Zeno and Stoic Consistency

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Zeno and Stoic Consistency Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1973 Zeno and Stoic Consistency John M. Rist University of Toronto, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Rist, John M., "Zeno and Stoic Consistency" (1973). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 446. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/446 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. 4 4 Ĕĝɼ ĨęĎɼ ġɼ ãĬ³j + ɭɼ 7ɼ o ɏåɼ ÞĖ ɼ ! 3%ɼ ɼ '»: #6ßèɼ ŅQ j"ɼ ĞǴ ɳɼ Ȯɼ °ɼ þɼ ƀAɼ -ɼ 2ɼ "(3$#/!Bɼ *ɼ !Iɼ ɼ ɼ 7ɼ ɼ MGĈ 2ǚ'ɼ Ơ ɼ {<ɼ Z ǛƵLɼ Íɼ ƕɼ ǜɼ Äɼ éɼ ɼ ċgS%ɼ ?êăɴüȯɹǵɢ {ɼ QƅCE&ɼ wIÔɼ OÛɼ Qɼ ė$ (·ɼ ɼ O ɼ 8 ɼ lj ɼ ÿĀHāĂýɼ ,ɼ 8ɼ ÕǶɼ !T FHɼ %ɼ $RÎɼ Ŏ0C Hëɼ Hɼ 2.8ɼ Uɼ ]ɼ ɼ 3NJ0¸34ɼ *ɼ 8´Vɼ Vkɼ 7ɼ Ȱŝɼ ¹ɼ "ɼ 7ɼ ɼ ¼ ɼ -qɼ ƖXɼ ɼ E Hɼ ɑlɼ ɼ 1 id2Vɼ &ɼ :"ɼ ĜAąmɼ ɼ ¾ɡ ɼ -ɼ / Uɼ VŹ ɼ 0 80ɼ )ɼ #Jɼ ɼ ɬɼ *ɼ Ē .<ɼ Ä]ɼ 5ņLº:ɼ G'ɼ Č; 0ȱɸȖɼ -ɼ oIJVɼ Ɨɼ NǕ_ɼ !I(ɼ ûƶ#ÒȲɼ @ǘg=ɼ 7ɼ !ɼ ŏɼ ppɼ ɼ ǝɼ yU= C^÷ɼ ğÑɼ ­ɼ !(ɼ řưƱžBF Lɼ d|ɼ +ɼ , ɼ $!Tɼ eɼ , qɼ , FA ȳɼ -ɼ ɼ ŇȴK@ɼ Ù Eɒɼ Ȃ"ɼ 21/S¿Qìɼ 5Śɼ ;ɼ ɣɶ ®}Ƿ;ɼ ^ɼ Ö ~hɼ ȗ©!ÓTÈɼ ǖÜɼ Å Ǟ Üɼ (`bÀɼ > Ɔɼ ɼ ȏijAɼ 3Ǹ;3 ¾'ɼ ;ɼ >ɼ ĮÆɼ ɼ Ȑ 65 íɼ ȃiɼ >+!Ƈɼ ɼ M,6%ɼ ɼ `ªÁ 5nɼ Ćɼ čZ3 'Aɼ ɼ M4 Ōɓh ȵ ɼ ȶSɼ &*4 ;ɼ ɼ ƘOɼ 7ɼ &+Aɼ ƙ,ɼ yɼ Õ¸ɼ ɼ ¡;.ɼ ƈÉÊ&ɼ .P )4 9A1"P oɼ ¢@ɼ Y/1&ɼ |%ɼ NjŞö 4y.ɼ >+× ɼ > Ő ɼ >şɼ $ɼ +-?ĉɼ ɨɼ ¦ɼ ȷɼ ÒŠɼ zȄ/#¿%ɼ ɼ Yɼ U<ɼ ɼ G3 +X.ɼ ½,8.ɼ øɼ Ĥ6ɼ ɼ ,Ĵȸ«ɼ ő=Bh ɼ Sɼ ɼ &P'"4 4 ƷXơe®ɼ X ɔ<Ƹɮîɼ Bǟ_ɼ Ǡ (ǡ4kɼ æɼ e"ɼ ƹ~X~`ɼ ÂGF CLɼ 6'0 $P ĭɼ $ɼ Ǣɐɼ Åƺ¦ɼ Kɼ %0« -&ɼ UN?ɼ ȹ (ªɼ ȔiYǣïɼ DƁɼ Ɖšɼ 1$b:ɼ ɩ(ɼ @ɼ -ɼ ɼ }=ɼ ɼ 2ɼ 4 ɼ MÖ¤<ɼ Ki'ɼ ɤrɼ @0Pɼ ÔIźɼ ɼ Ë%=_ɼ 4ɼ .ɼ ɼ ɼ 5&ɼ Øzɼ Ǥǹɼ "(uƢǥŢPɼ Ɗȅ1ƣfɼ äǦǺɼ HP 4J-*P #.$4 ¢ɼ 5O+8C#=P P 5ȡɼ ɼ ½Ƌɼ * Kɼ D*ɼ 9*ɼ L>;P KF P ɼ ď9Á mɼ &È0ðɼ ćɼ 2'ɼ ɼ E\ɼ N¥ţÌW)[ɼ Wacɼ "rvµbȺƤDJñ £ɕòɼ =Ûɼ ĥō)ɖlɼ &ɼ ZºƻŤ'ɼ xÊ/+;h%ɼ Rɼ óɼ R|9 ɼ [tǧBv&ƥJƂɼ ɼ 9ɼ K ɼ à26 jƦÂ`ɼ ƚ//³%áɼ Ýɼ /P !