Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction Christoph Pieper and Bram vander Velden Introduction Caesar’sdeath: anew beginning of history? The Ides of March 44 bce marked adefinite break in Cicero’sperception of con- temporary history.After more thanfifteen years in which Caesar had considera- blydominatedRoman politics and five years after the outbreak of the Civil War had brought the Republicanconstitution to its near collapse,¹ the chance of a fresh start of Republican politics and of his owncareer seemed within his grasp. It was time to reconsider his public role and to enter the stageofpolitics again. At least,this is the story² he wanted to conveyinpublic alreadyinspring 44,when he was finalizing his De diuinatione. The prefaceofBook 2might be one of his first public utterances after Caesar’sdeath, if for amoment we disregard his lost amnesty speech, which he held on 17 March.³ Ciceroframes the preface as an end to his years of political inactivity,for which his frenzied philosophical output of the years 46–44 is defined as asubstitution.⁴ First,Cicerogives achro- nological and thematicoverviewofhis works so far,thus trying to canonize their reception as acoherent philosophical corpus (Diu.2.1– 4). In asecond step, he again defends his philosophical activities of the past and announces his return to active political life: Ac mihi quidem explicandae philosophiae causam attulit casus grauis ciuitatis,cum in armis ciuilibus nec tueri meo more rem publicam nec nihil agere poteram, nec quid potius, Cf. Cicero’sfirst published textafter the Civil War, the preface to his Brutus,esp. Brut. 4–6, where he famouslystagesakind of funeral oration for the lost Republican constitution by refer- ring to the mourningfor the state (lugere[…]rem publicam,4)and the forum which is deprived of its best public speakers, Hortensius and himself (forum populi Romani […]spoliatum atque orbatum,6). Cf. Dugan 2005,218–219and 234–237. Cf. Steel2005,140 about how Cicero wanted his Philippics to be seen: “It is temptingtosee these speechesasthe glorious culmination of Cicero’spublic career […]. This is an excellent story”.(emphasisours). On this speech in Cassius Dio’sversion, see La Bua in this volume and recentlyBurden- Strevens 2015,150 –156;onthe reception of the speech in earlymodern commentaries of the Philippics,see Pieper in this volume. Cf. Eph. Tull. s.v. De pace in senatu for further secondary literatureonthis speech. Butler 2002,110 –111 argues that Cicero might have worked on finalizing De diuinatione in the weeks immediatelyfollowingCaesar’sassassination. Cf. also the treatment of the prefaceby Baraz 2012,188–194,and Steel 2005,138: “it is possible that Cicero wanted to dramatise the breakingnews of Caesar’sdeath and his hopes that it would transform life at Rome”. OpenAccess. ©2020Christoph Pieper and Bram van der Velden, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https:// doi.org/10.1515/9783110716313-003 2 Christoph Pieper and Bramvan der Velden quod quidem me dignum esset,ageremreperiebam. Dabunt igitur mihi ueniam mei ciues, uel gratiam potius habebunt,quod, cum esset in unius potestate respublica,neque egome abdidi neque deserui neque adflixi neque ita gessi quasi homini auttemporibus iratus, neque porroita autadulatus autadmiratus fortunam sum alterius, ut me meae paeniteret. Id enim ipsum aPlatone philosophiaque didiceram, naturales esse quasdam conuersiones rerumpublicarum, ut eae tum aprincipibus tenerentur,tum apopulis,aliquando asingu- lis.Quod cum accidisset nostrae rei publicae, tum pristinis orbati muneribus haec studia renouare coepimus,utetanimus molestiis hac potissimum re leuaretur et prodessemus ciui- bus nostris qua re cumque possemus.Inlibris enim sententiam dicebamus, contionabamur, philosophiam nobis prorei publicae procuratione substitutam putabamus. Nunc quoniam de re publica consuli coepti sumus, tribuenda est operarei publicae,uel omnis potius in ea cogitatio et cura ponenda; tantum huic studio relinquendum, quantum uacabit apublico officio et munere.⁵ The cause of my becominganexpounder of philosophysprang from the grave condition of the Stateduringthe period of the Civil War, when, beingunable to protect the Republic, as had been my custom,and findingitimpossible to remain inactive,Icould find nothingelse that Ipreferred to do that was worthyofme. Thereforemycountrymen will pardon me— rather they will thank me—because, when the Statewas in the power of one man, Irefused to hide myself, to quit my place, or to be cast down; Idid not bear myself likeone enraged at the man or at the times; and, further,Ineither so fawned upon nor admired another’s fortune as to repentmeofmyown. Forone thinginparticular Ihad learned from Platoand from philosophy, that certain