An Ethical Validity Claim for Discourse Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Ethical Validity Claim for Discourse Ethics ETHICAL VALIDITY: AN ETHICAL VALIDITY CLAIM FOR DISCOURSE ETHICS by JAMIE BURKE LINDSAY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2020 i © 2019 JAMIE BURKE LINDSAY All Rights Reserved ii Ethical Validity: An Ethical Validity Claim for Discourse Ethics by Jamie Lindsay This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _______________ ______________________________________ Date Omar Dabhour Chair of Examining Committee _______________ ______________________________________ Date Nickolas Pappas Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Linda Martín Alcoff Frank M. Kirkland Jeffrey Flynn (Fordham University) THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Ethical Validity: An Ethical Validity Claim for Discourse Ethics By Jamie Burke Lindsay Advisor: Linda Martín Alcoff Discourse ethicists generally are anti-realists about moral rightness, in that the rightness of moral norms is a matter of discursive justification, and is not grounded in or by any objective feature of the world. Put differently, the position is that rightness is wholly constructed by our moral practices. Further, discourse ethics and liberal theories of justice more broadly generally rely on a distinction between goods that are generalizable, and goods that are in some way context-bound and particularistic. Jürgen Habermas’ discourse ethics makes the distinction wholly formal, abstaining from any theoretical commitment to which goods are generalizable and leaving this as a matter for discursive deliberation. Those goods that are discursively determined to be generalizable are the object of valid moral norms, and those that are not generally justifiable as goods involve at best ethical values. In this dissertation, I argue – against Habermas – for a moral realist conception of discourse ethics, and for a substantive modification of the formal structure of Habermas’ position, in order to accommodate a validity claim attaching to ethical discourses. I argue that Habermas’ position requires a goodness claim, in addition to the rightness validity claim attaching to moral discourses. In the first chapter, I consider a couple of Habermas’ more idiosyncratic arguments, defending quasi-moral obligations to non-human animals, and arguing against non-therapeutic pre-birth genetic manipulation, governed only by market forces (or what he terms ‘liberal eugenics’). I argue that Habermas’ discourse theory of morality depends on a background general ethics that is at least under- iv theorized, a point which Habermas himself seems to begin to acknowledge, in The Future of Human Nature, in developing an ethics of the species when faced with the question of how to ethically value morality as a whole, suggesting the need for a specifically ethical validity claim. In the second chapter, I shift from the discourse theory of morality and ethics to the discourse theory of law and democracy, considering Habermas’ defenses of civil disobedience and his variable responses to humanitarian military intervention, particularly in Kosovo and Iraq. I argue that, as in the discourse theory of morality, Habermas’ discourse theory of law and democracy contains an implicit ethics. At the end of the second chapter, I consider Jacques Rancière’s theorization of a politics of dissensus, showing that Rancière is unable to justify his normative claim that there are better and worse sorts of policing. I show that this difficulty for Rancière is conceptually related to Habermas’ rejection of the possibility of an ethical validity claim. In the third chapter, I argue that moral feeling stands in a realist grounding relation to moral rightness, and that ethical feeling operates rather differently, and provides further guidance in developing an ethics integral to the discourse theory of morality and the discourse theory of law and democracy. I argue that Habermas’ account of moral feeling provides a referent, analogous to sense perception in truth-oriented discourses, a referent that is not wholly discursively produced. This suggests that Habermas must reject his antirealist reading of discourse theory. Then, I turn to the ethical feeling of hope, considering the role played by hope in discourse theory, and drawing out the implications for an ethical validity claim. I conclude by arguing that the presuppositions of discourse – including the values of inclusion and civility – are themselves ethical values. I argue that Habermas' necessary pragmatic presuppositions