Resúmenes IV Coloquio Internacional Sociedad Chilena De Filosofía Analítica (SCFA)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Resúmenes IV Coloquio Internacional Sociedad Chilena De Filosofía Analítica (SCFA) Resúmenes IV Coloquio Internacional Sociedad Chilena de Filosofía Analítica (SCFA) Departamento de Filosofía, Universidad Alberto Hurtado Instituto de Filosofía, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile Santiago, 25 al 28 de marzo de 2014 Representacionalismo, disyuntivismo y el problema de la alucinación Francisco Pereira Universidad Alberto Hurtado, Chile [email protected] Hay dos clases de teorías que protagonizan el debate contemporáneo sobre la estructura metafísica de la experiencia perceptual. Por una parte, tenemos las teorías representacionalistas que aspiran a dar una caracterización homogénea a todas nuestras experiencias perceptuales, sean estas percepciones, ilusiones o alucinaciones en virtud de la instanciación de propiedades representacionales primitivas que conforman un estructura metafísica común. Por otra parte, están las teorías relacionales (particularmente el “disyuntivismo”) que niegan por completo que exista un factor metafísico común a las percepciones, incluyendo las ilusiones, y a las alucinaciones que no podemos discriminar introspectivamente de ellas. En esta presentación me centraré en un problema específico que debe enfrentar el teórico relacional disyuntivista: “el problema de la alucinación”, es decir, el problema que tiene toda teoría disyuntiva para dar cuenta de aquellos aspectos que supuestamente las percepciones y sus contrapartes alucinatorias comparten a nivel fenomenológico y cognitivo, sin referir a la existencia de factores estructurales de orden metafísico en común. Abordaré esta temática en tres etapas diferentes: (i) Primero, especificaré los compromisos del disyuntivismo en relación al problema de la alucinación, (ii) Segundo, me detendré en las alucinaciones desde una perspectiva empírica y filosófica, (iii) Finalmente, argumentaré que el disyuntivismo es una tesis plausible si comprende la indiscriminabilidad como una propiedad epistémica negativa fundada, al menos en parte, en una confusión metacognitiva implícita que nos lleva a experimentar episodios no perceptuales como si fueran reales. Emotional Perception as Perception of Values. A Phenomenological Analysis Sarah Songhorian y Francesca Forle PERSONA Research Centre in Phenomenology and Sciences of the Person – CNC Center for Cognitive Neuroscience, San Raffaele University, Italia [email protected] In contemporary debate there are several different theories of emotions. There are feeling theories (James 1884; Lange 1885), conative theories (Frijda 1988) and cognitive ones. Within the latter kind both conceptualist perspectives (Solomon 1976) and non-conceptualist ones (Deonna, Teroni 2012; Helm 2009) can be found. Our aim in this paper is that of understanding Max Scheler’s work within a non-conceptualist cognitive theory of emotions and trying to propose the idea that emotions can be described as perceptions of values. In order to do so, we will start giving the schelerian account of a particular kind of emotion, that is vicarious emotions (Scheler 1923). This example will prove particularly relevant because vicarious emotions are one of the clearest cases in which we can identify the object as valuable, specifically because they involve other people – commonly considered as 1 valuable – and their affective states. The same account that will be provided here can also be applied to the other emotional experiences. We just chose the one we felt was the clearest. We will focus therefore on the careful analysis of fellow-feelings conducted by Scheler. We will propose a three variables model that will help us explain the elements of vicarious emotions, focusing, in particularly, on the object of those phenomena. We will also provide an account of the difference between the nature of those phenomena and the level of consciousness that the subject of them can experience in any given case. In particular, we will see that fellow-feelings in general have as their object valuable features, either another person or – there is often no disjunction here, but a conjunction – a specific affective state of that person. The level of consciousness of the subject sharing the emotion is not at issue here, since it does not change the nature of the experience itself or its objective source. As we will see, even in the case of emotional infection, for instance, where Anne doesn’t know why her mood changed entering a cheerful party, it is still true that that emotion comes from somewhere – another person or a group of people. The nature of the experience is not at all different because of the fact that she cannot identify such an origin. Then, having shown that the object of fellow-feelings in general are value-qualities, we will investigate which specific act is able to present them in propria persona (Husserl 1901, 1913). We will show that we can describe this act as a kind of perception, in particular affective perception. So, if fellow-feelings, as vicarious emotions, have