~\W‹ â9 >Ǫ BX‹ wðNjƭǪ œ?½ 0Ǫ HQ‹ AŠǪ ?‹ !ŪƵŰű|Ǫ !-Ə )mľēƼǪ ï#Ǫ øƮb Ǫ ? yzǪ Ɯ 1Ǫ «.%Ǫ 44Ǫ

( Ǫ BKMǪ ŲǡǪ ň=PǤoOǪ ì8 ųǪ ƝĘFGźǢǪ ¥¦Ñ²U(1Ǫ *Ǫ ZƐ Ǫ ˆŠ‹ +ŕ Ǫ ƞ Ǫ žŸ& ¢YǪ

£.Ǫ [Ǫ ƑĿƯǪ Ŗ njŤƒǪ :Ǫ "Ǫ ĞŗǍŘĔǗLǪ ƽĨǪ >‹ 8‹ 6‹ 7xYYq„uuU|‹ PunYq€Gy‹ uq‹ 3uuf‹ C:‹ /Ǫ  Ǫ CĕHĄ"ĊǪ )"+Ǫ @ąſř`;EǪ Í2ÎR%Ǫ Ǫ ·Â‚¸ Ǫ

¤Ǫ "Ǫ   +ŀǎǪ Że ǣÒǪ > ǏǪ #ŁǪ # ĖłǪ _}‹ b|‹ Ǫ ƟŚ 1$Ǫ

Ǫ # ŴĩǪ 9;Ǫ ć kǪ c|‹ gǐĈŵǪ ǝǘńǪ ŜÓǪ DǪ Ǫ s‹ Ƣ Ǫ Ǫ <Ǫ  ƉğrǪ ÷ Ǫƒ ) Ǫ Ɣ/Ǫ !iǑ Ǫ ùíƕƊǪ §Ê'ÁúǪ ‚uk‹ <;‹ Ǫ XÃQǪ

WX‹Ǫ *ĪǪ č # Ǫ

4ŒǪ *Ǫ Ù,Ǫe Ǫ $!-ťǒǓ Ǫ =Ǫ ß9<Ş >Ǫ Ǫ ³À'Ǫ _ĠǪ Zi -Ǫ ‡‰‹ ǦÜ }Ǫ ƣ Ǫ 3¹?T2Ǫ

3¾Ǫ IDGīǔǪ IƤǪ ò ŽǪ éê7 ¡Y°ĭĮǪ

&†Ǫ Ǫ Ŧƿ Ǫ 7 25ċŬÆǪ

ÇǪ ]u‹  Ǫ 8’ ¨š( Ë Ǫ

'“Ǫ Ǫ Kat{‹ pOPOǪ 9 ‹& "*Jg ‹

W(Ǫ Ǫ  Ǫ ^Ŷ1Ǫ 8”'•©&D Ǫ

.Ǫ ^u‹ ǀƗǙbǪ Ldu|‹ @sl‹ æ6ύ ¬ 2ý¿Ǫ

 Ǫǧ*Ǫ AVǪ 0‹ *#ĉǕ Ǫ CLEǪ uq‹ ŅǪ )ņǪ ñǞ:Ǫ ÉЭ0%Ǫ ǜc Ǫ 6ç%Ǫ Ǫ )'$()-‹ ° H-ʰ 

)à ʰ Įʰ (łɟʰ ;yuʰ .ʰ  ʰ  Ǥ/ ʰ Ŋʰ ď.‰ɠ Ǯ¸ʰ

   2 Ĝ/Rʰ ɡwūʰ ŝyʚ O .ɢʠʰ /Rʰ ɁzŞO?O ȐOɣʡʰ ƍʰ  Ŭʰ  *,*38"+<  Å_Jʰ ķ+şʰ ;<   mʰ 2 1$%/4 /"

)" ʰ Ĭ ʰ x ʰ Fʰ ʰ ü#Ĉʰ ƶʰ  U3ʰ o70ʰ Dʰ p ʰ   p„  ʰ ĐƷ! Ƞ ŭċʰ , ,Ĩ? ʰ Dʰ K.ʰ ÊCýBž ʰ