of communicative action are those of a particular – if generalizable – form of life, such that there is a worldview in discourse ethics, that they take the form of necessary preconditions of the moral point of view, much like the values put forward in Habermas’ “ethics of the species,” but that this means that, as Habermas himself maintains, these 'necessary v presuppositions' are not moral oughts, and yet, contra Habermas, they are worth valuing. Put differently, Habermas argues that the necessary pragmatic presuppositions are justified functionally or pragmatically, but I aim to show that the presuppositions are neither moral nor merely pragmatically justified but are properly ethical. This move would pluralize without radically relativizing the normative discourses of Habermasian discourse theory. In order to situate this dissertation within the broader contexts of ethics and political philosophy, in two appendices I critically engage the work of Allen Gewirth and Iris Marion Young. In the first chapter, I argue, against Allen Gewirth’s defense of universal moral human rights to freedom and well-being, that rather than leading to what he terms a ‘dialectically necessary’ conclusion, Gewirth’s argument is contingent on affirmation of the principle of strict correlativity of rights and duties, which he uses as a logical principle. Further, I argue that this in fact exhibits a larger problem, that Gewirth equivocates between sorts of necessity, conflating pragmatic necessity with logical necessity. In the second appendix, I start with a reconstruction of Young’s theory of justice, in order to deal with what appears to be an equivocation between two senses of ‘justice’: procedural justice understood in terms of democratic legitimation, governed by procedural norms including equality, inclusion, publicity, and reasonableness; and ideal justice understood in terms of self-determination and self-realization. Then, I argue that both the procedural and ideal accounts of justice rest on another ideal, the principle of the equal moral worth of persons, such that her overall account has a foundationalist structure: both procedural norms and the ideals of self-determination and self- realization are grounded in the ideal of the equal moral worth of persons. However, Young argues that ideals are only useful for awakening political imagination concerning alternatives to present conditions, such that the foundational ideal of Young’s theory provides a viable basis neither for the procedural norms Young defends nor for the norms of ideal justice. vi Jamie Burke Lindsay 9.13.19 Table of Contents Dissertation Introduction ................................................................................................................. 1 Chapter One: Ethical Validity ........................................................................................................... 5 (I.1) Habermas’ Discourse Ethics ......................................................................................................... 7 (I.2) Moral Norms vs. Ethical Values ................................................................................................. 18 (I.3) Quasi-Moral Obligations to Non-Human Animals & The Principle of Universalization (U) ....... 24 (I.4) Liberal Eugenics and an Ethics of the Species ............................................................................ 31 (I.5) Substantive Ethics ...................................................................................................................... 38 Chapter Two: Jürgen Habermas on Civil Disobedience and Military Intervention ........................... 51 (II.1) Habermas on Civil Disobedience .............................................................................................. 54 (II.2) Habermas on Humanitarian Military Intervention ................................................................... 66 (III.3) At the Limits of Habermas’ Discourse Theory of Law & Democracy ........................................ 80 Chapter Three: Normative Affect: From Immanuel Kant to Jürgen Habermas ................................. 92 (III.1) Kant’s Moral Feeling ................................................................................................................ 96 (III.2) Habermas and Affect ............................................................................................................. 105 (III.3) Generalizable Interests & Moral Feeling ............................................................................... 110 (III.4) The Ethical Feeling of Hope ................................................................................................... 121 Dissertation Conclusion ............................................................................................................... 137 (1) Overview of Dissertation