rev- olutions in government aretobeexpected; so that states arenow under amonarchy, now under ademocracy,and now under atyranny. When the last-named fatehad befallen my country,and Ihad been debarredfrommyformer activities,Ibegan to cultivateanew these present studies that by their means,rather than by anyother,Imight relievemymind of its worries and at the same time servemyfellow-countrymen as best Icould under the circum- stances. Accordingly,itwas in my books that Imade my senatorial speechesand my foren- sic harangues; for Ithought that Ihad permanentlyexchangedpolitics for philosophy. Now, however,sinceIhavebegun to be consulted again about public affairs,mytime must be devoted to the State, or,rather,myundivided thought and caremust be fixed upon it; and onlysomuch time can be giventophilosophyaswill not be needed in the discharge of my duty to the commonwealth. The passageclearlymarks the historical break with the sharp ‘then/now’-dichot- omy(attulit as perfect tense vs. nunc with present tense tribuenda est towardsthe end of the quotation). The period of the Civil War(in armis ciuilibus), which ac- cording to this passagelasted until Caesar’sdeath and thus until the end of his sole reign (in unius potestate res publica), has finally been replacedbyanew phase of publicengagement (publicum officium et munus)for Cicero. It is obvi- Cic. Diu. 2.6–7. Transl. Falconer 1923. Introduction 3 ouslyofanother quality than the time devoted to his previous philosophical studies. These, however,Ciceroframesbypolitical connotations as well:⁶ his fellow citizens are presented as the judgesofCicero’sphilosophicalengagement (da- bunt[…]ueniam mei ciues), which they should condone because it has been use- ful for them (prodessemus ciuibus nostris). So even if he expresses aturning point in his biographyaspolitician and philosopher in April 44,his former trea- tises are nonetheless described as an (albeit alternative)way of giving his polit- ical vote (sententiam dicebamus)and of speakinginfront of the assemblyofthe people (contionabamur)—in short: he “considered philosophyasasubstitute for administering the state” (pro rei publicae procuratione substitutam). The political changeinRome means no ontological changeofcharacter for Cicero, but one of gradation or better,ofintensification: the new political circumstances give rise to amoreimmediate political engagement,which relegates philosophytothe realms of dignified otium again.⁷ In the words of Jonathan Zarecki, philosophical works after Caesar’sdeath “provide insight into Cicero’sdecision to cast off the guise of retired elder statesman”.⁸ It is telling,however,that Ciceroprobablydid not write this prefaceinRome, the place whereaccordingtohis own conviction Roman politics should be con- ducted,⁹ but in one of his villas wherehehad been living most of the time since mid-April 44.The situation in Rome was not as glorious as the prefacetoDe diui- natione 2suggests. Caesar was dead, but manyRomans, instead of rejoicingand taking the chance to throw off the yoke of his dominatus,wantedhim backand gladlywelcomed Antony’sattempts to continue Caesar’spolitics.Caesarwas not onlypresent in everyone’smind, but in acertain waystill exercised his power.¹⁰ Cf. Butler 2002,110–111 on the political languageused in this passage. Cf. Baraz 2012,194:Cicero again is apolitical persona with philosophical interests,whereas beforeCaesar’sdeath, he has been aphilosophical persona with political interests (cf. ibid., 191). On Cicero’smanipulative use of otium in his rhetorical and philosophical works in the late50s,see Steel 2005,63–82. Fox2007, 231–232argues differently: accordingtohim, the multi- plicity of Ciceronian personae,which could be condensed in the philosophical works, is what reallyinterested Cicero. Zarecki 2014,136 (emphasis ours). Cf. Cicero’sfamous anecdote in Planc. 66 about the Romans not takingnoticeofhis Sicilian quaestorship,which he concludeswith the remark feci ut postea cotidie praesentem me uiderent, habitaui in oculis,pressi forum (“Isaw to it that afterwardsthey sawmepersonallyonadaily basis;Ilived in front of their eyes, Iwas glued to the forum.”); cf. also Q. Cicero (?), Comment. pet.2(the invitation to repeat as amantra: nouus sum, consulatum peto,Roma est). The letters to Atticus from 7and 8April (Att. 14.1 and 2) show the fixation of parts of the Roman upper class on Caesar,who, although dead, still serves as akind of political legitimation. 4 Christoph Pieper and Bramvan der Velden It seemed to Cicerothat while the Romans had killed adictator,the tyranny(ex- ercised by Antony in tandem with the decrees of the deceased Caesar)was still powerfullypresent.¹¹ This led to ahugerestlessness on Cicero’spart,who not onlyseems to have changed his locationalmostdaily(Att.