)÷3ʰ ėŠʰ /ʰ UR.  ;ʰ 1 ƹ*ʰ Kǰ ¡ʰ ƺvʰ ʰ Ơ ʰ 7ʰ ]ʰ ]&ȡČʰ &*ʰ ,ơ/DZAʰ RŮƻPʛŠʰ ‘ʬ“ʰ !#2 Mʓʰ ™ŔȢDzůA ʰ Ƽʰ ɇʰ *Űʰ F ʰ ŽǨ¢ʰ ŽwƽWʰ Pʰ  ʰ ɜʰ /ʰ ɤűʰ * ʰ :ʰ ʰ ,ij  H"účʰ K Ǵ ʰ İġ ʰ "   Ʊ #ʰ Ë5¹Ì ð"Í#ʰ ıº4»I44gE)-²ÎJJ-ǵ£ʰ 6Ųʰ (ɝ/ʰ ĝPšƾʰ 6 ȋ ”ʰ  {2ʰ Ɉ|Ƿʰ @ĩ ƿųʰ ńʰ ī ʰ {ȑʰ đǀɥ (ŴGʰ r;ʰ 6ɦ @ʰ Ȓʰ ħ $+ŵʰ 6ɚ~ ʰ šĠǁ Mǂʰ C#h9¤ʰ 2ȈÂʰ ģ ʰ

2 nʰ  ʰ Wȶˆ$%ʰ =Ǝʰ ɧƢɉ Œ ʰ Ţʰ Ĺɨǃ ʰ 2DŽɩʣʰ ʟDžʰ ʰ ɪɊ1ƚƣʪ %1ɫʰ ‹Ƥʰ ĺɋ8> ¥ʰ sʰ Ñ'³áâʰ ã-Jñʰ ,ʰ ʜ!>‰ʰ ʰ %ʰ Dʰ ʰ ƙ=ɮƦ9§ʰ )òʰ f·cóʰ SCĎʰ Dţʰ dž ʰ Ļ‡ ʰ 2  ʰ ȷLJ;;ʤʰ -/5   <

' ʰ nʰ Ƨʰ ?>ʰ Ə%ɛ0   ʰ /:ʰ ĒLj ɯ Gʰ  ŕ>ȥ ʰ Y ʰ .-29'0< )"äûʰ ÒÓ-gTʰ Ehʰ 4c¨ʰ ÔÕÿĉëdå ʰ

'T½ʰ (ʰ 2ljʰ ƒȌȸ<ɰNJ?ʰ  ʰ ȹȦʔʰ j ʰ 1Ȕʰ Ŷ ŷȍ ʰ Ťʰ ļʰ -)%2 rŸ(©ʰ Y((ʰ ^M ʰ ‡ʰ , <(ʰ  ʕQ ʰ ɱʰ ʰ ʝ.ʰ NjŹĽǸ@ʰ œo>ɲĥǹ}ʨʰ (+, Ŗ. ʰ ɳFʰ Ģʰ , /(!< ĭʰ Ǻʰ 6& ªʰ /2 W€ ʰ 2 ʰ ʰ † ʰ øC#)ʰ ?„( ʰ ʰ  ʰ ""ì_""e ʰ

'C ʰ ɴʰ ʰ :  ʰ ŋ +ʰ P ʰ 1ʰ ɵʰ & ʰ ēɶǻʰ ʥʰ ɷʰ ƨ Ⱥ ʰ  Ʉ>ʰ ʰ <njʰ ľʰ ʰ ʰ  źʰ ŗɏF ʰ  ʰ ‚Żǩʰ Ǎʖʰ ɸżǼǎȕʰ ,V 3 ÖBĊ-TæÉ«ʰ 92/)< ĴÃĀ3×ØăĄŌS"'#9ʰ  ʰ 1ʰ "$2 ʰ ʰ Ʃɐʰ Ž  ¾ʰ '2 Ȼz ʰ +ʰ ōʰ <%ɹʰ Ń ʰ ɑNťʰ ,ÙB ĆHf9¬ʰ ɺ ʰ Ƌǭʰ Ǐ=1ʰ žǽǐ ʰ ɒɅʰ Ɛ %ɓʰ ƪ+ʰ '%&, Ŏʰ ȧ&ƫɻʰ Ǿ!ʰ Ƭņʰ ʰ Ņʰ Ȩ ʰ Ƒʰ Eɼʰ ȩʰ Ŧ ƭʰ ɽ ſǒȪʰ ŏȫʰ ƀɆʗǓɔƁŧʰ ƒ=ʰ  #$), ŘŇȗɾʰ 46<  Ȁǔ ƃ ʰ +2 ʰ ˆŠƮʰ  57< ʰ Ƚňʰ Ɠʰ , ʀŒʰ !ʰ ʘƔ:ǕŜǥ ʁʰ ʂʰ ʃʄǖȘʰ ʅƄ–ʰ ʆȁʰ ƕʰ Ưʙʰ  `ʰ 6 ʰ 6 Ɗ&ʰ DŨʰ ğ0 ư´Ħ Ǘʩʰ * ,