Recommended publications
  • Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition
    Tacit Tirukku#a#: Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Smith, Jason William. 2020. Tacit Tirukku#a#: Religion, Ethics, and Poetics in a Tamil Literary Tradition. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard Divinity School. Citable link https://nrs.harvard.edu/URN-3:HUL.INSTREPOS:37364524 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use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
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond the Principles of Bioethics: Facing the Consequences of Fundamental Moral Disagreement
    DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1677-2954.2012v11n1p13 BEYOND THE PRINCIPLES OF BIOETHICS: FACING THE CONSEQUENCES OF FUNDAMENTAL MORAL DISAGREEMENT H. TRISTRAM ENGELHARDT (Rice Universtiy / USA) ABSTRACT Given intractable secular moral pluralism, the force and significance of the four principles (autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice) of Tom Beauchamp and James Childress must be critically re-considered. This essay examines the history of the articulation of these four principles of bioethics, showing why initially there was an illusion of a common morality that led many to hold that the principles could give guidance across cultures. But there is no one sense of the content or the theoretical justification of these principles. In addition, a wide range of secular moral and bioethical choices has been demoralized into lifestyle choices; the force of the secular moral point of view has also been deflated, thus compounding moral pluralism. It is the political generation of the principles that provides a common morality in the sense of an established morality. The principles are best understood as embedded not in a common morality, sensu stricto, but in that morality that is established at law and public policy in a particular polity. Although moral pluralism is substantive and intractable at the level of moral content, in a particular polity a particular morality and a particular bioethics can be established, regarding which health care ethics consultants can be experts. Public morality and bioethics are at their roots a political reality. Keywords: Bioethics. Pluralism. Moral disagreement. Ethical particularism. RESUMO Dado o pluralismo moral secular intratável, a força e o significado dos quatro princípios (autonomia, beneficência, não maleficência e justiça) de Tom Beauchamp e James Childress precisam ser reconsiderados criticamente.
    [Show full text]
  • University at Buffalo Department of Philosophy Nousletter Interview with Jorge Gracia
    University at Buffalo Department of Philosophy Nousletter Interview with Jorge Gracia Jorge Gracia is a polymath. He works in metaphysics/ontology, philosophical historiography, philosophy of language/hermeneutics, ethnicity/race/nationality issues, Hispanic/Latino issues, medieval/scholastic philosophy, Cuban and Argentinian art, and Borges. Gracia’s earliest work was in medieval philosophy. His more than three decades of contributions to medieval philosophy were recently recognized by his being named the winner of the most prestigious award in the field in 2011, the American Catholic Philosophical Association’s Aquinas Medal. That put him in the ranks of Jacques Maritain, Etienne Gilson, Bernard Lonergan, Joseph Owens, G. E. M. Anscombe, Peter Geach, Michael Dummett, John Finnis, Brian Davies, Anthony Kenny, Alisdair McIntyre and one Pope, Karol Wojtyla, and now one saint. Even after Gracia redirected some of his intellectual energies into other branches of philosophy, UB was still being ranked by the Philosophical Gourmet Report (PGR) as one of the best schools in medieval philosophy: 13th in 2006 and in the 15-20 range in 2008. If there were PGR rankings for Latin American philosophy or the philosophy of race and ethnicity, Jorge Gracia’s work would have enabled us to be highly ranked in those fields, higher, I suspect, than UB is in any other philosophical specialization. In the 2010 Blackwell Companion to Latin American Philosophy, Gracia was listed as one of the 40 most important figures in Latin American philosophy since the year 1500! Gracia is also one of the leaders in the emerging field of the philosophy of race and ethnicity.
