Poros E Penia: Privação Ou Ambivalência Do Amor?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Poros E Penia: Privação Ou Ambivalência Do Amor? desígnio 9 jul.2012 POROS E PENIA: PRIVAÇÃO OU AMBIVALÊNCIA DO AMOR? Juliano Paccos Caram* CARAM, J. P. (2012). “Poros e Penia: privação ou ambivalência do amor?”. Archai n. 9, jul-dez 2012, pp. 107-116. RESUMO: Ao longo da leitura do Simpósio de Platão, é pos- * Professor de História Introdução da Filosofia Antiga na sível compreender a estreita relação entre o apetite (ἐπιθυμία) Universidade Federal da e o amor (ἔρως), enquanto este se manifesta, em última Fronteira Sul (UFFS), No âmbito da discussão acerca da genealogia campus Chapecó, Santa instância, como um apetite de imortalidade (ἐπιθυμία τῆς Catarina, Brasil. Doutorando e fisiologia do amor (ἔρως), a partir do passo 203a8 em Filosofia Antiga pela ἀθανασίας). Entretanto, este mesmo amor, que potencializa a do Simpósio de Platão, a sacerdotisa de Mantinéia, Universidade Federal de alma na descoberta do belo em si mesmo (τὸ καλόν), também Minas Gerais (UFMG). Diotima, apresenta a Sócrates uma alegoria, na qual pode aprisionar o homem na sedução do sensível, levando-o a discorre acerca da origem não somente do amor crer que nada é mais real do que a experiência amorosa pura e (ἔρως) como também do apetite (ἐπιθυμία) que simples que se esgota na apreciação de um belo corpo. o engendra. Utilizando as próprias palavras de Só- É, pois, nessa tensão entre as coisas físicas e aquelas crates, a pergunta que se coloca, a respeito do amor, verdades eternas que as sustentam que se inscreve a ambiva- é a seguinte: quem é seu pai e sua mãe? (πατρὸς lência de eros. Nossa análise pretende, através de uma leitura δέ […] τίνος ἐστὶ καὶ μητρός;) [Smp. 203a9]. do mito-alegoria de Poros e Penia, contado pela sacerdotisa de Examinemos detalhadamente a resposta. Mantinéia, Diotima, a partir do passo 203a do Simpósio, demons- No dia em que Afrodite nasceu (ἐγἐνετο), trar como a ambivalência constituinte do amor já se encontra, enquanto os deuses festejavam o acontecimento tout court, nas próprias características dos progenitores de eros, no palácio de Zeus, Poros, o Expediente, filho de tais como delineadas por Platão nesse trecho. Penia, a deusa Métis, ali se encontrava, junto aos demais convi- da Pobreza, seria essencialmente responsável pela precariedade vas. Após o jantar, eis que surge Penia, a Pobreza, e passividade de Eros perante as coisas sensíveis ou, também mendigando (προσαιτήσουσα) como de costume de modo ambivalente, já na descrição da deusa encontram-se e por ali permanece, espreitando de longe Poros indícios de uma potência criativa capaz de planejamento e de que, embriagado de tanto néctar, acaba por ador- atividade? E o que dizer de Poros, pai do amor? Ele explicaria mecer no jardim. Penia, entretanto, sóbria e atenta, suficientemente bem este apetite incessante de Eros que deseja planeja (έπιβουλεύω), através de sua indigência ir sempre mais além do objeto já experimentado? (διὰ τὴν αὑτῆς ἀπορίαν), gerar uma criança a PALAVRAS-CHAVE: Simposio, apetite, ambivalência, partir de Poros (ἐκ τοῦ Πόροῦ) [Smp. 203b1-8]. privação. Aproveitando-se, então, da frágil condição do deus Expediente, Pobreza se deita (κατακλίνεται) de- 107 ABSTRACT que os cavalos dos adversários poderiam ser mais A reading of Plato’s Symposium suggests the close célebres que o de seu filho, Nestor diz a Antíloco relationship between desire (ἐπιθυμία) and love (ἔρως), que auriga nenhum o ultrapassava em métis, isto as the former ultimately manifests itself as a desire for é, em astúcia. E conclui nestes termos: “Quem nos immortality (ἐπιθυμία τῆς ἀθανασίας). However, this corcéis confia e no seu carro, e põe-se, insensato, a same love that empowers the soul in the discovery of beauty dar voltas, de um lado para outro, desbridam-se os itself (τὸ καλόν), can also entrap man in sensible, lead- corcéis, sem que possa contê-los” (Il. XXIII, 311- ing him to believe that nothing is more real than the pure 313). Por outro lado, “quem as manhas conhece, and simple experience of love, which wears itself out in the quando guia corcéis menos ágeis, contorna a meta de appreciation of a beautiful body. perto...” (Il., XXIII, 319-323). Logo, para suportar It is, therefore, in this tension between physical objects e vencer aurigas e cavalos mais fortes