Recommended publications
  • Ennius Or Cicero? the Disreputable Diviners at Cic
    ACTA CLASSICAXLIV(200/) 153-166 ISSN 0065-1141 ENNIUS OR CICERO? THE DISREPUTABLE DIVINERS AT CIC. DE DIV. 1.132 A.T. Nice University of the Witwatersrand ABSTRACT At the end of the first book of Cicero's De Divir1atior1e, Quintus remarks that, even though he believes in divination, there are some diviners whom he would not trust to give accurate predictions. These comments are followed by a quotation from Ennius' Telamo. Most modem scholars have assumed, therefore, that the previous lines also contain an echo, if not a paraphrase of Ennius' work. This supposition does not seem to be supported by the language or style employed by Cicero. The lines should rather be understood as embodying the parochial view that elite Romans had towards forms of divination that were foreign, rustic or mercenary and not practised by the Roman state. I At the end of the first book of De Divinatione ( 1.132), Quintus completes his argument in favour of divination by denying the respectability of certain kinds ofdiviners: Nunc illa testabor, non me sortilegos neque eos, qui quaestus causa hariolentur, ne psychomantia quidem, quibus Appius, amicus tuus, uti solebat, agnoscere; non habeo denique nauci Marsum augurem, non vicanos haruspices, non de circo astrologos, non Isiacos coniectores, non interpretes somniorum; non enim sunt ii aut scientia aut arte divini. 1 The lines that follow, '(sed)2 superstitiosi vates inpudentes harioli ... de his di vitiis sibi deducant drachmam, reddant cetera,' are normally attributed to Ennius. Some previous commentators considered that the Ennius quotation should begin earlier, specifically from 'non habeo denique nauci.' 3 In favour 1 I use here the Teubner edition of R.
    [Show full text]
  • 582 in Altman's Two Books on Plato, Plato the Teacher
    582 Book Reviews William H. F. Altman, (2016) The Revival of Platonism in Cicero’s Late Philosophy: Platonis aemulus and the invention of Cicero. Lanham, MD; London: Lexington Books. xxxii + 351 pp. $100.00. ISBN 9781498527118 (hbk). In Altman’s two books on Plato, Plato the Teacher (2012) and The Guardians in Action (2016), we find the traditional reading of Plato, i.e., the philosopher of ‘unchanging, eternal, and transcendent Ideas’ (p. xviii), combined with a rather unique interpretation of Plato as a pedagogue, whose main goal is not to instantiate the ideal state in reality but rather to spread an enlightened form of democracy through an ennobling education program of philosophy. Altman’s interpretation of Cicero as reader of Plato naturally progresses from these two books. Cicero is not the Academic Skeptic, as recent scholarship has argued, but rather an advocate for Platonic transcendence – and one no less relevant to our own historical moment than to the crisis for which Cicero’s philosophy was immediately intended: the fallen Republic. Central to Altman’s argument on Cicero is the main theme of his earlier work on Plato: the return to the cave. According to Altman, although Plato’s belief in transcendent Ideas of the world of intelligibility is genuine, the goal of Plato as philosophical pedagogue is not transcendence but rather a return to the chaotic world of becoming, in which politics take place. Cicero then, in his emulation and rivalry of Plato, is picking up where Plato left off. He is not merely indulging in Platonic transcendence but relying on his philosophical rhetoric at its most subtle level to win over an ideologically fraught and often incredulous Roman readership to political enlightenment and devotion to the Ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Steel, C. (2017) Re Publica Nihil Desperatius: Salvaging the State in Cicero’S Pre-Civil War Philosophical Works
    Steel, C. (2017) Re publica nihil desperatius: salvaging the state in Cicero’s pre-civil war philosophical works. In: Müller, G. M. and Zini, F. M. (eds.) Philosophie in Rom - Römische Philosophie? Kultur-, literatur- und philosophiegeschichtliche Perspektiven. Series: Beiträge zur Altertumskunde (358). De Gruyter, pp. 269-282. ISBN 9783110493108. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/153358/ Deposited on: 12 December 2017 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk Re publica nihil desperatius: salvaging the state in Cicero’s pre-civil war philosophical works CATHERINE STEEL When Cicero summarised his philosophical output in the second book of De divinatione (div. 2,1–4) written in 44 B.C., he treated all the prose treatises that he had written since his consulship (with the single puzzling exception of de legibus) as a single oeuvre. No distinction is drawn between ‘philo- sophy’ and ‘rhetoric’ or between works written before and after the water- shed of the Civil War and the period of Cicero’s active participation in that conflict. De re publica – which he describes as written when he held gubernacula rei publicae – is included in the list after the trio of De natura deorum, De divinatione itself and the prospective De fato; and, invoking the practice of Aristotle and Theophrastus, his oratorii libri, including De oratore alongside Orator and Brutus, are given at the end of the catalogue.