% 34 ĩɼ Ȏ<5wɼ F ƃ. ɼ 4z ɼ ťǨ ɼ Nǩ"ɼ бȘɯȢƧȆȇɗɼ +,- 4 4 /0124 ¡ɼ Jɼ įŦɼ ?4T_ "ɼ ňŧȻɪŨ)Ãɼ ƌũɼ ɘƼȼƨnjĵsɼ ĶÏ.)Ƚɼ ^ɼ Ⱦ±ɼ ǻƽɼ ]qmɼ "ɼ ɼ Pɼ WŪƾǼçùɼ Īȿɼ ɀƍcɼ ɰɼ ʼn)ɼ ɼ Ǎg ɼ ­ǽÎǎķCɼ <!Ż,ɼ -ɼ Ɂ ɼ É×Ǫɼ @ɼ İǫÇɼ ƎƩǏȣ¬ƿuɼ ǔ§¬ɼ bȤɼ ĸ9ȥǾɼ əƄ¯ūr[ɼ £kɼ ɂIŬɼ Z ɼ ]23 ɼ Ƀƛ ɼ >ɼ Ɯɥɼ ɼ ŭĹș9ɱɼ )ɦƪśŮǬŒtɼ ɄƏĺɼ Ʌaůɼ ĦɆǿ#œȦɼ ſ$$?ɼ ɼ MN@<B% P ɼ 'B+Ŕɼ *gÇǐɼ P 4 ɇaŰɼ ǭ¨úɼ ɻĻɼ )ɼ @Ǒɼ ɼ °ɧűɼ Qɼ pŕȚ+1 ȧɼ Ɛļȉ˶ǀâŲȨȩɼ 4P4 P( f¨ɼ ȑÏǁ(dɼ ɼ Ľ,ɼ 'F:ɼ 7ɼ T$ɚɼ ľǮ§ɼ cɈɼ Ð)ǂɺW¶ Jɼ ɼ RĿÌ1ƫǯųnɼ ĕEɼ ¼Eɼ żȊ GƬȪɼ ɼ /¤Hɼ ɼ Ù#ɛŴȕɼ ŀɼ 9ŵŁȫɉɼ ɊƑtɼ Dɜț6ɼ aôɼ ƒɼ ɼ Ɲ/ȋ}ɷ ɼ *nɼ ě ɼ Ú ɝ¹Ŝɼ Ŋ\ɼ vɼ ƭfȜsɼ ´*ɼ Ú)ɼ d[ɼ Ž1CB:ɼ ɼ »Gǃɲɼ ǰ'ɼ ɼ K²õɼ *ɼ &lɼ 1RƮDŽȀ1ƓcŖłDžɼ ¯f#u#6\ɼ #ɋɼ 8ȁɼ ē ɼ +ɼ Ajɼ Fɼ :Lɼ 6džɼ Ȭɼ ɼ ƳµDZPɼ *ɼ ǒDÐ9ɼ &ɌǓɼ 8 ɼ Ưŗɼ -7 ɼ ɞĊɼ ī ɼ Ńɼ Ŷ Dzɼ ŘÃSP)ȝŋC©ɼ #dzɍŷÑȭWɼ #Àɼ ɟ¥xɼ Ǘ ȞÓɼ ÍŸ4Lńɼ Ġ Eƞ0%ɼ Iɼ ^$=Ɏɼ sȌɼ ƔÆLJ?ɼ O ɼ !ɼ !ȟkɼ NJ?ɼ "Ƞeɼ >Ɵ,ɼ ıɼ ɫ<ɼ .( Ø{wɼ Yɼ :ɼ ² ɼ Ljƴɼ Oɠ ɼ 2)3:P Ęȍ0%ɼ ɼ 5ɼ - 2 - smooth flow. Presumably the man who is happy is never taken aback, never has to recast his priorities. He is above all consistentf his intentions and motives can be viewed as forming a coherent whole . According to Stobaeus , 9 Zeno also defined the end ( telos ) as living consistently, by which he meant living according to a single harmonious pattern. The reason he gave was that people who live otherwise, not consistently , but in conflict ( f-Jxor(vi,.J'-> ) , are unhappy ( to1.l:'.o- �q.1ovo�v1'\.)\I ) • This looks like an empirical appeal. If you are incon- sistent, you are unhappy - as anyone who looks can see. It is an lo empirical test of the kind of life which will bring happiness. Perhaps such empirical methods help the Stoics avoid giving the impres­ sion of founding their ethics on an unjustifiable shift from statements of