e velozes and the eternal truths in which they are anchored, that the é necessário um tipo de conhecimento prático, ambivalence of eros is inscribed. Our analysis aims, based astucioso, ardiloso, ou seja, faz-se necessária uma on a reading of the myth-allegory of Poros and Penia, métis. Ora, como bem observaram M. Detienne e J-P. told by Diotima, priestess of Mantinea, from section 203a Vernant, por mais banal que esse episódio da Ilíada of the Symposium, to demonstrate how the constitutive possa nos parecer, ele traz à luz a oposição entre o ambivalence of love is already found, tout court, in the emprego da força e o recurso à métis. “Numa situação characteristics of the progenitors of Eros, as outlined by de batalha ou de competição – quer seja nas lutas Plato in this passage. Would Penia, the goddess of poverty, com um homem, com um animal ou com uma força be primarily responsible for the precariousness and pas- natural –, o sucesso pode ser obtido pelas duas vias”, sivity of Eros in the face of sensible things, or also in an isto é, ou pela força física, ou pela astúcia racional ambivalent way, as in her description there are indications (DETIENNE & VERNANT, 1974, p. 19). of a creative power capable of planning and activity? And Dessa ilustração da astúcia na Ilíada, podemos what about Poros, the father of love? Would he accurately retirar algumas consequências importantes para se explain the relentless desire of Eros who always wishes to pensar o estatuto ambivalente do apetite na confi- go beyond the already experienced object? guração de eros. O amor é, por assim dizer, neto de KEY-WORDS: Symposium, desire, ambivalence, pri- Métis, no Simpósio. Enquanto tal, ele deve possuir, vation. desde seu engendramento, esta ambivalência pro- posta pela leitura de M. Detienne e J-P. Vernant. liberadamente junto a ele e, assim, engendra Eros Se a vitória de Antíloco pode ser atingida tanto (ἐκύησε τὸν Ἔρωτα) [Smp. 203b8-c1]. pela força física, quanto pelo uso da razão, deve- Da alegoria apresentada por Diotima, e resu- -se ao fato de que a astúcia desdobra-se como uma mida acima, podemos extrair algumas considerações “força” que concorre com o físico e que, por vezes, que serão de extrema importância para a compreen- possibilita maior êxito ao homem que age sob suas são da origem do apetite. Em primeiro lugar, temos recomendações do que sob suas próprias forças. Do a própria ascendência de Poros: ele é filho da deusa mesmo modo, a ambivalência do apetite que engen- Métis que, principalmente nas literaturas homérica e dra o amor também se encontra entre o visível e o hesiódica, possui características muito interessan- invisível, ora tendendo a um, ora a outro. Sendo, tes: Métis, a Astúcia, é, por um lado, apresentada portanto, neto da Astúcia, Eros pode se manifestar como uma forma peculiar de inteligência, uma pru- tanto como apetite direcionado ao corpo ou como dência advertida; por outro, como uma divindade apetite pelas coisas incorpóreas. feminina, filha de Oceano. Vejamos alguns exemplos. Em Hesíodo, por sua vez, Métis é a perso- No Canto XXIII da Ilíada, no episódio dito dos nificação da deusa “mais sábia que os deuses e os 1. As referências à Ilíada são 2 jogos, o velho Nestor, modelo do Sábio, do conse- homens mortais” (Th., v. 887) . Por conseguinte, o extraídas de Homero (2003). rebento que dela nasce, isto é, Poros e, finalmente, lheiro expert em métis, transmite a seu filho Antíloco 2. As referências são extraídas de 1 suas recomendações (XXIII, 306 ss) . Mesmo sabendo o filho deste com Penia, a saber, Eros, também Hesíodo (1991). 108 desígnio 9 jul.2012 herdarão a sabedoria ardilosa de Métis, tal como ambas as características, num misto de expediente aquela astúcia da razão capaz de conceder a vitória e de pobreza e que, por sua vez, dá origem à con- ao que se mostra fisicamente mais fraco, porém dição ambivalente do apetite que se encontra na ardilosamente mais forte. Assim, como escrevem gênese de eros. M. Detienne e J-P. Vernant: Examinemos, agora, um segundo aspecto a ser destacado nesta alegoria, a saber, a relação entre a métis é, antes de tudo, uma forma de inteligência Eros e Afrodite. O Amor é engendrado no dia do e de pensamento, um modo de conhecer; ela implica nascimento da deusa da beleza, Afrodite. Por isso, um conjunto complexo, mas muito coerente, de atitudes ele também será