Jesuit Psychology and the Theory of Knowledge

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Jesuit Psychology and the Theory of Knowledge Chapter 5 Jesuit Psychology and the Theory of Knowledge Daniel Heider 1 Introduction Although Jesuit philosophical psychology of the sixteenth and the first decades of the seventeenth century was mostly united against secular Aristotelianism, exemplified by “the sects” of the Alexandrists and the Averroists, doctrinal vari- ety conflating the panoply of Scholastic streams with important ingredients of the neo-Platonic and medical tradition can be seen as a typical feature of the early Jesuits’ philosophical syncretism.1 Despite this doctrinal heterogeneity, the goal of this chapter is to propose what I regard as an important “paradigm shift” in the development of the early (Iberian) Jesuits’ psychology. It has been claimed that Jesuit philosophers of the third generation, such as Pedro Hurta- do de Mendoza (1578–1641), Rodrigo de Arriaga (1592–1667), and Francisco de Oviedo (1602–51), substantially revived the Scholastic via moderna.2 This histo- riographical hypothesis about the crucial role of late medieval nominalism— there are, as yet, very few studies on the matter—will be verified on two issues typical of the period, both of which can be viewed as variants of the classical problem of “the one and the many.” First, there is the query about the char- acter of the distinction between the soul (the principle of unity) and its vital powers (the principle of plurality). Famously, critiques of the Scholastic theory of really distinct accidents (i.e., powers interceding between the soul and its acts; henceforth, the real distinction thesis [rdt]) constituted a representative piece of the philosophical agenda for early modern philosophers in general.3 1 For Jesuit syncretism, see Daniel Heider, “Introduction,” in Cognitive Psychology in Early Jesuit Scholasticism, ed. Daniel Heider (Neunkirchen-Seelscheid: Editiones Scholasticae, 2016), 1–11. 2 For Hurtado, see Ester Caruso, Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza e la rinascita del nominalismo nella Scolastica del Seicento (Florence: La Nuova Italia, 1979); for Arriaga, see Stanislav Sousedík and Tereza Saxlová, eds., Rodrigo de Arriaga (†1667): Philosoph und Theologe (Prague: Karo- linum, 1998). For the influence of late medieval nominalism on Oviedo, see Daniel Heider, “The Notitia intuitiva and Notitia abstractiva of the External Senses in Second Scholasticism: Suárez, Poinsot and Francisco de Oviedo,” Vivarium 54, no. 2–3 (2016): 173–203, here 192–200. 3 For a critique of Descartes and John Locke (1632–1794), see Dominik Perler, “Faculties in Me- dieval Philosophy,” in The Faculties: A History, ed. Dominik Perler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), 97–139, esp. 97–100. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���9 | doi:�0.��63/97890043944�4_007 <UN> 116 Heider The second issue is the gradual elimination of the intentional species (species intentionales).4 As is well known, mainstream Scholastic thinkers conceived intentional likeness as a necessary principle in explaining the production of cognitive acts. They were regarded as necessary “mediators” between sensible objects and cognitive powers. The flat reduction of the intentional species to their “mechanicized” counterparts epitomized the second important topos for philosophers and scientists active in the era of the scientific revolution.5 Im- portantly, proponents of both real identity between the soul and its powers (the real identity thesis [rit]) and of (partial) elimination of the species are far from restricted to traditional early modern philosophy. Not only can they be found in late medieval nominalism and even before in medieval Augustinian- ism and late ancient philosophy;6 both views were firmly established parts of the early Jesuit philosophical curriculum on the eve of modernity. This chapter compares Suárez’s rdt and his theory of the universal appli- cability of the sensible species in the external senses with Mendoza’s rit and his tenet of only partial applicability of the external senses’ sensible species. The following (chronological) objection can immediately be raised. Although Suárez wrote his commentary on De anima in the first half of the 1570s in Segovia, it was not published until 1621, while Hurtado’s Universa philosophia (Universal philosophy) was published for the first time six years earlier, in 1615. If we (rightly) assume that no essential innovations were made by Hurtado in the relevant parts of the Cursus, he could not react explicitly to Suárez’s views. Three partial replies can be proposed to defend the historical and the system- atic merit of this comparative project: (1) Although Hurtado does not quote from the commentary on De anima, he cites Suárez’s psychological views from 4 For the process of elimination of the intelligible species, see Leen Spruit, Species intelligibi- lis: From Perception to Knowledge, vol. 2, Renaissance Controversies, Later Scholasticism, and the Elimination of the Intelligible Species in Modern Philosophy (Leiden: Brill, 1995); see also Katharine Park, “The Organic Soul,” in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, ed. Charles B. Schmitt et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 464–84. 