    [Show full text]
  • Ratio 15.4 Text
    Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 2002, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Ratio (new series) XV 4 December 2002 0034–0006 LIVED BODY vs GENDER: REFLECTIONS ON SOCIAL STRUCTURE AND SUBJECTIVITY Iris Marion Young Abstract Toril Moi has argued that recent deconstructive challenges to the concept of gender and to the viability of the sex/gender distinction have brought feminist and queer theory to a place of increasing theo- retical abstraction. She suggests that we should abandon the category of gender once and for all, because it is founded on a nature-culture distinction and it tends incorrigibly to essentialize women’s lives. Moi argues that feminist and queer theories should replace the concept of gender with a concept of the lived body derived from existential phenomenology. In this essay I take up and develop this suggestions, and argue that there are several advantages that a category of the lived body has over a category of gender for feminist and queer theo- ries: (1) no nature-culture distinction is necessary but the body can be described as historically and socially specific; (2) it is not necessary to break out a gendered and “raced” part of identity with this cate- gory; (3) differences of sexual desire can be described without recourse to an “inner core” of identity or “sexual orientation.” I go on to argue, however, that it is important to retain a concept of gender for a theoretical purpose beyond that which Moi and those she criticizes conceive. In recent years feminist and queer theories have tended to conceive their theorizing as restricted to identity and subjectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Liberal Multiculturalism Anke Schuster University of Groningen
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CommonKnowledge Essays in Philosophy Volume 7 Article 15 Issue 1 Liberalism, Feminism, Multiculturalism 1-2006 Does Liberalism Need Multiculturalism? A Critique of Liberal Multiculturalism Anke Schuster University of Groningen Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Schuster, Anke (2006) "Does Liberalism Need Multiculturalism? A Critique of Liberal Multiculturalism," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 7: Iss. 1, Article 15. Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific nivU ersity Library | ISSN 1526-0569 | http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/ Essays in Philosophy Essays in Philosophy A Biannual Journal Vol. 7, No. 1, January 2006 Does Liberalism Need Multiculturalism? A Critique of Liberal Multiculturalism Abstract: In this paper I will argue that liberal multiculturalism is neither a necessary nor a convincing extension of liberalism. In evaluating the two main strands of liberal multiculturalism, I will first analyse the approaches of Charles Taylor and Bhikhu Parekh as the main proponents of the version that focuses on the cultures themselves and raises the issue of the value of cultures in connection with public discourse. I will then turn to Amy Gutmann and Will Kymlicka as liberal multiculturalists who use the liberal norm of individual equality as a starting point. I will show that the arguments adduced in favour of liberal multiculturalism fail, due to the following shortcomings. Taylor’s approach is underspecified with respect to the relationship between the process of evaluating cultures and its outcome.
    [Show full text]
  • Equality of Whom? Social Groups and Judgments of Injustice
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 9, Number 1, 2001, pp. 1±18 Equality of Whom? Social Groupsand Judgmentsof Injustice* IRIS MARION YOUNG Political Science, University of Chicago ECENT philosophical debates about normative ideals of equality have Rfocused on questions of what we should be aiming at when we wish to make people more equal. Should normsof equality be conceived in termsof welfare, for example, which entails reference to subjective valuations, or should goals of equality be directed at objective resources? Are conceptsof the distribution of resources adequate for comparing objective well-being or do we need to conceptualize and compare what persons are capable of doing with these resources? Recent debates have shown that the apparently simple question of what we should compare when we make judgments of equality and inequality harbors a nest of conceptual and practical tensions. Contributors to the debate have greatly clari®ed these issues, if not solved them.1 Little attention has been paid to another side of this question, however, namely whom we are discussing when we compare people's situation with regard to any or all of these targets of equality. Theorists usually assume that the units we should be comparing when we make judgments of inequality are individuals. Many assessments of inequalities and claims for redress on grounds that an inequality isunjust, however, compare groups of individualsaccording to one or more measures of equality. People commonly claim that women lack equality with men, Blackswith whites,old people with younger people, children of working-class parents with children of middle-class parents, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics: a Study of Dietrich BonhoeEr's Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics
    Durham E-Theses The virtue of Bonhoeer's ethics: a study of Dietrich Bonhoeer's Ethics in relation to virtue ethics MOBERLY, JENNIFER,LYNNE How to cite: MOBERLY, JENNIFER,LYNNE (2009) The virtue of Bonhoeer's ethics: a study of Dietrich Bonhoeer's Ethics in relation to virtue ethics, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/89/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 The Virtue of Bonhoeffer’s Ethics A Study of Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics Jennifer Moberly Thesis submitted for PhD Durham University December 2009 Abstract Jennifer Moberly, „The Virtue of Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics: A Study of Dietrich Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics in Relation to Virtue Ethics‟ (thesis submitted for PhD, December 2009) This study first explores prima facie reasons for rejecting the possibility of seeing a close relationship between Bonhoeffer‟s Ethics and virtue ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics Content
    Ethics Content I Introduction to Ethics Unit-1 Nature and Scope of Ethics Unit-2 Importance and Challenges of Ethics Unit-3 Ethics in the History of Indian Philosophy Unit-4 Ethics in the History of Western Philosophy II Ethical Foundations Unit-1 Human Values Unit-2 Human Virtues Unit-3 Human Rights Unit-4 Human Duties III Applied Ethics Unit-1 International Ethics Unit-2 Bioethics Unit-3 Environmental Ethics Unit-4 Media Ethics IV Current Ethical Debates Unit-1 Natural Moral Law Unit-2 Deontology and Moral Responsibility Unit-3 Discourse Ethics Unit-4 Social Institutions UNIT 1 NATURE AND SCOPE OF ETHICS Nature and Scope of Ethics Contents 1.0 Objectives 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Moral Intuitionism 1.3 Human Person in Search of Himself/Herself 1.4 Love and the Moral Precepts 1.5 The Dynamics of Morality 1.6 The Constant and the Variable in Morality 1.7 Let Us Sum Up 1.8 Key Words 1.9 Further Readings and References 1.0 OBJECTIVES This unit aims at introducing the students to the philosophical need for Ethics starting from a brief discussion of Moral law and how the human person in his or her process of growth intuits the ethical principles. Discussions pertaining to the dynamics of morality is undertaken to show how on the one hand new situations call for new responses from moral point of view and on the other hand certain fundamentals of ethics remain the same in so far as there is something of a common human nature adequately understood.
    [Show full text]
  • Nicholas Southwood This Brief, Bold Monograph Addresses 'The Central
    Book Reviews 117 Nicholas Southwood Contractualism and the Foundations of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 208 pp. isbn 978-0-19-953965-9 (hbk). £40.00. This brief, bold monograph addresses ‘the central problem of moral philoso- phy: … identifying the … ultimate [constitutive] grounds of morality’ (pp. vii, 4, 9). Southwood espouses ‘the contractualist idea that the rightness and wrongness of our conduct is to be explained by reference to some … actual or hypothetical agreement … [This] offer[s] the best hope of vindicating a robust notion of moral truth while also acknowledging that morality is in some sense a human construction, that moral truths are somehow dependent on actual human capacities’ (p. vii). To show this, Southwood develops a novel ‘deliberative model’ of contractualism, distinct to Gauthier’s ‘Hobbesian’ and to Scanlon’s ‘Kantian’ contractualist models; its affinities to Habermas’ discourse ethics are omitted (pp. 3, 87n2). The ‘morality’ Southwood seeks to ground is a ‘complete set … of deontic facts … about what is permissible, impermissible, and obligatory,’ as a common code by which we are to live (p. 102n32), in contrast to what is ‘good, worth- while, [or] virtuous’ (p. 7) for us to do (p. 8). Adequately grounding morality requires vindicating ‘various platitudes that define morality’s intensional char- acter’ and ‘substantive judgments concerning morality’s extensional character’ (p. 11). Morality’s intensional character is specified by platitudes about its nor- mativity and its objectivity (p. 13). Morality’s normativity consists in agents having sufficient justifying reasons to act (or to refrain) as morality requires (p. 14); ‘moral requirements are necessarily categorical and binding’ and ‘dis- tinctively other-regarding’ (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Commanded Love and Moral Autonomy the Kierkegaard-Habermas Debate
    ___________________________________ ___________________________________ Commanded Love and Moral Autonomy The Kierkegaard-Habermas Debate Merold Westphal — Fordham University One way to read Kierkegaard’s Works of Love is to speculative knowledge). But his ethics is theo- as an all out assault on the Enlightenment ideal of nomous, and thus heteronomous, and he will moral autonomy from a religious point of view. vigorously reject the second and third constraints Kant is the locus classicus of this ideal, just as on the ethics of divine command he develops in Descartes and Locke are, respectively, for the Works of Love. correlative ideals of epistemic and political auton- The second constraint involves an elitism he is omy. Since these three components belong to the eager to repudiate. Kant recognizes that one central core of what we have come to think of as might need “the idea of another Being over him” the modern understanding of the subject, Kierke- in order to recognize one’s duty or be motivated gaard’s critique has a distinctively postmodern to do it, but “it is man’s own fault if he is subject flavour. But, as we shall see, it is postmodern to such a need ...”4 The idea seems to be this. If precisely by the way it is biblically premodern. we are sufficiently enlightened or intellectually The first thing Kant says about the relation of mature, we will have a morality that “does not religion to morality in his ‘Fourth Critique’ is need religion at all,” but if we are intellectually that “morality does not need religion at all.” inferior or immature, we will need to get our Because morality presupposes “man as a free morality by way of religion and the notion of agent who, just because he is free, binds himself divine commands.