amante do belo (ἐραστὴς [...] mentais, de comportamentos intelectuais que combinam τὸ καλόν) (Smp. 203c3-4) e, desse modo, tenderá a argúcia, a sagacidade, a previsão, a flexibilidade do tanto ao belo visível, quanto desejará atingir a espírito, o disfarce, o desembaraço, a atenção vigilante, essência mesma do belo, ou seja, o belo invisível. o sentido de oportunidade, as habilidades diversas, uma Assim, tendo sido engendrado no dia do nas- experiência longamente adquirida; ela se aplica às reali- cimento de Afrodite, a partir da união de pais apa- dades fugazes, mutantes, desconcertantes e ambíguas, rentemente tão opostos, o apetite de Eros se mostra que não se prendem nem à medida precisa, nem ao ambíguo. Segundo a natureza da mãe (Smp. 203d3), cálculo exato, nem ao raciocínio rigoroso. (1974, p. 10). o amor é sempre indigente, está longe do luxo e da beleza. Ele é, antes, rude (σκληρός) e miserável Ora, é de se esperar que também Poros e seu (αὐχμηρός), descalço (ἀνθπόδητος) e despro- filho Eros sejam expressão, na alegoria platônica, vido de morada (ἄοικος), sempre companheiro da dessa racionalidade astuciosa proveniente de Métis.
Recommended publications
  • Naming the Extrasolar Planets
    Naming the extrasolar planets W. Lyra Max Planck Institute for Astronomy, K¨onigstuhl 17, 69177, Heidelberg, Germany [email protected] Abstract and OGLE-TR-182 b, which does not help educators convey the message that these planets are quite similar to Jupiter. Extrasolar planets are not named and are referred to only In stark contrast, the sentence“planet Apollo is a gas giant by their assigned scientific designation. The reason given like Jupiter” is heavily - yet invisibly - coated with Coper- by the IAU to not name the planets is that it is consid- nicanism. ered impractical as planets are expected to be common. I One reason given by the IAU for not considering naming advance some reasons as to why this logic is flawed, and sug- the extrasolar planets is that it is a task deemed impractical. gest names for the 403 extrasolar planet candidates known One source is quoted as having said “if planets are found to as of Oct 2009. The names follow a scheme of association occur very frequently in the Universe, a system of individual with the constellation that the host star pertains to, and names for planets might well rapidly be found equally im- therefore are mostly drawn from Roman-Greek mythology. practicable as it is for stars, as planet discoveries progress.” Other mythologies may also be used given that a suitable 1. This leads to a second argument. It is indeed impractical association is established. to name all stars. But some stars are named nonetheless. In fact, all other classes of astronomical bodies are named.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium: the Ethics of Desire
    Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire FRISBEE C. C. SHEFFIELD 1 Contents Introduction 1 1. Ero¯s and the Good Life 8 2. Socrates’ Speech: The Nature of Ero¯s 40 3. Socrates’ Speech: The Aim of Ero¯s 75 4. Socrates’ Speech: The Activity of Ero¯s 112 5. Socrates’ Speech: Concern for Others? 154 6. ‘Nothing to do with Human AVairs?’: Alcibiades’ Response to Socrates 183 7. Shadow Lovers: The Symposiasts and Socrates 207 Conclusion 225 Appendix : Socratic Psychology or Tripartition in the Symposium? 227 References 240 Index 249 Introduction In the Symposium Plato invites us to imagine the following scene: A pair of lovers are locked in an embrace and Hephaestus stands over them with his mending tools asking: ‘What is it that you human beings really want from each other?’ The lovers are puzzled, and he asks them again: ‘Is this your heart’s desire, for the two of you to become parts of the same whole, and never to separate, day or night? If that is your desire, I’d like to weld you together and join you into something whole, so that the two of you are made into one. Look at your love and see if this is what you desire: wouldn’t this be all that you want?’ No one, apparently, would think that mere sex is the reason each lover takes such deep joy in being with the other. The soul of each lover apparently longs for something else, but cannot say what it is. The beloved holds out the promise of something beyond itself, but that something lovers are unable to name.1 Hephaestus’ question is a pressing one.