5 For the Cartesian “mechanicized Aristotelianism” of the theory of visual perception, see Ce- lia Wolf-Devine, Descartes on Seeing: Epistemology and Visual Perception (Carbondale: South- ern Illinois University, 1993). 6 For the rit of William of Auvergne (c.1180/90–1249), see Perler, “Faculties in Medieval Philos- ophy,” 100–5; regarding Ockham’s rit combined with his “soul–mind dualism,” see Dominik Perler, “What Are the Faculties of the Soul? Descartes and His Scholastic Background,” in Continuity and Innovation in Medieval and Modern Philosophy: Knowledge, Mind, and Lan- guage, ed. John Marenbon (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 9–38, esp. 25–31. Ockham’s elimination of the intentional species is examined by Katherine H. Tachau, Vision and Cer- titude in the Age of Ockham: Optics, Epistemology and the Foundations of Semantics 1250–1345 (Leiden: Brill, 1988), 130–35. <UN>.
Recommended publications
  • SECOND SCHOLASTICISM and BLACK SLAVERY1 Segunda Escolástica E Escravidão Negra La Segunda Escolástica Y La Esclavitud Negra
    PORTO ALEGRE http://dx.doi.org/10.15448/1984-6746.2019.3.36112 SECOND SCHOLASTICISM AND BLACK SLAVERY1 Segunda Escolástica e escravidão negra La Segunda Escolástica y la esclavitud negra Roberto Hofmeister Pich2 Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul, Porto Alegre, RS, Brasil Abstract In order to systematically explore the normative treatment of black slavery by Second Scholastic thinkers, usually placing the problem within the broad discussion of moral conscience and, more narrowly, the nature and justice of trade and contracts, I propose two stations of research that may be helpful for future studies, especially in what con- cerns the study of Scholastic ideas in colonial Latin America. Beginning with the analysis of just titles for slavery and slavery trade proposed by Luis de Molina S.J. (1535–1600), I show how his accounts were critically reviewed by Diego de Avendaño S.J. (1594–1688), revealing basic features of Second Scholastic normative thinking in Europe and the Americas. Normative knowledge provided by these two Scholastic intellectuals would be deeply tested throughout the last decades of the 17th century, especially by authors who sharpened the systemic analysis and a rigorist moral assessment of every title of slavery and slaveholding, as well as the requirements of an ethics of restitution. Keywords: black slavery, Second Scholasticism, commutative justice, probabilism, Luis de Molina, Diego de Avendaño. 1 This study was prepared during a stay as guest professor at the Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms- Universität Bonn / Germany, as first “CAPES / Universität Bonn Lehrstuhlinhaber”, from July 2018 to February 2019. I hereby express my gratitude to the remarkable support of the Brazilian Agency Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior (Coordination for the Improvement of Higher Education Personnel) and the University of Bonn.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Truthmaking in 17Th-Century Scholasticism
    Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism by Brian Embry A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Brian Embry 2015 Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism Brian Embry Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2015 Abstract Some propositions are true and others are false. What explains this difference? Some philosophers have recently defended the view that a proposition is true because there is an entity, its truthmaker, that makes it true. Call this the ‘truthmaker principle’. The truthmaker principle is controversial, occasioning the rise of a large contemporary debate about the nature of truthmaking and truthmakers. What has gone largely unnoticed is that scholastics of the early modern period also had the notion of a truthmaker [verificativum], and this notion is at the center of early modern scholastic disputes about the ontological status of negative entities, the past and future, and uninstantiated essences. My project is to explain how early modern scholastics conceive of truthmaking and to show how they use the notion of a truthmaker to regiment ontological enquiry. I argue that the notion of a truthmaker is born of a certain conception of truth according to which truth is a mereological sum of a true mental sentence and its intentional object. This view entails the truthmaker principle and is responsible for some surprising metaphysical views. For example, it leads many early modern scholastics to posit irreducible negative entities as truthmakers for negative truths, giving rise to an extensive literature on the nature of negative entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Sovereignty and Economic Ethics Among the Spanish Second Scholasticism: Its Influence on Modern Thought