fact to statements of value. A conflicting character brings unhap­ piness, as you can see! If you want to avoid unhappiness , the argument runs, make your behaviour consistent. There is no suggestion that you must do so, or that you ought to do so. If you want to be unhappy, then the Stoic will not attempt to change your belief. What he contents himself with doing is showing that, if you are inconsistent, you really will be unhappy . There is no absolute decree, you ought to behave consistently, virtuously, etc. Rather there is the proposition that whoever is happy will, as a matter of fact, be consistent, virtuous, etc. But to say with the Stoic that virtue entails happiness is not to say that the only reason - or indeed a necessary reason - for being virtuous is because it entails happiness. It seems that both happiness and virtue may in some sense be sought for their own sake. In fact it seems that the Stoics were prepared to say two things : 1) It will in fact pay to be virtuous provided that you want to be happy; and 2) the good man will seek virtue for its own sake. Some of the apparent difficulties ::'. \). reconciling these propositions may be resolved by examining the notion of seeking virtue for its own sake. What then do the Stoics say that virtue is? We are not short of definitions, although no definition is associated with Zeno alone. Normally virtue appears either as a "con­ sistent disposition"ll or more generally as some kind of condition of 1 the ruling part of the soul ( �y�pov1Kbv ) 2. No one would dispute that the consistency in question, whether or not it was always consis­ tency with " nature " in the sense of external nature, is consistency within oneself. Plutarch attributes to the Stoics generally an account of virtue both as a disposition and power produced by reason, and as 13 a consistent and steadfast reason itself6 and Cleanthes, in a poemp gives 01-l:>..