    [Show full text]
  • 9781469658254 WEB.Pdf
    Literary Paternity, Literary Friendship From 1949 to 2004, UNC Press and the UNC Department of Germanic & Slavic Languages and Literatures published the UNC Studies in the Germanic Languages and Literatures series. Monographs, anthologies, and critical editions in the series covered an array of topics including medieval and modern literature, theater, linguistics, philology, onomastics, and the history of ideas. Through the generous support of the National Endowment for the Humanities and the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation, books in the series have been reissued in new paperback and open access digital editions. For a complete list of books visit www.uncpress.org. Literary Paternity, Literary Friendship Essays in Honor of Stanley Corngold edited by gerhard richter UNC Studies in the Germanic Languages and Literatures Number 125 Copyright © 2002 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons cc by-nc-nd license. To view a copy of the license, visit http://creativecommons. org/licenses. Suggested citation: Richter, Gerhard. Literary Paternity, Liter- ary Friendship: Essays in Honor of Stanley Corngold. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2002. doi: https://doi.org/ 10.5149/9780807861417_Richter Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Richter, Gerhard, editor. Title: Literary paternity, literary friendship : essays in honor of Stanley Corngold / edited by Gerhard Richter. Other titles: University of North Carolina studies in the Germanic languages and literatures ; no. 125. Description: Chapel Hill : University of North Carolina Press, [2002] Series: University of North Carolina studies in the Germanic languages and literatures | Includes bibliographical references. Identifiers: lccn 2001057825 | isbn 978-1-4696-5824-7 (pbk: alk. paper) | isbn 978-1-4696-5825-4 (ebook) Subjects: German literature — History and criticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Obdrzalek, Moral Transformation and the Love of Beauty In
    [Penultimate draft; Journal of the History of Philosophy, 2010 (Vol. 48), 415-44] Moral Transformation and the Love of Beauty in Plato's Symposium Suzanne Obdrzalek 1. Introduction On the day Eros was conceived, the gods were having a party to celebrate the birth of Aphrodite. His father-to-be, Poros (resource), was having a grand old time, and in fact got so carried away with the nectar that he passed out cold in Zeus’ garden. His mother-to-be, Penia (poverty), had not made the guest list, and was skulking around the gates. She was poor but cunning, and on seeing Poros sprawled on the ground, hatched a plot to relieve her poverty. She would sleep with him—after all, Poros was too drunk to know what was going on—and conceive a child who would enable her to escape her penury. The name of this child was Eros. This is the story of the origins of erōs which Diotima offers in her speech in the Symposium, and on the face of it, Plato couldn’t have come up with a stranger, more startling myth (203b1–204c6). Love, we learn, is born when a scheming, desperate woman who takes advantage of a drunk man who lies passed-out in the dirt. There is no mention of marriage, the wedding-bed, affection, beauty, even lust—no mention of any of the things which one would ordinarily associate with a myth about the origins of love. Plato is focusing on the seamier side of erōs; his myth describes just the sort of sexual encounter which might make a man mistrust erōs, in which a man is seduced by a cunning woman for the sake of profit.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University Recommended Citation Lamascus, Lorelle D., "Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium" (2010). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 71. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/71 LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN POVERTY AND EROS IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM By Lorelle D. Lamascus A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, In partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2010 ABSTRACT LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN EROS AND POVERTY IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University, 2010 This dissertation responds to a long-standing debate among scholars regarding the nature of Platonic Eros and its relation to lack. The more prominent account of Platonic Eros presents the lack of Eros as a deficiency or need experienced by the lover with respect to the object needed, lacked, or desired, so that the nature of Eros is construed as self-interested or acquisitive, subsisting only so long as the lover lacks the beloved object. This dissertation argues that such an interpretation neglects the different senses of lack present in the Symposium and presents an alternative interpretation of Eros based on the Symposium ’s presentation of Eros as the child of Poverty and Resource. Chapter one examines the origin and development of the position that Platonic Eros is acquisitive or egocentric and the influence this has had on subsequent interpretations of Plato’s thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Myth and Exegesis in Plotinus: How to Divide and Recompose Words and Things
    Rupkatha Journal on Interdisciplinary Studies in Humanities (ISSN 0975-2935), Vol. IX, No. 2, 2017 DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v9n2.08 Full Text: http://rupkatha.com/V9/n2/v9n208.pdf Myth and Exegesis in Plotinus: How to Divide and Recompose Words and Things José María Zamora Calvo Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain. Email: [email protected]. ORCID ID: 0000- 0001-7101-2234 Received May 25, 2017; Revised July 15, 2017; Accepted July 17, 2017; Published August 09, 2017. Abstract This paper explores the central thesis of the myth presented by Plotinus in his treatise On Love (III, 5 [50] 9, 24-29). Myth is a narrative that divides and deploys over time structures differentiated only by their “rank” or “powers”. First, the myth teaches, and then allows those who have understood it to “recompose” the data scattered through the discourse. The Hesiodic genealogy –Uranus, Kronos, Zeus– corresponds to the three main hypostases –the One, the Intelligence and the Soul. Likewise, the death and later dismemberment of child Dionysus symbolize the multiplicity and impassivity of sensible matter. Keywords: myth; Plotinus; exegesis; Neoplatonism; Dionysus Introduction Plotinus (204/5 – 270 C.E.) is considered first and foremost as an exegete of Plato who introduced profound changes into Platonism, in an age when “novelty” was not valued per se. As Dodds (1960, p. 2) remarks, the essence of Plotinus’ system stems more from the new sense transmitted by the whole to the parts, than in the parts considered separately one from another. However, according to Plotinus, if the truth was discovered long ago, and is deposited in the Hellenic tradition, especially under the authority of Plato’s dialogues, it has still to be clarified, as it was not always clearly stated (ἀναπεπταμένως) (Ennead V 1 [10] 8, 11; see Narbonne, Achard & Ferroni, 2014, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Predation by Three Hemipterans on The
    WAITE INSTITUTE 28. b.e LIBR.ARY PRTJDAÎTON BY THREE HE¡4IPTERANS ON TI'IE NATIVfi BUÐWORM' HET'TOTHTS PUNCTTGER WALLENGR}¡N, (I,EPÏÐOPTERA : NOCTUIDAE) by Muhammad Saeed Awan M"Sc. (Sind) (Unir,rersity of Sind, Hyderabad, Pakistan) lr thesis subnitte<l for the degree of Doctor of trhilosophy in the Faculty of Agricul.tural Science at The UniversitY of Adelaíde Department of EntomologY Waite Agricutltur:al Research Institute The University of. Adelaide South Australia l4ay I9Bt To My Par:ents Frontispiece Adult (9) Oec¿a; ia schefl.enbergii feecli,ng on late fifth caterpillar (kiiled irr hc't- water). t_ TABLE OE CONTEMTS I Bse--Ue.. I SUMMÀRY vii DECLARATTON x ACKNOI^ILEDCflI'IENTS xi CIIAPTER 1. GEIíERAI, ]}¡TRODUCTTON 1 1". r Estímate of global pest damage I r.2 Pest cont¡6] practices and associated problems I r.3 Bio-control potentíal of natural enemies 4 L.4 Natural enemies and population ecologists 5 r.5 Economic status of H. punctiger 6 1,6 Natural enemies of H. pungtiger and other Hel-iothis species in Australia 7 r-7 Control of HeLiotltis spp. in Ausùralia and elsewhere I r.8 Biology of H. punctiger 10 1.9 objects of present study 11 CHAPTER 2. METHODS OF REARING STOCKCULTURES L2 2.L Predator cultures 12 2.2 HeLiothis punctiger culture 13 CHAPTER 3. BIOLOGICAL STUDIES T5 3.1 Introduction 15 a) Egg incubation period and egg viabilities of three species at constant temPeratures I5 3-2.L Methcds 15 3.2.2 Results and Discussion 16 3.3 Rate of development and survival of juveniles of three species L7 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cambridge Companion to Greek Mythology Edited by Roger D