    [Show full text]
  • Structural Injustice and the Politics of Difference1
    Iris Marion Young Structural Injustice and the Politics of Difference1 It has become a truism that a politics of difference is equivalent to “identity politics,” which is about claims of justice concerning cultural difference. In this essay I take issue with this set of equiv- alences. There are at least two versions of a politics of difference, which I call a politics of positional difference and a politics of cultural difference. They share a critical attitude toward a differ- ence-blind approach to politics and policy. They differ, however, in how they understand the constitution of social groups, and in the issues of justice that they emphasize. While both versions of a politics of difference appear in contemporary political debates, I perceive that over the last two decades both the attention of public discourse and that of political theorists has shifted from the politics of positional difference to a politics of cultural differ- ence. I argue that this shift is unfortunate because it tends to ob- scure important issues of justice and because it tends to limit the framing of difference politics to a liberal paradigm. We should af- firm both approaches, I argue, but also be clear on the conceptual and practical differences between them. As a social movement tendency in the 1980’s, the politics of dif- ference involved the claims of feminist, anti-racist, and gay libe- ration activists that the structural inequalities of gender, race, and sexuality did not fit well with the dominant paradigm of equality and inclusion. In this dominant paradigm, the promotion of ju- stice and equality requires non-discrimination: the application of the same principles of evaluation and distribution to all persons regardless of their particular social positions or backgrounds.
    [Show full text]
  • Jurgen Habermas: Discourse Ethics and the Development of a Contemporary Christian Ethic
    JUrgen Habermas: Discourse Ethics and the Development of a Contemporary Christian Ethic A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF MCMASTER DIVINITY COLLEGE IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE MASTER OF DIVINITY MCMASTER UNIVERSITY HAMIL TON, ONTARIO BY MICHAEL JOHN FORD APRIL 2003 MASTER OF DIVINITY MCMASTER UNIVERSITY Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Jiirgen Habermas: 'Discourse Ethics and the Development of a Contemporary Christian Ethic AUTHOR: Michael John Ford SUPERVISOR: Dr. Kurt A. Richardson NUMBER OF PAGES: 107 McMASTER DIVINITY COLLEGE Upon the recommendation of an oral examination committee and vote of the faculty, this thesis-project by MICHAEL JOHN FORD is hereby accepted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF DIVINITY External Reader Dean Date: April2l, 2003 Abstract The purpose of this thesis is to introduce the reader to the person and work of social philosopher and social theorist JUrgen Habermas. It introduces pertinent aspects of Habermas's biography, and surveys a portion of his library of writings. It then explains Habermas's communication theory, specifically his theory of communicative action. Then, Habermas's theory of discourse ethics is introduced and explicated. This thesis culminates with an examination of the appropriateness and applicability of Habermas's theory of discourse ethics for the development of a contemporary Christian ethic. 11 Acknowledgements The preparation of this thesis has been an edifying experience, and I would like to extend thanks to a number of people who made the experience what it has been. To my supervisor, Dr. Kurt Anders Richardson, thank you for valuable insights, edits, and observations.
    [Show full text]