\cy.o�\-HVt>v as one of a list Of predicates Of "the good" - l4 which would certainly include the notion of the good for mano At !Ş Ş Ş Ş MŞ Ş Ş N Ş ;Ş K Ş #Ş " Ş VŞ 4ņĞ5Ş %0òŞ Ľ Ş Ş ) Ş T? Ş kŞ Hê 2%[Ş %,,ľ¡Ş Ş ) $ Ş # Ş Ş M Ş U QŞ .Ş 5Ş ] Ŗ rÍŞ !· ä!Ş V+Ş W17Ş |Ş Ş 3 :Ş Ş Ş Ş ¢Ş !B+Ş Ş Ş kYŞ Ş ó&Ş £Ş Ş Ş ' Ş -Ş 8¤Ş Ş fŞ IJZě}Ş XP@EŞ Ş Ş Ļ'CŞ K#Ş Ş Ş $ Ş \Ş Ü !Ş 0 ŗ AîEŞ $Ş %_Ş 'Ş Ş 6 Ş " iŞ Ş OŞ CŞ /Ş L) {Ş 5Ş aŘ BĦzŞ =Ş Œ-BŞ ~G¸Ş ÚŊ y&Ş VŞ %b!Ş I Ş Ş Ş Ş BŞ ħ$8¥Ş "Ş Ş D Ş Ş Ş Ě&Ş Ş 'eZC5Ş 3",Ş #Ş A.Ş Ş %Ĩ-%.¹Ş vŞ UŞ Ş Ý(Ş I&Ş J Ş "Ş 0Ş ,.Ş %Ş Ş -Ş ô¦Ş $Ş Ş )Ş ( Ş Ş ĜŞ #Ş 1Ş Ş 0Ş dař 04û 5ºŞ ] i@5Ş ( Ş *NŞ Ş Ş O&Ş 6 Ş 7 Ş )} §Ş y% Ş -Ş "|Ş Ş X8Ş 3Ş 8»Ş ZŞ đ3Ş Ş Ş RmŞ .$) ĒŞ Ş Ş Ş Ş TŞ Ş Ş q Ş -BŞ IŞ ĩ Ş [% 4BŞ Ş VŞ ŋ ^EŞ ,Ş J Ş /# Ş w0Ş "Ş Ş P Ş Ş `Ş ĿŞ Ş OŞ ŕŞ ?:Ş Ş Ş 7 ĮŞ "Ş %7Ş =!mŞ 4!Ş Ş $ Ş [Ş Ş q Ş Ş (OŞ Ş (X)½Ş àŞ "Ş 2Ş Ş ķ ąŞ Ş Ş ï'~Ş ē9ĸŞ Ş (' 4Ş !Ś Ĕ9Ş Ş ŀfŞ ; ¾Ş tĪ(FŞ /Ş D _Ş D\Ş ×Ş Ş <Ş Ă2Ş {Ş =Ş Ş IŞ " Ş Ş :; Ō$9Ş /Ş Ş Xĕ ğŞ Ş õŞ 4Ş @)¨Ş Ş U©Ş Ş SŞ <#Ş ªŞ ĐŞ CŞ )ś 3eŞ !Ş =Ş Ş R1 &¿Ş ÔŞ lY(&Ş Ş Ş 3Ş ăŞ ë2åohĹŞ " Ė Ş NŞ ^:Ş WŞ (@&Ş \Ş rÎŞ u4Ş %Ş ĆŞ ^ ĝŞ -Ş Ş ,Ş 3Ş Þ-ì 9Ş Ő Ş T K ;Ş UŞ , AÀŞ Ò#ŁŞ R#&bŞ 6Ş &Ş 0Ş JŞ «Ş H QŞ Ş Ş Ş !Ş H $ 0Ş Q Ş ; Ş ĉ<Ş pð<Ş cŝŞ ) GŞ @,Ş S =hndE¬Ş <<,Ş īkR&­Ş *Ş ėōc6Ş &ÁŞ ãŞ Ĭ= Ş C CŞ FŞ /Ş Ş öY4 EŞ Ş "Ş +88ÂŞ ÕŞ TŞ Ş őŞ Ş 0 Ş ł;$QŞ z P4Ş Ş $6Ş /ÑŞ H>*Ş Ş DŞ "<Ş )Ş QÃ9ÄŞ Ö$,AŞ u nŞ æŞ J>Ş 7+Ş 'Ş Ş 66ÊŞ @FŞ "/ Ş sÏŞ A-Ş #Ş ) Ù+''Ş 1'Ş Ş 1i9Å Ó( .ĘŞ Ş Û x !®Ş ] &LŞ )8+.Ş Ş j+Ġ*K'KŞ į7"?IŞ ##`ġ5¯Ş %,Ş !cŞ #79 Ş .Ş DŞ 17FŞ *Ş 3 +MŞ (ÆŞ â1 Ş Ş =?üŞ !ýŞ pç(+ËÌŞ İŞ èg_Ş *gŞ ŇWĢFŞ !#ı2Ş Ŏęĺ-Ş /Ş Ş ňl M >Ş Ş *ļÇŞ á 1'Ş `Ş Ş 'WŞ Ş Ş Ş 2 ?$ Ş Ş O3Ş !") Ş ijLYŞ Ş Ş Ş v Ş .