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-84520-5 — The Cambridge Companion to Greek Mythology Edited by Roger D. Woodard Index More Information Index S A Collection of Wonders from the Entire Admetus, 449 Earth Arranged by Locality, 238, 247 Adonis, 441, 450 A Common Chorus, 446 Adrastia, 232 A Streetcar Named Desire, 444 Adrastus, 337 A View from the Bridge, 444 adultery, 8, 362, 417 A Wonder Book, 11, 384 Aeacus, 215, 230, 232, 242 Abas, 373 Aeetes, 17, 18 Abdera, 216 Aegean Sea, 269–70, 279–80 Acarnania, 326 Aegeus, 26, 255, 257–8, 270, 273–4; see Accius, 83, 146, 355 also Aigeus Achaea, 280, 334 Aegeus, 194 Achaeans, 24, 37, 56–9, 61–2, 73, 78, Aegicores, 279 147, 191, 280, 335–6, 346–7; see also Aegids, 272–4 Achaians Aegina, 58, 349 Achaeus, 280 Aegipan, 98 Achaians, 458; see also Achaeans aegis, 146, 264, 269, 272, 385 Acharnians, 193, 199–200, 202, Aegisthus, 192 325 Aegyptus, 173 Achelous, 326 Aelius Theon, 356 Acheron, 319 , 322, 417 Aenea, 348 Achilles, 25, 31 , 33-8, 48, 54–9, 63–71, Aeneaden, 359 78–9, 81–2, 84, 91, 105, 123, 138, Aeneas, 91, 291, 347–8, 355–6, 359, 369, 147, 167, 169, 199, 201, 291, 296, 378–9, 417, 433 302, 31 0 , 323, 325, 335, 350, 359, 361, Aeneid, 346, 357–9, 379, 410, 413, 415, 404, 408, 433, 457–8, 460 417, 422 Acrisius, 331 Aeolians, 280 Acropolis, 203, 206, 258, 260, 280, 295, Aeolic (traditions, lands, etc.), 33–5, 38, 298–301, 313 , 315 , 338–41, 347 41, 48, 68, 83 Actaeon, 293, 366–7, 441 Aeolic meter, 275, 277; see also meter Actorione, 290 Aeolosicon, 194, 197 Acusilaus, 242, 244–5, 281 Aeolus, 197, 247, 280, 373 Ad Familiares, 246 Aeolus, 197 Adam Bede, 436 Aerope, 221 Addison, Joseph, 427, 435, 440, 444 Aeschylus, 19, 167, 172, 174–5, 178, 185, Adeimantus, 215 196, 204, 230, 336, 351, 430–1, 436–7, adharma, 129 440, 443–4 511 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-84520-5 — The Cambridge Companion to Greek Mythology Edited by Roger D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Love of Nike
    THE LOVE OF NIKE: ON THE DENIALS OF RACIALIZED PATRIARCHY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF COURAGEOUS OVERCOMING by DANA L. ROGNLIE A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School of the University of Oregon in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy June 2018 DISSERTATION APPROVAL PAGE Student: Dana L. Rognlie Title: The Love of Nike: On the Denials of Racialized Patriarchy and the Philosophy of Courageous Overcoming This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Doctor of Philosophy degree in the Department of Philosophy: Bonnie J. Mann Chair Malcolm Wilson Core Member Rocío Zambrana Core Member Jennifer J. Freyd Institutional Representative and Sara D. Hodges Interim Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School Original approval signatures are on file with the University of Oregon Graduate School. Degree awarded June 2018. ii © 2018 Dana L. Rognlie This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (United States) License. iii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Dana L. Rognlie Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy June 2018 Title: The Love of Nike: On the Denials of Racialized Patriarchy and the Philosophy of Courageous Overcoming Motivated by student survivors of sexual violence at the ‘University of Nike,’ this dissertation claims the denial of trauma is a central motor to the temporal operation of racialized patriarchy and its philonikian, or ‘victory-loving,’ notions of masculinity. I bear witness to this ‘temporality of denial’ in the institutional responses of the University of Oregon and UO-alum Phil Knight’s Nike corporation to the group sexual assault of Jane Doe by three university men’s basketball players.