    June 8, 2011 16:44 Research Publishing : IJAS Sample ijas-0403 International Journal of Arts & Sciences, CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934 :: 4(3):141-150 (2011) Copyright c 2011 by InternationalJournal.org POLITICAL SOVEREIGNTY AND ECONOMIC ETHICS AMONG THE SPANISH SECOND SCHOLASTICISM: ITS INFLUENCE ON MODERN THOUGHT Rui Coimbra Gonçalves University of Coimbra, Portugal The question of power as it was thought by the theologians from the Spanish Second Scholasticism results always sensitive, especially while converting her in terms of political sovereignty exercise over the conquered peoples from the overseas. If the pattern native from Francisco de Vitoria, based in his turn in the ideas of Saint Thomas Aquinas, offered us already at the dawn of the XVI th century a compromise situation according to this matter, recognising the rights from the aborigine of no submission to the Christian missions, for Luis de Molina, the struggle was clearly for the defence by which the conquered peoples should convert in practical actions their claim to maintain their condition of independence and resistance against colonial power. The case was quite different in Francisco Suárez, a Spanish theologian from the University of Coimbra, like Molina. For him the church would have legitimacy to employ her force through the secular arm delegated in and offered by a prince of Christianity if any native nation refused to be evangelized. Finally the main aim of this report will be to find how the Spanish doctors from the early modern age in Europe continue today exerting their influence on the contemporary ethics namely through the economic questions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rational Shakespeare Michael Wainwright the Rational Shakespeare
    The Rational Shakespeare Michael Wainwright The Rational Shakespeare Peter Ramus, Edward de Vere, and the Question of Authorship Michael Wainwright Royal Holloway University of London Egham, UK ISBN 978-3-319-95257-4 ISBN 978-3-319-95258-1 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95258-1 Library of Congress Control Number: 2018949924 © The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Palgrave Macmillan, part of Springer Nature 2018 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the ­publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and ­institutional affiliations.
    [Show full text]
  • Directions in the Study of Early Modern Reformed Thought
    Perichoresis Volume 14. Issue 3 (2016): 3-16 DOI: 10.1515/perc-2016-0013 DIRECTIONS IN THE STUDY OF EARLY MODERN REFORMED THOUGHT RICHARD A. MULLER * Calvin Theological Seminary ABSTRACT. Given both the advances in understanding of early modern Reformed theology made in the last thirty years, the massive multiplication of available sources, the significant liter- ature that has appeared in collateral fields, there is a series of highly promising directions for further study. These include archival research into the life, work, and interrelationships of var- ious thinkers, contextual examination of larger numbers of thinkers, study of academic faculties, the interrelationships between theology, philosophy, science, and law, and the interactions pos- itive as well as negative between different confessionalities. KEY WORDS: Reformed orthodoxy, post-Reformation Reformed thought, early modernity, ex- egesis, philosophy Recent Advances in Research The study of early modern Reformed thought has altered dramatically in the last several decades. The once dominant picture of Calvin as the prime mover of the Reformed tradition and sole index to its theological integrity has largely disappeared from view, as has the coordinate view of ‘Calvinism ’ as a monolithic theology and the worry over whether later Reformed thought re- mained ‘true ’ to Calvin. The relatively neglected field of seventeenth-century Reformed thought has expanded and developed both in the number of di- verse thinkers examined and in the variety of approaches to the materials. (Given the number of recent published studies of early modern Reformed thought, the following essay makes no attempt to offer a full bibliography, but only to provide examples of various types of research.