B3ʰ l ɕʰ ZȂĿǘ!ʰ ŀʇʰ ʰ ʰ ɖʰ UǙ!  ʰ ƛ2 ʰ 7 ʰ IāĂ7 -Őç#ʰ ʰ @ Fʰ ʈșʰ ʰ ȭ&ʰ ƱL ʰ ĵȚ  ʉ2Ķʰ ~?ʦʰ & ʰ ȮțQ‘ʰ őʰ 0 ʰ Ł!ʰ ʰ Ȏ$7ʰ +ũʰ , . ^ʰ (Ɩ@ʰ ʞ Ȝʰ Ʋ18ʰ Śǚ Nʰ ʊʰ lʰ ʰ ʰ ǧʰ &L]ʰ ĔɗǛ  ʰ  :ʰ ƗZʰ ʰ , $3­ʰ †3ʰ 5#5AÀʰ Ęʰ ʋ *!ʰ &ƅ2®ʰ Ƴʌʰ ʰ ǜȏYŪ ’ʰ 0 ǝȝ8ʰ ȾɞNʰ HÚąE)#Û-'S¯ʰ   !ʰ ʰ ʰ !ȯ ʰ :ȴʰ M  8ʰ ɘʍʰ Ǡ ś Ǧʰ  !, ÜeuƘ A ʰ

4I ʰ ʰ ʯ,mʰ 2  ÝÇÁ"í4Ȅîb59aʰ

' ʰ į$ʰ $Qʧʰ %, 088ʎʰ 5:< ĕə$Ȱ Q—\ʰ 0ʰ *(2 ,*2 Xǡq+%ƆǢǪƒʰ %ʰ sŒʰ ʰ $L%$qʰ E$Ɯʰ jǣ\ʏ%<˜ʰ " , "Zʰ vʰ ƴ.*+Ɲʰ ʰ N  ʰ ʰ IJ ) Þb i7'#µ ßʰ +ʰ &,2  

"# < Ƶʰ Ƈȱƈʑ*Ȳʰ 12 ,Ětʰ Ė ʰ VVĤÄʰ2ô4'œè#¶éćʰ È`ʰõdï öIù ʰ

"& < Ğ%ʰ ʰ   Xʰ 7Lȅ’ʰ , x ʰ   ʰ Ɖʒ ȟʰ  ʰ !ƞʰ , kǫʰ  ʼnXʰ ʰ ‹&=ʰ ʰ kǬʰ  2 tʰ ę= G\ʰ Ȇȇ ʐʰ % '%%, 02   ʰ ɀ ʰ  2 - 19 -

35. See p. 4 above.

36. See Daniel Devereux, ''Aristotle on the Active artd Contemplative Lives, " Philosophical 'Research ·Archives 3, no .. l.118. (1977), p. 7.

3 7. See p. 1 above.

38. See D. F. Pears, "Aristotle's Analysis of Courage," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, III (1978).

39. On to kalon as an end of action and to aischron as an object of avoidance see nt-:7".1115bll-13, 23-24, 1116all-12 ,15; 8.1116a28-3 2 ' b2-3, 19' �0-31, . 1117a 8, 16-17; 9.1117b9, 14-15; 12.1119bl6; IV.1. 1120a23:-24, 112lb4-5; 2.1122b6-7, 1123a24-25; IX.8.1169a21-22, 28, 32, 35; X.8.1178bl3; and E.E. III.l.1229a2, 1230a29-33.