    [Show full text]
  • M. Tullii Ciceronis Laelius De Amicitia
    This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project to make the world’s books discoverable online. It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that’s often difficult to discover. Marks, notations and other marginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book’s long journey from the publisher to a library and finally to you. Usage guidelines Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we have taken steps to prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. We also ask that you: + Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for personal, non-commercial purposes. + Refrain from automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google’s system: If you are conducting research on machine translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero on the Philosophy of Religion
    CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by John Patrick Frederick Wynne January 2008 CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. John Patrick Frederick Wynne, Ph. D. Cornell University, 2008 Cicero wrote de Natura Deorum (dND), de Divinatione (Div.) and de Fato (Fat.) in succession and describes the latter two as continuations of the first. I argue that the three dialogues form a trilogy, in which Cicero as author indicates a stance on the material he presents (but that too little of the fragmentary Fat. remains to be useful for my purposes). There are much-debated attributions of preferences to Cicero’s propriae personae at the conclusions of dND and Div.; I take these preferences to express Cicero’s authorial stance. I examine relevant parts of the speeches to which they react and, first, make philosophical interpretations of each (often comparing other sources for Hellenistic thought) and, second, pay attention to the interaction of Cicero’s characterization of each speaker with the arguments the speaker gives. I find that Balbus in dND advocates the avoidance of superstition and the reform of religious beliefs in line with Stoic physics and that Cotta has a strong commitment to traditional Roman religious views consistent with his sceptical epistemology. Cotta’s scepticism is elusive in its details but perhaps yields a kind of fideism. I find that Quintus Cicero’s advocacy in Div.
    [Show full text]
  • Fate, Chance, and Fortune in Ancient Thought
    FATE, CHANCE, AND FORTUNE IN ANCIENT THOUGHT LEXIS ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Adolf Hakkert Publishing - Amsterdam Carlos Lévy and Stefano Maso editors 1. Antiaristotelismo, a cura di C. Natali e S. Maso, 1999 2. Plato Physicus, Cosmologia e antropologia nel ‘Timeo’, a cura di C. Natali e S. Maso, 2003 (out of print) 3. Alessandro di Afrodisia, Commentario al ‘De caelo’ di Aristotele, Frammenti del primo libro, a cura di A. Rescigno, 2005 (out of print) 4. La catena delle cause. Determinismo e antideterminismo nel pensiero antico e con- temporaneo, a cura di C. Natali e S. Maso, 2005 5. Cicerone ‘De fato’, Seminario Internazionale, Venezia 10-12 Luglio 2006, a cura di S. Maso, ex “Lexis” 25/2007, pp. 1-162 6. Alessandro di Afrodisia, Commentario al ‘De caelo’ di Aristotele, Frammenti del secon- do, terzo e quarto libro, a cura di A. Rescigno, 2008 7. Studi sulle Categorie di Aristotele, a cura di M. Bonelli e F.G. Masi, 2011 8. Ch. Vassallo, Filosofia e ‘sonosfera’ nei libri II e III della Repubblica di Platone, 2011 9. Fate, Chance, and Fortune in Ancient Thought, F.G. Masi - S. Maso (eds.), 2013 LEXIS ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY (ed. minor) Libreria Cafoscarina Editrice s.r.l. - Venezia Carlos Lévy and Stefano Maso editors 1. Plato Physicus, Cosmologia e antropologia nel ‘Timeo’, a cura di C. Natali e S. Maso, 2011 2. Cicerone ‘De fato’, Seminario Internazionale, Venezia 10-12 Luglio 2006, a cura di S. Maso, 2012 LEXIS ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Adolf Hakkert Publishing - Amsterdam Carlos Lévy and Stefano Maso editors IX ADOLF M. HAKKERT – PUBLISHING Amsterdam 2013 Volume pubblicato con il parziale contributo PRIN 2009 responsabile prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Natali, Determinism Tr. 30.3.2020