    [Show full text]
  • Per030015 1913 00216.Pdf
    x.x *U» Avtnid» •« *^.*è^» *—.¦**—.. ^^^^ ^--» ^——lidirtar-ctaf» - BRASFMENDES Dl ALMEIDA DOD». «MUHDO />$-.-==3 JORNAL ¦¦5=3r_íí^^_-^i=í<-=.~_=-—— •'' -,. —=—*=:*Arr:-.T-—-- -'-'-' -*" ¦^•i-^- ,__ ' ^r-zzz*^. :^_=z_- i "~ - Segunda-feira, 4 de Agoslo de 1913^^^'"^ AN^tXIH h- RldT DK JANEIRO £ [ft) ._JL um .enhnr .d, •"J pnBCI8A»8E parara i«*.il*â"»i*nt.i, rm lllllfl. t"«- -xii'1'rt.v dc .-:.. *i(-*í nn l.ieita.li. n.i.no t««. ijil l( EXPEDIENTE C»>HHW> IU. ¦ ¦'., ** .,'.¦ 1,11.1,. Ir, BO | „,t*T,„Ulu?rosor'?,, ,11. «M^^^^m^^^^ A DO DIA itiüi.» '».-n«top*»r#tí>8 inw^r*wf**w~vvvvTr*~í~i" ¦¦¦¦¦¦¦ ¦»«_ QUESTÃO Iraí.all.o carioca e ..".o d'« ' «r i l,l.'i]A-Sl«: tinii m...;ii co-litco», lem a aua urg»Mi.'*«ao »» faícllilo «itleltfio paru a.iueiiaa ou i.oitiiKuríu. .|Uo roauiiiu o Fiidaccao e Adralnintrarla! «rA.mtiK . lurnnniulelra; na mui abso uuminie idi.nii«*a en«omm« .n. oaptlaaj «ia l>«.r«»i.». irl.iul variado, lave e 110 Mi,/. d., Atirmiioi so. oa» dia grandes »till>a conenrtar .oi.r.a Aviiilda nlo Branco ni. «ni ii, so.rn. mí.iis'i*i.ll«.'a eii.|.rega'h.«i iiomfaiioos beta r .....ni «• branca, 'tm comproni|.«ua. pai* ,12* ia lornetii. |ili'itu«rapl.la *fSt\ ir conta ni «ua Vl7*.t*_^t>a<à. i ^S. ^*_írf tHLon « alteMailo» de tonduola romeei» aOn(fi< p.iier aclar tuaiar : n. <"• l.UOA-SE uma num .ecoa «iue ia4.a: terá l.o::. trainment» •.
    [Show full text]
  • Sut Effaith Gaiff Y Gem Fawr A'r Bel-Droed Y Fro?