value-qualities as their objects, and if value-qualities are presented in propria persona in the act of affective perception, then we can describe emotions as fellow- feelings as a particular kind of value perception. Fellow-feelings, as a specific kind of emotion, can then be considered in parallel with other forms of perceptions, so that our account can be described as a partially non-conceptualist view on emotions as acts of presentation of value-qualities. References Darwall S. (1998), “Empathy, Sympathy, Care”, Philosophical Studies, 89, pp. 261–282. Deonna J. A., Teroni F. (2012), The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction, London/New York: Routledge. De Monticelli R. (2008), L’ordine del cuore. Etica e teoria del sentire, Garzanti, Milano. De Monticelli R. (2009), La novità di ognuno. Persona e libertà, Garzanti, Milano. De Monticelli, R., Conni, C. (2008), Ontologia del nuovo. La rivoluzione fenomenologica e la ricerca oggi. Bruno Mondadori, Milano. Eisenberg N., Strayer J. (1987), Empathy and Its Development, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Frijda N.H. (1988), “The Laws of Emotion”, American Psychologist, 43, pp. 349-358. Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The Phenomenological Mind. An Introduction toPhilosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. Routledge, London & New York. Helm B. W. (2009), “Emotions as Evaluative Feelings”, Emotion Review, 1/3, pp. 248-255. Husserl, E. (1901). Logical Investigations, Trans. J. N. Findlay, Routledge, London 2001. Husserl, E. (1913). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological Philosophy, Kluwer Academic Publisher, Boston 1989. James W. (1884), “What is an Emotion?”, Mind, 9/34, pp. 188-205. Lange C. G. (1885), “Ueber Gemüthsbewegungen. Eine psycho-physiologische Studie”, trans. Eng. Haupt I. A., “The Emotions. A Psychophysiological Study”, in Dunlap K. (Ed.)(1922), The Emotions. Volume I. Psychology Classics, Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins Company, pp. 33-90. Scheler M. (1913), Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt Toward a Foundation of An Ethical Personalism, transl. M. S. Frings and R. L. Funk, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL, 1973. Scheler M. (1923), The Nature of Sympathy, transl. P. Heath, Routledge & Keegan Paul, London, 1973. Scheler M. (1933), Selected Philosophical Essays, transl. John Wild et al., Northwestern University Press, Northwestern, 1973. Solomon R. C. (1976), The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life, Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group, re-edited (1993) Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Stein E. (1917), On the Problem of Empathy, ICS Publications, Washington, D.C. 1989. Stern D. N. (1977), The First Relationship: Infant and Mother, Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Steuber K. R. (2006), Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology and the Human Sciences, Cambridge, MIT Press. 2 Whiting D. (2011), “The Feeling Theory of Emotion and the Object-Directed Emotions”, European Journal of Philosophy, 19/2, pp. 281-303. Zahavi D. (2001), "Beyond Empathy. Phenomenological Approaches to Intersubjectivity", Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8/5-7, pp. 151–167. Zahavi D. (2007), "Expression and Empathy", In D. Hutto, M. Ratcliffe (editors), Folk Psychology Reassessed, Springer, pp. 25–40. Zahavi D. (2010), “Max Scheler”, In A. Schrift (editor), History of Continental Philosophy III, Acumen Press, Edinburgh, pp. 171186. Zahavi D. (2012), “Basic Empathy and Complex Empathy”, Emotion Review, 4/1, pp. 81-82. Second-Order Knowledge and Indexicality Yves Bouchard Université de Sherbrooke, Canada [email protected] The KK-thesis stipulates that Ka ⊃ KaKa, in other words, that if an agent a knows a proposition ' then she knows that she knows that . This is an epistemic counterpart of the modal axiom 4, i.e., ⊃ . In a standard modal system like KT, the inclusion of 4 allows the addition or the reduction of homogeneous iterated modalities (iterated necessity operators or iterated possibility operators can be homogeneously augmented or homogeneously reduced to one single operator). This behavior of the system, which is S4, corresponds to one particular interpretation of the notion of necessity, according to which necessity is understood through a reflexive and transitive accessibility relation. In the same fashion, the epistemic operator obeys a certain understanding of the notion of knowledge when it exhibits the properties of S4. Whereas in alethic logic there is no a priori difficulty with the perspective of several notions of necessity (depending on ontological considerations, for instance), in epistemic logic it seems
Recommended publications
  • EPISTEMOLOGY and PHILOSOPHY of MIND HISTORICAL Historical Dictionaries of Religions, Philosophies, and Movements, No