    [Show full text]
  • Instituto De Filosofia Da Universidade Do Porto 1. Some Notes on The
    PAULA OLIVEIRA E SILVA SOME NOTES ON THE INFLUENCE OF THE 16TH CENTURY MEDICAL LITERATURE ON THE NATURE OF EMOTIONS IN F. SUAREZ’S DE PASSIONIBUS Instituto de Filosofia da Universidade do Porto 1. Some notes on the concept of Iberian Scholasticism We commonly name as Second Scholasticism, Iberian Scholasticism or Baroque Scholasticism the intellectual movement structured around the School of Salamanca in the early sixteenth century which disseminated to other Spanish universities and the Portuguese universities of Coimbra and Évora in the second half of the same century. The doctrines explained by these scholars and flourished from this academic context are preserved either in printed or manuscript form, being its influence crucial in the outlining of the European forma mentis of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. However the designation «Second Scholasticism» is far from being agreed on among scholars, due to the lack of adaptability between the word and the reality it refers to. In fact, in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, we can notice discontinuity to a certain extent in the scholastic teaching modelled in the universities of the thirteenth century on which it is based. Such remoteness from the medieval model is due to a complex set of factors and to the emergence of the movement designated as Renaissance Humanism. Nevertheless, even if this movement affected the European forma mentis, the medieval Scholastic paradigm did not disappear. In fact, it persisted throughout the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, alongside the Renaissance Humanism 1, being influenced by it to the point that the concept of Scholastic 1 Charles NAUERT points out the continuity between the medieval age and the Renaissance, touching on more radical interpretations on the innovative character of the movement known as Renaissance 1 Humanism, apparently contradictory, can be introduced while also recognizing, in documents, that the exact characterization of the semantic content of the concept is still to be defined 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanent Causation in Spinoza and Scholasticism
    Immanent Causation in Spinoza and Scholasticism by Stephen John Zylstra A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Stephen John Zylstra 2018 ABSTRACT Immanent Causation in Spinoza and Scholasticism Stephen John Zylstra Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2018 Spinoza is well-known for his claim that God is the only substance that exists, and that everything else is a mere “mode” of that substance. At the same time, Spinoza maintains that all things depend causally on God for their being. But if all of reality is in some sense identical with God, in what manner can God be its cause? Spinoza’s answer is found in his claim that “God is the immanent, and not the transeunt, cause of all things.” In this thesis, I investigate the scholastic roots of this distinction and its implications for understanding the fundamental features of Spinoza’s monistic ontology. The scholastics commonly distinguish between two kinds of activities, one which “remains” in the subject doing it and the other which “passes” outside. Those classified as immanent were primarily mental operations like thinking and willing. The first part of this thesis examines how the scholastics disagree over whether this kind of activity ought to be construed as a kind of production; the nature of its relation to its subject; and ii whether it is produced by means of ‘emanation’. The concept of an immanent cause emerges within this context. In the second part of this thesis, I bring this research to bear on our understanding of Spinoza’s metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Second Scholasticism Analytical Metaphysics
    CALL FOR PAPERS Next year, the outstanding Czech Christian philosopher Prof. Stanislav Sousedík (*1931) will celebrate an important anniversary. We would like to honour this occasion by hosting the conference Second Scholasticism Analytical Metaphysics Christian Apologetics A Conference in Honour of Professor Stanislav Sousedík’s 90th birthday 27th–29th October 2021 ◆ Catholic Theological Faculty, Prague, Czech Republic ithin Sousedík’s lifelong scholarly efforts, three ousedík came to be more deeply involved with contem- Wkey areas of interest can be distinguished: Sporary Western philosophy after the Velvet Revolution ܫ scholastic philosophy, especially Thomism, Scotism, of 1989. He identified analytical philosophy as the branch and the so-called Second scholasticism; closest to his scholastic interests since, like scholasticism, it pursues restrained and rigorous reasoning. The affinity of ܫ analytical philosophy, which the two currents gave him the idea he linked to his metaphysi- to bring the older scholastic tradi- cal interests; and, finally, tion up to date by means of analyti- ܫ an apologetic of the Christian cal philosophy and philosophical or, specifically, Catholic logic. His efforts found broader worldview. response and, gradually, a group of students gathered around him, ousedík first became ac- who followed upon his ideas in Squainted with the basics of historical and systematic respects. scholastic thought was during With their help he founded the his early theological studies. He journal Studia Neoaristotelica, which further developed his knowledge at first aimed at the Czech milieu only by self-study, deprived, but later opened to like-minded under the communist regime, of foreign scholars. contemporary literature and of the necessary contact with for- evertheless, in doing that he eign scholars, to whom he had Nbecame aware that his effort virtually no access before 1989.