Recommended publications
  • The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Antoninus
    The meditations of Marcus Aurelius Antoninus Originally translated by Meric Casaubon About this edition Marcus Aurelius Antoninus Augustus was Emperor of Rome from 161 to his death, the last of the “Five Good Emperors.” He was nephew, son-in-law, and adoptive son of Antonius Pius. Marcus Aurelius was one of the most important Stoic philosophers, cited by H.P. Blavatsky amongst famous classic sages and writers such as Plato, Eu- ripides, Socrates, Aristophanes, Pindar, Plutarch, Isocrates, Diodorus, Cicero, and Epictetus.1 This edition was originally translated out of the Greek by Meric Casaubon in 1634 as “The Golden Book of Marcus Aurelius,” with an Introduction by W.H.D. Rouse. It was subsequently edited by Ernest Rhys. London: J.M. Dent & Co; New York: E.P. Dutton & Co, 1906; Everyman’s Library. 1 Cf. Blavatsky Collected Writings, (THE ORIGIN OF THE MYSTERIES) XIV p. 257 Marcus Aurelius' Meditations - tr. Casaubon v. 8.16, uploaded to www.philaletheians.co.uk, 14 July 2013 Page 1 of 128 LIVING THE LIFE SERIES MEDITATIONS OF MARCUS AURELIUS Chief English translations of Marcus Aurelius Meric Casaubon, 1634; Jeremy Collier, 1701; James Thomson, 1747; R. Graves, 1792; H. McCormac, 1844; George Long, 1862; G.H. Rendall, 1898; and J. Jackson, 1906. Renan’s “Marc-Aurèle” — in his “History of the Origins of Christianity,” which ap- peared in 1882 — is the most vital and original book to be had relating to the time of Marcus Aurelius. Pater’s “Marius the Epicurean” forms another outside commentary, which is of service in the imaginative attempt to create again the period.2 Contents Introduction 3 THE FIRST BOOK 12 THE SECOND BOOK 19 THE THIRD BOOK 23 THE FOURTH BOOK 29 THE FIFTH BOOK 38 THE SIXTH BOOK 47 THE SEVENTH BOOK 57 THE EIGHTH BOOK 67 THE NINTH BOOK 77 THE TENTH BOOK 86 THE ELEVENTH BOOK 96 THE TWELFTH BOOK 104 Appendix 110 Notes 122 Glossary 123 A parting thought 128 2 [Brought forward from p.
    [Show full text]
  • Humanism and Neo-Stoicism." War and Peace in the Western Political Imagination: from Classical Antiquity to the Age of Reason
    Manning, Roger B. "Humanism and Neo-Stoicism." War and Peace in the Western Political Imagination: From Classical Antiquity to the Age of Reason. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2016. 181–214. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 26 Sep. 2021. <http:// dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781474258739.ch-004>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 26 September 2021, 04:18 UTC. Copyright © Roger B. Manning 2016. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 4 H u m a n i s m a n d N e o - S t o i c i s m No state . can support itself without an army. Niccolò Macchiavelli, Th e Art of War , trans. Ellis Farneworth (Indianapolis, IN : Bobbs-Merrill, 1965; rpr. New York: Da Capo, 1990), bk. 1, p. 30 Rash princes, until such times as they have been well beaten in the wars, will always have little regard for peace. Antonio Guevara, Bishop of Guadix, Th e Diall of Princes , trans. Th omas North (London: John Waylande, 1557; rpr. Amsterdam: Th eatrum Orbis Terrarum, 1968), fo. 174v Th e Humanist response to the perpetual problems of war and peace divided into the polarities of a martial ethos and an irenic or peace- loving culture. Th ese opposing cultures were linked to an obsession with fame or reputation, honor, and the military legacy of ancient Greece and Rome on the one hand, and on the other, a concern with human dignity, freedom, and a stricter application of Christian morality.