    PHILOSOPHY • EPISTEMOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY OF MIND HISTORICAL Historical Dictionaries of Religions, Philosophies, and Movements, No. 70 DICTIONARY OF BAERGEN Epistemology Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that investigates our beliefs, evidence, and claims of knowledge. It is one of the core areas of philosophy and is relevant to an DICTIONARY astonishingly broad range of issues and situations. Epistemological issues arise when HISTORICAL we recognize that there is a fact of the matter but we do not know what it is; when we wonder about the future, the past, or distant places; and when we seek answers in the sciences and even in our entertainment (for example, murder mysteries and comedies of misunderstanding). OF Epistemology Historical Dictionary of Epistemology provides an overview of this field of study and its theories, concepts, and personalities. It begins with a chronology of important events (from 385 BC to AD 2005) and is followed by an introduction, which gives a historical overview. The book contains more than 500 entries covering notable concepts, theo- ries, arguments, publications, issues, and philosophers and concludes with an exten- sive bibliography of historical and contemporary epistemological works. Students and those who want to acquaint themselves with epistemology will be greatly aided by this book. RALPH BAERGEN is a professor of philosophy at Idaho State University. For orders and information please contact the publisher SCARECROW PRESS, INC. A wholly owned subsidiary of ISBN-13: 978-0-8108-5518-2 The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN-10: 0-8108-5518-6 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200 Lanham, Maryland 20706 1-800-462-6420 • fax 717-794-3803 www.scarecrowpress.com RALPH BAERGEN HDEpistempologyLITH.indd 1 6/12/06 1:07:32 PM 06-236_01_Front.qxd 6/12/06 12:54 PM Page i HISTORICAL DICTIONARIES OF RELIGIONS, PHILOSOPHIES, AND MOVEMENTS Jon Woronoff, Series Editor 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Forming the Mind Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind
    FORMING THE MIND STUDIES IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY OF MIND Volume 5 Editors Henrik Lagerlund, The University of Western Ontario, Canada Mikko Yrjönsuuri, Academy of Finland and University of Jyväskylä, Finland Board of Consulting Editors Lilli Alanen, Uppsala University, Sweden Joël Biard, University of Tours, France Michael Della Rocca, Yale University, U.S.A. Eyjólfur Emilsson, University of Oslo, Norway André Gombay, University of Toronto, Canada Patricia Kitcher, Columbia University, U.S.A. Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki, Finland Béatrice M. Longuenesse, New York University, U.S.A. Calvin Normore, University of California, Los Angeles, U.S.A. Aims and Scope The aim of the series is to foster historical research into the nature of thinking and the workings of the mind. The volumes address topics of intellectual history that would nowadays fall into different disciplines like philosophy of mind, philo- sophical psychology, artificial intelligence, cognitive science, etc. The monographs and collections of articles in the series are historically reliable as well as congenial to the contemporary reader. They provide original insights into central contem- porary problems by looking at them in historical contexts, addressing issues like consciousness, representation and intentionality, mind and body, the self and the emotions. In this way, the books open up new perspectives for research on these topics. FORMING THE MIND Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment Edited by HENRIK LAGERLUND The University of Western Ontario, Canada A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-1-4020-6083-0 (HB) ISBN 978-1-4020-6084-7 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Knowledge, Belief and Conditional Belief Guillaume Aucher
    Principles of Knowledge, Belief and Conditional Belief Guillaume Aucher To cite this version: Guillaume Aucher. Principles of Knowledge, Belief and Conditional Belief. Interdisciplinary Works in Logic, Epistemology, Psychology and Linguistics, pp.97 - 134, 2014, 10.1007/978-3-319-03044-9_5. hal-01098789 HAL Id: hal-01098789 https://hal.inria.fr/hal-01098789 Submitted on 29 Dec 2014 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Principles of knowledge, belief and conditional belief Guillaume Aucher 1 Introduction Elucidating the nature of the relationship between knowledge and belief is an old issue in epistemology dating back at least to Plato. Two approaches to addressing this problem stand out from the rest. The first consists in providing a definition of knowledge, in terms of belief, that would somehow pin down the essential ingredient binding knowledge to belief. The second consists in providing a complete characterization of this relationship in terms of logical principles relating these two notions. The accomplishement of either of these two objectives would certainly contribute to solving this problem. The success of the first approach is hindered by the so-called ‘Gettier problem’. Until recently, the view that knowledge could be defined in terms of belief as ‘justified true belief’ was endorsed by most philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Transparency and the KK Principle