    1 C. Natali Determinism and deliberation in Alexander of Aphrodisias [traduzione rivista 31.3.2020] I In this paper I defend a minority position in contemporary scholarship on Alexander of Aphrodisias with regard to the theme of determinism and his theory of what is up to us. Many modern scholars agree about the following basic points. The first point is that Aristotle did not develop a specific stance on the problem of determinism, given the fact that at the time this problem was not considered a central theme in the philosophical debate. Second, Alexander’s position on indeterminism was influenced by the debate in the imperial period rather than that he offers an exact account as to what Aristotle had maintained. In the third place, indeterminism is a slightly embarrassing position to hold; therefore, it is better to liberate the ancient philosophers from it, in so far as possible. What is more, a strong tendency can be discerned to attribute some form of compatibilism to most of the ancient philosophical schools – which cannot be easily reconciled with the polemics that existed between the schools. As for me, I think that already in Plato’s Academy philosophers began to reflect on the problem of determinism, freedom and human responsibility, starting out from certain statements in Plato’s Republic and in book 10 of the Laws.1 As far as Alexander is concerned, I think that his position can be characterised as a kind of ‘creative orthodoxy’, which consists in trying to show the vitality of the Aristotelian view point in the debate in imperial times.
    [Show full text]
  • Heeaclitus of Ephesus
    THE FRAGMENTS OP THE WOKK OF HEEACLITUS OF EPHESUS ON NATURE TRANSLATED FROM THE GREEK TEXT OF BYWATER, WITH AN INTRODUCTION HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL G. T. W. PATRICK, PH.D. PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE STATE UNIVERSITY OF IOWA BALTIMOKE N. MURKAY 1889 5 JUG FB P3 [Reprinted from the AMEKICAN JOUKNAL OF PSYCHOLOGY, 1888.] A THESIS ACCEPTED FOR THE DEGREE OP DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY, 1888. OF ISAAC FRIEDENWALD, BALTIMORE. I. All thoughts, all creeds, all dreams are true, All visions wild and strange ; Man is the measure of all truth Unto himself. All truth is change, All men do walk in sleep, and all Have faith in that they dream : For all things are as they seem to all, And all things flow like a stream. II. There is no rest, no calm, 110 pause, Nor good nor ill, nor light nor shade, Nor essence nor eternal laws : For nothing is, but all is made. But if I dream that all these are, for that I dream They are to me ; For all things are as they seem to all, And all things flow like a stream. Argal this very opinion is only true relatively to the flowing philosophers. TENNYSON. PREFACE. The latest writers on Heraclitus, namely, Gustav Teichmiiller and Edmund Pfleiderer, have thought it necessary to preface their works with an apology for adding other monographs to the Heraclitic literature, already enriched by treatises from such distinguished men as Schleiermacher, Lassalle, Zeller, and Schuster. That still other study of Heraclitus, however, needs no apology, will be admitted when it is seen that these scholarly critics, instead of determining the place of Heraclitus in the history of philosophy, have so far disagreed, that while Schuster makes him out to be a sensationalist and empiricist, Lassalle finds that he is a rationalist and idealist.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero's Style
    MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page i CICERO’S STYLE MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page ii MNEMOSYNE BIBLIOTHECA CLASSICA BATAVA COLLEGERUNT H. PINKSTER • H. S. VERSNEL D.M. SCHENKEVELD • P. H. SCHRIJVERS S.R. SLINGS BIBLIOTHECAE FASCICULOS EDENDOS CURAVIT H. PINKSTER, KLASSIEK SEMINARIUM, OUDE TURFMARKT 129, AMSTERDAM SUPPLEMENTUM DUCENTESIMUM QUADRAGESIMUM QUINTUM MICHAEL VON ALBRECHT CICERO’S STYLE MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page iii CICERO’S STYLE A SYNOPSIS FOLLOWED BY SELECTED ANALYTIC STUDIES BY MICHAEL VON ALBRECHT BRILL LEIDEN • BOSTON 2003 MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page iv This book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Albrecht, Michael von. Cicero’s Style: a synopsis / by Michael von Albrecht. p. cm. – (Mnemosyne, bibliotheca classica Batava. Supplementum ; 245) Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 90-04-12961-8 1. Cicero, Marcus Tullius–Literary style. 2. Speeches, addresses, etc., Latin–History and criticism. 3. Latin language–Style. 4. Rhetoric, Ancient. 5. Oratory, Ancient. I. Title. II. Series. PA6357.A54 2003 875’.01–dc21 2003045375 ISSN 0169-8958 ISBN 90 04 12961 8 © Copyright 2003 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910 Danvers, MA 01923, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idle Argument in Cicero's De Fato