    [Show full text]
  • Gerald A. Mccool, S. J
    A PREFACE Gerald A. McCool, S.J. The authors of these essays, as their reader will discover, are united in their admiration for the tradition of St. Thomas. Many of them, in fact, are willing to give their own philosophical allegiance to it. Yet, as their essays also show, disagreement over the correct interpretation of St. Thomas can still cause discord in the ranks of philosophers who look to him for inspiration. Thomists can still be found, it would appear, who find it hard to extend the hand of fellowship to colleagues whose understanding of the Angelic Doctor differs from their own. Disagree­ ment among Thomists, however, can be an encouraging sign. Shared devotion to St. Thomas, combined with a readiness to disagree with their colleagues over the proper interpretation of his teaching, has always been a characteristic of thinkers in the tradition of the Angelic Doctor; and if, as these essays show, lively discussion and spirited controversy can still be found in it, the tradition of St. Thomas must still retain its life and vigor. Indeed my own historical study of the nineteenth- and twentieth­ century neo-Thomistic movement (as part of an older and identifiable tradition of St. Thomas) has given support to my own confidence in the vitality of that larger tradition. The neo-Thomistic movement began modestly in the nineteenth century, and, after the promulgation of Leo XIII' s Aeterni Patris, developed into a leading force in twentieth-century Catholic thought. Reaching its high point at the middle of the century, the movement then found it difficult to retain its internal unity, and, after Vatican II, neo-Thomism was forced to surrender the position of leadership which it had enjoyed in Catholic philosophy and theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Medieval Philosophy After the Middle Ages
    chapter 11 MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY AFTER THE MIDDLE AGES Jacob Schmutz ‘Hasn’t Amerigo Vespucci discovered lands unknown to Ptolemy, Pliny and other geographers up to the present? Why shouldn’t the same be the case in other matters?’, asked the acclaimed Parisian professor of theology John Mair (1467–1550) in the fi rst decade of the sixteenth century (Mair 1509 , 1v). His judgement could well appear prophetic for all admirers of modern novelties in science, philosophy and religion, if only his name wasn’t the symbol of that very tradition that has usually been seen as the major obstacle to discoveries, namely, medieval-rooted scholasticism. From Erasmus, Rabelais and Luther down to Voltaire, passing through Puritan pulpits or Parisian ladies’ salons , his name and that of his contemporaries used to stand for the idle and obscure debates of academic philosophy: ‘to me, a Cursus philosophicus is but an Impertinency in Folio ; and the studying of them a laborious idleness’ wrote, for instance, Joseph Glanvill (1636–80) in his attempt to break scholastic dogmatism by the introduction of experimental method (Glanvill 1661 , 151, quoted by Knebel 2000 , 3). But whereas enlightened minds knew to express their disgust with wit, modern scholars satisfy themselves with a simply dismissive tone. Among historians of logic, for instance, it is commonly held that the creativity of scholasticism came to a certain form of standstill somewhere between the sixteenth and seventeenth cen- tury, and that there was something like a ‘big void’, fi lled only by the birth of analyt- ical philosophy in the nineteenth century.