    Transparency and the KK Principle Nilanjan Das (MIT) and Bernhard Salow (Trinity College Cambridge) Penultimate Draft – Please Cite Published Version Abstract An important question in epistemology is whether the KK principle is true, i.e., whether an agent who knows that p is also thereby in a position to know that she knows that p. We explain how a “transparency” account of self-knowledge, which maintains that we learn about our attitudes towards a proposition by reflecting not on ourselves but rather on that very proposition, supports an affirmative answer. In particular, we show that such an account allows us to reconcile a version of the KK principle with an “externalist” or “reliabilist” conception of knowledge commonly thought to make that principle particularly problematic. The KK principle states that someone who knows that p is in a position to know that she knows that p. In addition to an enviable pedigree of historical supporters,1 this thesis has considerable intuitive appeal. For, to put it roughly, if the KK principle is false, rational agents can be alienated from their own attitudes and actions in a counterintuitive manner. One way to bring this out is by noting that there seems something self-undermining or incoherent about someone who says (in thought or out loud) something of the form “while it is raining, I’m not willing to take a stance on whether I know that it is.” But if nothing in the vicinity of the KK principle is correct, this is hard to explain. For if there are counterexamples to KK, there are fully coherent agents who know p without being in a position to know that they know this.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis
    A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis James R. Beebe (University at Buffalo) International Journal for the Study of Skepticism (forthcoming) In Beebe (2011), I argued against the widespread reluctance of philosophers to treat skeptical challenges to our a priori knowledge of necessary truths with the same seriousness as skeptical challenges to our a posteriori knowledge of contingent truths. Vahid (2013) offers several reasons for thinking the unequal treatment of these two kinds of skepticism is justified, one of which is a priori skepticism’s seeming dependence upon the widely scorned KK thesis. In the present article, I defend a priori skepticism against Vahid’s criticisms. Keywords: Skepticism; a priori skepticism; second-order knowledge; KK thesis In a previous issue of this journal, Hamid Vahid (2013) offers a thorough examination of some recent non-standard approaches to philosophical skepticism (e.g., Beebe 2010; 2011; Kraft MS; Kung MS; Schaffer 2010). One non-standard form of skepticism, dubbed ‘a priori skepticism,’ challenges our ability to have a priori knowledge of necessary truths (cf. Beebe 2011). Against proponents of these approaches, Vahid argues that many non-standard skeptical challenges fail to raise any significant doubts concerning first-order knowledge claims—i.e., claims of the form ‘S knows that p,’ for some domain of propositions. Rather, Vahid maintains that these challenges at best contest our ability to have second-order knowledge—i.e., to know that we know the propositions in question. Because skepticism about second-order knowledge claims is seen as significantly less threatening to our overall view of ourselves as knowledgeable creatures, Vahid suggests that non-standard skepticism should be considered philosophically less interesting than its supporters maintain.
    [Show full text]
  • The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas
    Knowing and Trusting: The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas by Matthew Kent Siebert A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 © Copyright by Matthew Kent Siebert, 2014 Knowing and Trusting The Medieval Social Epistemologies of Augustine and Aquinas Matthew Kent Siebert Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2014 Abstract This dissertation is an introductory exploration of two influential medieval thinkers, Augustine and Aquinas, on the topic of testimony. I explain how Augustine’s view that testimony is a source of knowledge (notitia) developed through four stages, and argue that on Augustine’s view testimonial belief is justified inferentially. I argue that Aquinas thinks some testimonial belief is justified inferentially, and some is justified by adhering to the speaker as the formal object of one’s belief, on the grounds that the speaker is truthful. I argue that these provide knowledge when they provide cognitio. And I argue that Aquinas’s view can be developed into a plausible account of testimonial trust and trustworthiness. ii Acknowledgments I am extremely grateful for the guidance and support of Peter King, Martin Pickavé, and Jennifer Nagel in the writing of this dissertation. I am also grateful to Deborah Black, Michael Siebert, Simona Vucu, and Ian Drummond, for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts of some of these chapters. And I am grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Government of Ontario, and the University of Toronto for financial support.