    ru ... sut effaith gaiff y gem fawr a'r bel-droed y fro? (Tudalen gefn) RHIF 294 Tachwedd 2002 PRIS 40c • • Ar 01dros 80 mlynedd, mae'r Wyl yn 01 Pensaer mewn welingtons mcwn cae yn mesur twmpath a adawyd eiliadau ynghynt gao Blodwen y fuwch; dau gant 0 hwyaid plastig coch, melyn a glas yn nofio mewn afon; chwech 0 ddynion nobl yn gafael yn dynn am ei gilydd 0 dan orchudd blastig; ffarmwrs cryf mewn gwisg wen p.v,c. yn dringo polyn llithrig i fyrstio balwn; helfa drysor yn y tywyllwch. Na, nid cyfres newydd 0 Doctor Who, ond wythnos Ffair Nant yn Nant Peris! Ffarwel hen Ifair, dy ddyddiau fo beth fyddai atgyfodi 'Ffsir Heb rif, yn 119wn anrhydedd: Nanr' a'i Uu go i brysurdcb yr Yn deilchion boed YWyddfa fawr unfed ganrif ar hugain. Pan gwrddi di a'th ddiwedd. Yn draddodiadol, ffair Hugh Lunt, 1912. amaethyddol boblogaidd Dyna oedd proffwydoliaeth ydoedd ar y deunawfed 0 Fedi - drist Hugh Lunt yn fuan wedi amser i werthu cynnyrch troad y ganrif ddiwethaf Daeth amaethyddol a da byw, ond fe y ffair i ben dan amgylchiadau oedd hefyd yn amscr i fwynhau anodd dros ddeuzain a chymdeithasu a dyna ocdd y mlynedd yn 01 ond aros i wnaeth Vr W>'ddfa - er prif fwriad tu 61 ailddechrau'r gwaetha' bygythiad y ffair eleni - tynnu pobl at ei bardd, er bod colled enbyd gilydd. Wrth gwrs, nid oedd modd cacl sioe amaethyddol i'r pcntref 0 golli i ail-grcu'r traddodlad a ocdd yn ond llwyddw yd 11\V)'1 a'r mwvnhsd nifer 0 arbcnnIo ~uwn ~ bobl Nant trwv a'r ardal.
    [Show full text]
  • GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. Del – 1 IMMORTALS
    BIOtransfer GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. del – 1 IMMORTALS GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. del IMMORTALS KAZALO: 1 Immortals 1.1 Olympian deities 2 1.2 Protogenoi (primordial) 3 1.3 Titans 4 1.4 Gigantes (giants) 6 1.5 Personified concepts 7 1.6 Chthonic deities 12 1.7 Sea deities 13 1.8 Sky deities 16 1.9 Rustic deities 19 1.10 Agricultural deities 31 1.11 Deified mortals 32 1.12 Health deities 33 1.13 Other deities 34 1.14 Seznam z merilnimi podatki o BIOtransferu 37 Vir: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Greek_gods Ljubljana, 04.04.2013 Stran 1 od 50 121010_BR_FOTO_grške_mitološke_osebe_1.del BIOtransfer GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. del – 1 IMMORTALS 1 IMMORTALS 1.1 OLYMPIAN DEITIES TWELVE OLYMPIANS 1. Aphrodite 2. Apollo 3. Ares 4. Artemis 5. Athena 6. Demeter 7. Dionysus 8. Hades 9. Hephaestus 10. Hera 11. Hermes 12. Hestia 13. Poseidon 14. Zeus Ljubljana, 04.04.2013 Stran 2 od 50 121010_BR_FOTO_grške_mitološke_osebe_1.del BIOtransfer GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. del – 1 IMMORTALS 1.2 PROTOGENOI (PRIMORDIAL) 15. Aether 16. Ananke 17. Erebos or Erebus 18. Gaia or Gaea 19. Hemera 20. Chaos 21. Chronos 22. The Nesoi 23. Nyx or Night 24. Uranus 25. The Ourea 26. Phanes 27. Pontus 28. Tartarus 29. Thalassa Ljubljana, 04.04.2013 Stran 3 od 50 121010_BR_FOTO_grške_mitološke_osebe_1.del BIOtransfer GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1. del – 1 IMMORTALS 1.3 TITANS THE TWELVE TITANS 30. Hyperion 31. Iapetus 32. Coeus 33. Crius 34. Cronus 35. Mnemosyne 36. Oceanus 37. Phoebe 38. Rhea 39. Tethys 40. Theia 41. Themis Ljubljana, 04.04.2013 Stran 4 od 50 121010_BR_FOTO_grške_mitološke_osebe_1.del BIOtransfer GRŠKE MITOLOŠKE OSEBE 1.
    [Show full text]