    [Show full text]
  • No One Errs Willingly: the Meaning of Socratic Intellectualism
    Created on 21 September 2000 at 13.38 hours page 1 NO ONE ERRS WILLINGLY: THE MEANING OF SOCRATIC INTELLECTUALISM HEDA SEGVIC κν κν µαρτον, ο κ ρνσοµαι. (Willingly, willingly I erred;I won’t deny it.) [Aeschylus], Prometheus Bound, 266 Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor. (I see what is better and approve of it, but pursue what is worse.) Ovid, Metamorphoses,7.20 Concepts, just like individuals, have their history and are no more able than they to resist the dominion of time, but in and through it all they nevertheless harbour a kind of homesickness for the place of their birth. Sren Kierkegaard, The Concept of Irony, 13. 106 I The Western philosophical tradition is deeply indebted to the fig- ure of Socrates. The question ‘How should one live?’ has rightly been called ‘the Socratic question’. Socrates’ method of cross- examining his interlocutors has often been seen as a paradigmatic form of philosophical enquiry,and his own life as an epitome of the philosophical life. What philosophers and non-philosophers alike have often found disappointing in Socrates is his intellectualism. A prominent complaint about Socratic intellectualism has been mem- orably recorded by Alexander Nehamas: ‘And George Grote both expressed the consensus of the ages and set the stage for modern ã Heda Segvic 2000 I am grateful to Myles Burnyeat, David Furley, John McDowell, and Julius Morav- csik for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. I also wish to thank the editor of Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy for his generous criticisms and corrections. Created on 21 September 2000 at 13.38 hours page 2 2 Heda Segvic attitudes toward Socrates when he attributed to him “the error .
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Intellectualism in Aristotle David Keyt University of Washington, [email protected]
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1978 Intellectualism in Aristotle David Keyt University of Washington, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Keyt, David, "Intellectualism in Aristotle" (1978). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 87. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/87 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. INTELLECTUALISM IN ARISTOTLE David Keyt University of Washington 1978 I When Aristotle returns to the topic of happiness at the end of the Nicoma­ chean Ethics (X.6-8) presumably to give us his final and best thoughts on the matter, he says that perfect happiness (he. teleia eudaimonia) is theoretical activity (the�retik� energeia), that happiness and contemplation (theoria) are coextensive, and that the life of reason (ho kata ton � bios), also called 1 the philosophic or theoretical life (I.5.1095bl9, �.E. I . 4. 1215bl-2, �passim), is the happiest life (X. 7.1177al2-18, 1178a4-8, 8.ll 78b7-32). He goes on to say that the life in accordance with the other excellence (ho kata tl!'n allen areten bios)--namely, the life in accordance with practical wisdom and moral virtue, elsewhere called the political or practical life (I.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparison of Focus and Audience Between Seneca's Natural
    East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Electronic Theses and Dissertations Student Works 5-2014 Comparison of Focus and Audience Between Seneca’s Natural Questions and Pliny’s Natural History Joshua Ely East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/etd Part of the European History Commons, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the Oral History Commons Recommended Citation Ely, Joshua, "Comparison of Focus and Audience Between Seneca’s Natural Questions and Pliny’s Natural History" (2014). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 2368. https://dc.etsu.edu/etd/2368 This Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Comparison of Focus and Audience Between Seneca’s Natural Questions and Pliny’s Natural History _____________________________ A thesis presented to the faculty of the Department of History East Tennessee State University _____________________________ In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in History _____________________________ by Joshua J. Ely May 2014 _____________________________ Dr. William D. Burgess Jr, Chair. Dr. Brian Maxson Dr. John Rankin Keywords: History of Antiquity, History of Science, Rome, Pliny, Seneca, Natural History, Natural Questions ABSTRACT Comparison of Focus and Audience Between Seneca’s Natural Questions and Pliny’s Natural History by Joshua Ely Around 65 AD, the Ancient Roman philosopher Seneca wrote his only text concerning Natural Phenomenon: Natural Questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De Otio and De Brevitate Vitae Joshua Dean Wimmer [email protected]
    Marshall University Marshall Digital Scholar Theses, Dissertations and Capstones 1-1-2012 Lend Me Your Voice: Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De otio and De brevitate vitae Joshua Dean Wimmer [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://mds.marshall.edu/etd Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons Recommended Citation Wimmer, Joshua Dean, "Lend Me Your Voice: Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De otio and De brevitate vitae" (2012). Theses, Dissertations and Capstones. Paper 255. This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Marshall Digital Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses, Dissertations and Capstones by an authorized administrator of Marshall Digital Scholar. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LEND ME YOUR VOICE: DISCOVERING ROMANITY IN SENECA’S DE OTIO AND DE BREVITATE VITAE A Thesis submitted to the Graduate College of Marshall University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Latin by Joshua Dean Wimmer Approved by Dr. E. Del Chrol, Committee Chairperson Dr. Caroline Perkins Dr. Christina Franzen Marshall University May 2012 Copyright by Joshua Dean Wimmer 2012 ii Dedication and Acknowledgments DEDICATION Pro parentibus meis ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would sincerely like to extend my most deeply felt gratitude to Dr. E. Del Chrol, Dr. Caroline Perkins, and Dr. Christina Franzen of the Department of Classics at Marshall University, as well as to any and to all who have helped in some way, no
    [Show full text]
  • The Fragments of Zeno and Cleanthes, but Having an Important
    ,1(70 THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES. ftonton: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. ambriDse: DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO. ltip&amp;gt;ifl: F. A. BROCKHAUS. #tto Hork: MACMILLAX AND CO. THE FRAGMENTS OF ZENO AND CLEANTHES WITH INTRODUCTION AND EXPLANATORY NOTES. AX ESSAY WHICH OBTAINED THE HARE PRIZE IX THE YEAR 1889. BY A. C. PEARSON, M.A. LATE SCHOLAR OF CHRIST S COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. LONDON: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE. 1891 [All Rights reserved.] Cambridge : PBIXTKIi BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS, AT THK UNIVERSITY PRKSS. PREFACE. S dissertation is published in accordance with thr conditions attached to the Hare Prize, and appears nearly in its original form. For many reasons, however, I should have desired to subject the work to a more under the searching revision than has been practicable circumstances. Indeed, error is especially difficult t&amp;lt;&amp;gt; avoid in dealing with a large body of scattered authorities, a the majority of which can only be consulted in public- library. to be for The obligations, which require acknowledged of Zeno and the present collection of the fragments former are Cleanthes, are both special and general. The Philo- soon disposed of. In the Neue Jahrbticher fur Wellmann an lofjie for 1878, p. 435 foil., published article on Zeno of Citium, which was the first serious of Zeno from that attempt to discriminate the teaching of Wellmann were of the Stoa in general. The omissions of the supplied and the first complete collection fragments of Cleanthes was made by Wachsmuth in two Gottingen I programs published in 187-i LS75 (Commentationes s et II de Zenone Citiensi et Cleaitt/ie Assio).