    [Show full text]
  • Francisco Suárez and the Complexities of Modernity
    journal of jesuit studies 6 (2019) 559-576 brill.com/jjs Francisco Suárez and the Complexities of Modernity Juan Antonio Senent-De Frutos1 Universidad Loyola Andalucía [email protected] Abstract I present here a key to reading the work of Jesuit thinker Francisco Suárez in the con- text of the plurality and complexity of modernity. I show the main configuration that defines modernity in its hegemonic version, as well as its limitations. From there, I propose how Suárez’s work can be understood from the perspective of its own Ignatian and Jesuit spiritual framework and in relation to the development of modernity. Al- though a dominant version of modernity has historically prevailed, modernity cannot be understood as a uniform process but one that has been articulated and expressed in different civilizing missions since the Renaissance. One modern way of respond- ing to the socio-cultural challenges of the Renaissance was articulated by the Society of Jesus. I believe that in light of what I term an “Ignatian modernity,” we can better understand Suárez’s intellectual mission, its historical virtuality, and the possibilities marginalized by hegemonic modernity. Keywords Francisco Suárez – modernity – ignatian modernity – early modernity – Suarezian political modernity 1 Jesuits since Modernity This article about Francisco Suárez in the context of modernity2 is set in a broader context of research we are developing on the “Ignatian cultural 1 Professor of legal philosophy and political philosophy and director of the Department of Humanities and Philosophy at the Universidad Loyola Andalucía. 2 This article develops the presentation made as the co-organizer of the International Sym- posium on Jesuit Studies (Department of Humanities and Philosophy, Universidad Loyola © Juan Antonio Senent-De Frutos, 2019 | doi:10.1163/22141332-00604001 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the prevailing cc-by-nc license at the time of publication.
    [Show full text]
  • Bbm:978-94-015-8181-3/1.Pdf
    INDEXES INDEX OF NAMES Abaris 344 320,471 Abel 70, 104, 248, 447, 450 Alcinous (pseudo-), see Albinus of Smyrna Abelard, Peter 244, 375, 402, 405, 424, 425, Alcmaeon of Croton 189, 269 431 Alcuin of York 402 Abraham 70, 78, 96, 104, 105, 108, III, Il3, Alderotti, Taddeo (physician) 80 Il4, Il8, 121, 126 217, 227, 242, 249, 305, Aldo di Asolo (printer) 86 n 310, 447, 455 Aldobrandini, Pietro (Cardinal) 156, 157 Aceti, G. 442 Aldobrandini, Tommaso 156, 157, 158 Adam (Adamus), Melchior 70, 74, 97, 113, Alessandro di Sangro, Bishop of Bene- 128 vento 46 Adam xxiii, 52, 69, 70, 77, 91, 96, 100, 101, Alexander of Aphrodisias 43, 102, Il7, 216, 104, 107, 114, 115, 126, 215, 217, 238, 247, 230, 443, 467 251, 307, 310, 349, 446, 454, 466 Alexander of Hales 56, 456 Adrian VI, Pope (Adrian of Utrecht) 385 Alexander the Great 109, 131, 139, 166 Aegidius Romanus 27, 80, 102 Alexandre de Villedieu (Alexander de Aelian (Claudius Aelianus) 150 Villa Dei) 80 Aeschines Socraticus 180 Alfarabi, see al-Farabi Aeschylus 172, 173 Alfonso X (the Wise), King of Castile and Aesculapius 105, 109, 110 Leon 75,80 Aesop 73, 105 Algasel, see al-Ghazzali Aetius of Antioch 458 Allacci (Allatius), Leone 17B, 194 Agenor, King of the Phoenicians 108, Il2 Allen, M.]. B. 61 Aglaophemus 16, 24, Il2, Il7, 297 Allut, P. 63 Agricola, Rudolph 143, 242, 385 Amabile, L. xviii Agrippa von Nettesheim, Heinrich Cor- Amalric (Amaury) of Bene, 432 nelius 49, 51 n, 64, 447 Ammonius Alexandrinus (Eclectic philo- Aguzzi Barbagli, D.
    [Show full text]