40. See I.l.1094a6-9 and III.9.1117b7-8. When Aristotle says in speaking of bravery that "it is not the case, then, with all the virtues that their exercise is pleasant, except in so far as one attains the end" (III.9. 1117bl5-16), the end in question is the external end. See also III.3.1112b33.

41. On Hector's motivation see III. 8.1116a21-29.

42. On this topic see also Ackrill's notes on 1139bl, 1176b7, and 1177bl-26 in Aristotle's Ethics.

43. scil . of the two pre�eminent human activities. Happiness, of course, is loved for its own sake,

44. Aristotle's Ethical Theory (Oxford, 1968) , p. 356 •

. 45. See Pears, 2£.• cit., p. 274.

46. If it be objected that Aristotle, in giving his final account of happiness in X.6-9, seems to have forgotten his (implicit) distinction between an internal and an external end of action, the reply is that the internal end of action is alluded to twice in the course of these chapters: see X.6.1176b6-9 and 8.1178bl2-13.

47. See Ackrill, Aristotle's Ethics, ad. loc.

48. Stewart, ad. loc.

49. "Theoria versus Praxis in the Nicomachean Ethics and ," Classical Philology (forthcoming).

50. Funds for reproducing this paper were provided by a grant from the Graduate School Research Fund of the University of Washington.  = 

ˆ)7þ Ņ

!= # =   !#& '$* Ķ¸ğŅ F2ĽŅ "* ,$/

   "* ĝæ ĢçŅ    Ņ 80= ģ¹Ņ _ĚâĵãºŅ  ,% /

 =   = 0¬ÊŅ 3ă Ņ ĹķĠŅ ĕ•Ë Ņ Ņ ĤŅ | 'û4'»8“Ņ eĥ'Ņ ¢Ņ 4*:;2-+5= ±<Ìÿ;Ņ

są½Ņ  `ďŅ $ĆŅ &«QŅ m@”Ņ £Ņ ÍŅ  ĦħêŅ -cü– ¤¶Ņ z  ¾­ ĨKŅ ,&  /

d6ÎëŅ 1*+Ņ W   ìŅ ĎŅ (*  ()* Ā¥Ņ a=ýĐ *Ņ vÏĺLCŅ $9?™Ņ  ÒĻŅ = Ņ (/ -'$ /

 = k 7Ņ * = ( = tî ²MŅ 0Ė ĩ TŅ )= -w*Ņ  Ņ „ Ņ 

‚Ņ ï Ņ = !ð,Ņ ÔŅ X?Õ ĪŅ Y;@Ņ —īŅ ĬÂŅ  .Ņ ‹Ņ &/ , $/

ò:Ŀ5 9Ņ l’ NŅ 3 Ņ <Ø(Ņ ³Ņ Z ĭóŅ Gx¦āŅ )* /

$ = = Ņ ľ Ņ [ġĮĈįUŅ ~œ:Ņ İ" Ņ ŽqŅ   "* .,/

 !Ņ $Ņ n& Ņ ŒŅ i  Ņ §Ņ Ņ ěä ®Ņ g ÄÙ Ņ '= ,"! /

&= !Ņ %= o ė¨ÚŅ \ĜåıõŅ hIJÅ۞ Ņ H€+ Ċ©Ņ ,#( /

1/Ņ j/Ņ ¯  Ņ Ü =ijöEŅ ^÷,Ņ )Ņ b ·DŅ { A Ņ % ÝŅ Ņ r##Ņ ,&) /

! Ęß¡Ņ ‰ċ ĂŅ yà 8Ņ 5ªŅ †‘,Ņ 17= ]ę Čø°Ņ # Ņ %.Ņ uùŅ %" ) Ņ Ip ú  Ç Ņ ,") / ļRŅ  =

"= = Š A&ĴŅ 2č ŃńŅ ÈŅ áŸÉ6Ņ  (Ņ J+´ PŅ +,/