    [Show full text]
  • 8897567 Lprob 1.Pdf
    FORMING THE MIND STUDIES IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY OF MIND Volume 5 Editors Henrik Lagerlund, The University of Western Ontario, Canada Mikko Yrjönsuuri, Academy of Finland and University of Jyväskylä, Finland Board of Consulting Editors Lilli Alanen, Uppsala University, Sweden Joël Biard, University of Tours, France Michael Della Rocca, Yale University, U.S.A. Eyjólfur Emilsson, University of Oslo, Norway André Gombay, University of Toronto, Canada Patricia Kitcher, Columbia University, U.S.A. Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki, Finland Béatrice M. Longuenesse, New York University, U.S.A. Calvin Normore, University of California, Los Angeles, U.S.A. Aims and Scope The aim of the series is to foster historical research into the nature of thinking and the workings of the mind. The volumes address topics of intellectual history that would nowadays fall into different disciplines like philosophy of mind, philo- sophical psychology, artificial intelligence, cognitive science, etc. The monographs and collections of articles in the series are historically reliable as well as congenial to the contemporary reader. They provide original insights into central contem- porary problems by looking at them in historical contexts, addressing issues like consciousness, representation and intentionality, mind and body, the self and the emotions. In this way, the books open up new perspectives for research on these topics. FORMING THE MIND Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment Edited by HENRIK LAGERLUND The University of Western Ontario, Canada A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-1-4020-6083-0 (HB) ISBN 978-1-4020-6084-7 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka
    ANNOTATED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF JAAKKO HINTIKKA 1953 Books (a) Distributive Normal Forms in the Calculus of Predicates, Acta Philosophica Fennica 6, (1953), 71pp. By distributing quantifiers deeper and deeper into the formulas of a finite first-order language, with or without identity, at the same time as truth-functions are transformed into a propositional normal form, we obtain a simple normal form for such formulas. This refutes the conjecture of Hilbert and Bernays that “a simply characterizable normal form is not obtainable in this way in general.” The basic properties of these distributive normal forms are established, including a set of sufficient conditions of inconsistency. Papers (a) “A New Approach to Sentential Logic”, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Commentationes Physico-Mathematicae 17, no. 3, (1953), 13pp. 1954 Papers (a) “An Application of Logic to Algebra”, Mathematica Scandinavia 2, (1954), 243-246. 1955 Books (a) Two Papers on Symbolic Logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica 8, (1955), 115pp. (Includes “Form and Content in Quantification Theory”, 11-55, and “Reductions in the Theory of Types”, 57-115.) First paper: For a finite first-order language, the concept of a model set (m.s.) of formulas is defined by means of certain simple closure and compatibility conditions. Intuitively, a m.s. is a partial description of a possible world. A set of formulas is accordingly consistent if it can be embedded in some m.s.. A simple proof procedure is obtained by considering rules for an attempt to embed the negation of a sentence S in a m.s.. If such an attempt fails in all directions, a proof is obtained for S.
    [Show full text]
  • Could KK Be OK?
    Could KK be OK? Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy Penultimate Draft 1 Introduction The KK principle|the principle that knowing entails knowing that one knows|has seen better days. In the past it was defended by Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, Averro¨es, Aquinas, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and Prichard, to name a few.1 Today it languishes in disrepute.2 Louise Antony refers to it as \the principle, roundly rejected by epistemolo- gists of almost every stripe, that in order to know that P , I must know that I know that P ." (2004, p.12) Its fall is often thought of as closely linked to the rise of externalist theories of knowledge|theories that de-emphasize the role of the knower's reasons or justification for her beliefs (at least when reasons and justification are understood along traditional lines), and stress the importance of causal and/or nomological connections between the knower and the fact known.3 Despite its current unpopularity among epistemologists, the KK principle|or at least the failure of popular objections to the KK principle|is often presupposed in work outside of epistemology. Much work in philosophy of language, game theory, and For helpful comments and discussion, thanks to Brian Hedden, Augst´ınRayo, Damien Rochford, Miriam Schoenfield, Paulina Sliwa, Robert Stalnaker, Jonathan Vogel, Roger White, Steve Yablo, and audiences at Oxford, St. Andrews, and MIT. 1Hintikka (1962, pp.107-8), a staunch defender of the KK principle, mentions these and other promi- nent historical proponents. 2See esp. Williamson (2000), along with Alston (1980), Sorensen (1988), and others. 3See e.g., Hemp (2006).