    [Show full text]
  • Epictetus, Stoicism, and Slavery
    Epictetus, Stoicism, and Slavery Defense Date: March 29, 2011 By: Angela Marie Funk Classics Department Advisor: Dr. Peter Hunt (Classics) Committee: Dr. Jacqueline Elliott (Classics) and Dr. Claudia Mills (Philosophy) Funk 1 Abstract: Epictetus was an ex-slave and a leading Stoic philosopher in the Roman Empire during the second-century. His devoted student, Arrian, recorded Epictetus’ lectures and conversations in eight books titled Discourses, of which only four are extant. As an ex- slave and teacher, one expects to see him deal with the topic of slavery and freedom in great detail. However, few scholars have researched the relationship of Epictetus’ personal life and his views on slavery. In order to understand Epictetus’ perspective, it is essential to understand the political culture of his day and the social views on slavery. During his early years, Epictetus lived in Rome and was Epaphroditus’ slave. Epaphroditus was an abusive master, who served Nero as an administrative secretary. Around the same period, Seneca was a tutor and advisor to Nero. He was a Stoic philosopher, who counseled Nero on political issues and advocated the practice of clemency. In the mid to late first-century, Seneca spoke for a fair and kind treatment of slaves. He held a powerful position not only as an advisor to Nero, but also as a senator. While he promoted the humane treatment of slaves, he did not actively work to abolish slavery. Epaphroditus and Seneca both had profound influences in the way Epictetus viewed slaves and ex-slaves, relationships of former slaves and masters, and the meaning of freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study on Dikaiosune and Eudaimonia in Plato's Republic
    A STUDY ON DIKAIOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY EYLÜL ŞENTUNA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF SCIENCE IN THE DEPARTMENT PHILOSOPHY FEBRUARY 2012 i Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences _____________________ Prof. Dr. Meliha Altunışık Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosophy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosopy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assoc. Prof. Ertuğrul R. TURAN (AU,PHIL) _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İNAM (METU,PHIL) ______________________ Assist. Prof. Elif ÇIRAKMAN (METU,PHIL) ______________________ ii I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Eylül Şentuna Signature : iii ABSTRACT A STUDY ON DIKAOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC Şentuna, Eylül M.S., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam February 2012, 74 pages The aim of this study is to analyze the concept of dikaiosunê in Plato’s Republic with its main aspects.
    [Show full text]
  • A Selection from the Discourses of Epictetus with the Encheiridion, by Epictetus
    The Project Gutenberg EBook of A Selection from the Discourses of Epictetus With the Encheiridion, by Epictetus This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net Title: A Selection from the Discourses of Epictetus With the Encheiridion Author: Epictetus Release Date: January 9, 2004 [EBook #10661] Language: English *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK SELECTIONS FROM EPICTETUS *** Produced by Ted Garvin, David King, and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team A SELECTION FROM THE DISCOURSES OF EPICTETUS WITH THE ENCHEIRIDION TRANSLATED BY GEORGE LONG (Only George Long’s biographical sketch of Epictetus and the ENCHERIDION are included here for use in class. If you want to read The Discourses , go to http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/10661 Or just download the epub format (for use with iPad and other e-readers) from my site. Ukrit Patnoi) EPICTETUS. Very little is known of the life of Epictetus. It is said that he was a native of Hierapolis in Phrygia, a town between the Maeander and a branch of the Maeander named the Lycus. Hierapolis is mentioned in the epistle of Paul to the people of Colossae (Coloss. iv., 13); from which it has been concluded that there was a Christian church in Hierapolis in the time of the apostle. The date of the birth of Epictetus is unknown. The only recorded fact of his early life is that he was a slave in Rome, and his master was Epaphroditus, a profligate freedman of the Emperor Nero.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected]
    Digital Commons @ George Fox University George Fox Evangelical Seminary 2013 Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Church History Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Loren, "Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria" (2013). George Fox Evangelical Seminary. Paper 6. http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes/6 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in George Fox Evangelical Seminary by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. Kings College London Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria A Dissertation submitted to The School of Arts and Humanities In Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Theology and Religious Studies By Loren Kerns London, United Kingdom July 2013 Copyright by Loren Kerns, 2013 All rights reserved. Abstract Philo of Alexandria forged his theory of the soul and its passions while expositing the meaning of Torah. Though writing as a Jewish teacher and disciple of Moses, his biblical reflections display a strong orientation toward Middle-Platonic philosophy. On the topic of the soul and its passions, however, Philo also exhibits significant Stoic influence. The introduction notes Philo’s apparent incompatible use of both the complex Platonic and the monistic Stoic psychological models. After assessing the degree to which Philo understood 'passion' to be a type of Stoic impulse or opinion (chapter one), chapter two demonstrates that Philo consistently drew upon the Stoics’ depiction of all passions as irrational, excessive, and unnatural.
    [Show full text]