    SMITH “IDLE ARGUMENT IN CICERO’S DE FATO” The Idle Argument in Cicero’s De Fato Kevin Smith Indiana University Purdue University Fort Wayne Abstract Throughout the course of this paper I examine Cicero’s analysis of the Idle Argument for fatalism and the two possible refutations of the argument that he mentions in his work entitled De Fato. Between the two refutations, one of which was originally given by the Stoic Chrysippus and the other by the Academic Skeptic Carneades, Cicero clearly expresses preference for the one given by Carneades. Cicero claims to prefer Carneades’s refutation for two reasons: because it is simpler than Chrysippus’s refutation and because it allows for praise and blame to be justly applied while Chrysippus’s refutation does not. I argue that this was a mistake, due to the fact that both refutations are equally complicated and they both allow for praise and blame to be justly applied. Upon showing that both of Cicero’s reasons for preferring Carneades’s refutation were false, I conclude that Cicero had no good reason for preferring one refutation over the other and that he therefore made a mistake when he claimed that Carneades’s refutation was better than the one given by Chrysippus. Are we as human beings in control of our own lives, and if so to what extent? This is one of the most frequently asked questions in the history of Western philosophy, and many philosophers have tried to answer it from their own unique philosophical perspective. One of the most interesting treatments of this issue was written by the philosopher and statesman Marcus Tullius Cicero back in the first century BC.
    [Show full text]
  • The First Discovery of the Freewill Problem Author(S): Pamela Huby Source: Philosophy, Vol
    Royal Institute of Philosophy The First Discovery of the Freewill Problem Author(s): Pamela Huby Source: Philosophy, Vol. 42, No. 162 (Oct., 1967), pp. 353-362 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/3748497 Accessed: 06-06-2019 19:40 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/3748497?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Royal Institute of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy This content downloaded from 198.137.18.103 on Thu, 06 Jun 2019 19:40:59 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE FIRST DISCOVERY OF TE FREEWILL PROBLEM' PAMELA HUBY HISTORICALLY there have been two main freewill problems, the problem of freedom versus predestination, which is mainly theo- logical, and the problem of freedom versus determinism, which has exercised the minds of many of the great modern philosophers. The latter problem is seldom stated in full detail, for its elements are taken as so obvious that they do not need to be stated.
    [Show full text]
  • 582 in Altman's Two Books on Plato, Plato the Teacher
    582 Book Reviews William H. F. Altman, (2016) The Revival of Platonism in Cicero’s Late Philosophy: Platonis aemulus and the invention of Cicero. Lanham, MD; London: Lexington Books. xxxii + 351 pp. $100.00. ISBN 9781498527118 (hbk). In Altman’s two books on Plato, Plato the Teacher (2012) and The Guardians in Action (2016), we find the traditional reading of Plato, i.e., the philosopher of ‘unchanging, eternal, and transcendent Ideas’ (p. xviii), combined with a rather unique interpretation of Plato as a pedagogue, whose main goal is not to instantiate the ideal state in reality but rather to spread an enlightened form of democracy through an ennobling education program of philosophy. Altman’s interpretation of Cicero as reader of Plato naturally progresses from these two books. Cicero is not the Academic Skeptic, as recent scholarship has argued, but rather an advocate for Platonic transcendence – and one no less relevant to our own historical moment than to the crisis for which Cicero’s philosophy was immediately intended: the fallen Republic. Central to Altman’s argument on Cicero is the main theme of his earlier work on Plato: the return to the cave. According to Altman, although Plato’s belief in transcendent Ideas of the world of intelligibility is genuine, the goal of Plato as philosophical pedagogue is not transcendence but rather a return to the chaotic world of becoming, in which politics take place. Cicero then, in his emulation and rivalry of Plato, is picking up where Plato left off. He is not merely indulging in Platonic transcendence but relying on his philosophical rhetoric at its most subtle level to win over an ideologically fraught and often incredulous Roman readership to political enlightenment and devotion to the Ideas.
    [Show full text]