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism, Information, and Closure: Dretske's Theory
    CHRISTOPH JA¨GER SKEPTICISM, INFORMATION, AND CLOSURE: DRETSKE’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE ABSTRACT. According to Fred Dretske’s externalist theory of knowledge a subject knows that p if and only if she believes that p and this belief is caused or causally sustained by the information that p. Another famous feature of Dretske’s episte- mology is his denial that knowledge is closed under known logical entailment. I argue that, given Dretske’s construal of information, he is in fact committed to the view that both information and knowledge are closed under known entailment. This has far-reaching consequences. For if it is true that, as Dretske also believes, accepting closure leads to skepticism, he must either embrace skepticism or abandon his information theory of knowledge. The latter alternative would seem to be pref- erable. But taking this route would deprive one of the most powerfully developed externalist epistemologies of its foundation. 1. EXTERNALISM, INFORMATION, AND THE KK THESIS Externalist theories of knowledge typically claim to provide an effective response to skepticism. One of the most influential exter- nalist epistemologies has been developed by Fred Dretske. The core idea of his theory is that: ðKÞ An epistemic subject knows of some object (or source of information) s that it has the property F if and only if the subject believes s to be F and this belief is caused (or causally sustained) by the information that s is F: Dretske has spelled out this view in great detail. According to the account of information laid out in his book Knowledge and the Flow of Information, a signal carries, relative to a given subject, the information that s is F if and only if the conditional probability of s’s being F, given the signal and the subject’s background knowledge, is 1, but, given only the subject’s background knowledge, is less than 1.1 The central feature of this account, which is primarily designed for perceptual knowledge, is that the information relation is veridical: Erkenntnis 61: 187–201, 2004.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Thomas Aquinas and The
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Thomas Aquinas and the Problem of Human Self-Knowledge A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy © Copyright All Rights Reserved By Therese Scarpelli Cory Washington, D.C. 2009 Thomas Aquinas and the Problem of Human Self-Knowledge Therese Scarpelli Cory, Ph.D. Director: John F. Wippel, Ph.D. This dissertation presents a comprehensive analysis of Thomas Aquinas’s theory of self-knowledge, examining each of the four kinds of self-knowledge he identifies: (1) actual perception of one’s existence (actual self-awareness); (2) habitual self-awareness; (3) apprehension of the soul’s nature; and (4) the judgment of this apprehension in light of divine truth. Broadly speaking, it contends that Thomas is attentive to experienced phenomena and provides precise and thoughtful analyses of phenomena such as bodily consciousness, implicit and explicit awareness of oneself as subject, unified perception of the self as a single subject, and scientific knowledge of the soul’s nature. Moreover, his explanation of self-knowledge is consistent with the principles of his general theory of knowledge, while it also takes into account the unique characteristics of an act of knowledge wherein the knower is the known, and integrates both Augustinian and Aristotelian principles. Thus Thomas’s comments on self-knowledge constitute a carefully nuanced doctrine with significant implications for both his theory of knowledge and his explanation of human subjectivity. The first chapter examines the doctrine of two of his main sources, Augustine and Aristotle, while placing special emphasis on the way that difficulties of interpretation of texts in both these thinkers helped shape Thomas’s own conception of self-knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Flawedargumentfinal
    Okasha, S. (2013). On a flawed argument against the KK principle. Analysis, 73(1), 80-86. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans133 Early version, also known as pre-print Link to published version (if available): 10.1093/analys/ans133 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document A preprint version of an article that has been accepted for publication in Analysis © The Author. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Analysis Trust. All rights reserved. University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ On a flawed argument against the KK principle Abstract It is often claimed that externalist analyses of knowledge imply the falsity of the KK principle. However one of the standard arguments for this claim in the literature rests on a straightforward intensional fallacy. The fallacy is exposed and discussed. Keywords: externalism, KK principle, reliabilism, internalism, intensional fallacy Externalists in epistemology typically reject the KK principle – which says that if a subject knows that p, then she knows that she knows that p. Indeed many epistemologists write as if it is obvious that the KK principle fails on an externalist analysis of knowledge. Surprisingly however, one of the standard arguments found in the literature for this claim is fallacious. The aim of this paper is to expose and document the fallacy. Externalism says that whether a subject‟s true belief constitutes knowledge depends on an „external‟ condition, i.e.
    [Show full text]