Truth and Truthmaking in 17Th-Century Scholasticism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Truth and Truthmaking in 17Th-Century Scholasticism Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism by Brian Embry A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Brian Embry 2015 Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism Brian Embry Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2015 Abstract Some propositions are true and others are false. What explains this difference? Some philosophers have recently defended the view that a proposition is true because there is an entity, its truthmaker, that makes it true. Call this the ‘truthmaker principle’. The truthmaker principle is controversial, occasioning the rise of a large contemporary debate about the nature of truthmaking and truthmakers. What has gone largely unnoticed is that scholastics of the early modern period also had the notion of a truthmaker [verificativum], and this notion is at the center of early modern scholastic disputes about the ontological status of negative entities, the past and future, and uninstantiated essences. My project is to explain how early modern scholastics conceive of truthmaking and to show how they use the notion of a truthmaker to regiment ontological enquiry. I argue that the notion of a truthmaker is born of a certain conception of truth according to which truth is a mereological sum of a true mental sentence and its intentional object. This view entails the truthmaker principle and is responsible for some surprising metaphysical views. For example, it leads many early modern scholastics to posit irreducible negative entities as truthmakers for negative truths, giving rise to an extensive literature on the nature of negative entities. In order to find truthmakers for the so-called eternal truths, such as ‘A human being is an animal’, some philosophers claim that individual essences distinct from and independent of God necessarily have being from eternity. ii Other early modern scholastics reject these extravagant views; they argue that only positive, present tense truths are made true by existing things. This view is motivated jointly by (i) a distinctive theory of truth bearers, (ii) a common sense view of the truth conditions for negative, tensed, and modal truths, and (iii) the idea that truths are about their truthmakers. I argue that this view has significant philosophical consequences and should be attractive to those who think both that truth is grounded in being and that not every truth has a truthmaker. iii Acknowledgments This dissertation has benefited tremendously from the feedback of many patient readers, including Martin Pickavé, Marleen Rozemond, Jessica Wilson, Peter King, Adam Murray, Elena Derksen, Daniel Rabinoff, James Davies, Sydney Penner, Stephan Schmid, Megan Embry, audience members at the 2014 Toronto Colloquium in Mediaeval Philosophy, and audience members at the 2012 Toronto-Berlin Workshop in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. I owe special thanks to Megan Embry, not only a patient reader but also a patient spouse who provided much more than feedback. Material from chapter five also appears in Brian Embry, “An Early Modern Scholastic Theory of Negative Entities: Thomas Compton Carleton on Lacks, Negations, and Privations,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23, no. 1 (2014): 22-45. Material from chapters three and four will also appear in Brian Embry, “Truth and Truthmakers in Early Modern Scholasticism,” Journal of the American Philosophical Association, forthcoming. iv Table of Contents Abbreviations ix Note on Translations xi Introduction 1 Part I 1 Truthmaking 13 1.1 Motivation 13 1.2 A “Cross-Categorial” Relation 21 1.3 Necessitation 22 1.3.1 Alleged Problems With Necessitation 24 1.4 Many-Many 27 1.5 Relevance 30 1.6 Summing Up 33 2 Medieval Background 34 2.1 Correspondence and Aquinas 35 2.2 The Sophisma, ‘Omnis homo de necessitate est animal’ 41 2.3 Verificare and Verificatio 45 2.4 Complexe Significabile 49 2.5 Chatton’s Principle 58 3 Truth in 17th-Century Scholasticism 66 3.1 The Monadic Property View and the Real Relation View 72 3.2 Suárez’s Legacy: The Semi-Extrinsic Denomination View and the Connotation View 77 v 3.2.1 The Semi-Extrinsic Denomination View 79 3.2.2 Denominations 80 3.2.3 The Composite View and Truthmaking 89 3.3 The Connotation View 91 3.4 Conclusion: Truth and Conformity 97 4 The Standard Account of Truthmaking 103 4.1 The Standard Account 103 4.2 Departures from the Standard Account 113 Part II 5 Negative Truths 115 5.1 Carentism 116 5.1.1 “How can any existent really be negative?” 122 5.1.2 Individuating Lacks 126 5.1.3 “What, though, is a non-hippopotamus, and where exactly in the room is it?” 130 5.1.4 Lacks, Privations, and Their Subjects 134 5.1.5 Theological Objections 138 5.1.6 A Difficulty for the Hypothesis of Negative Entities 143 5.2 Incompatibilism 151 Excursus: Contemporary Objections 155 5.3 Nihilism 161 5.3.1 Peinado’s Theory of Truth: A First Pass 162 5.3.2 Peinado on Negative Truths 164 vi 5.3.3 Motivating Peinado’s Truthmaker Principle: The Intentional Mode View of Affirmation and Negation 170 5.3.4 Motivating the Aboutness Constraint and the Intentional Mode View of Negation 176 Excursus on Mauro 179 5.3.5 Peinado’s Theory of Truth 179 5.4 Conclusion 187 6 Future Contingents 189 6.1 Denying Future? 191 6.2 Denying Presentism 194 6.3 Denying Independence 204 6.4 Modifying Truthmaker 213 6.4.1 Peinado’s Motivation for the Wide-Base Truthmaker Principle 216 Excursus on Oaklander’s Theory of Tense 223 6.4.2 Wide-Base Truthmaking and Peinado’s Theory of Truth 224 6.5 Conclusion 228 7 Eternal Truths 230 7.1 Realist Essentialism 231 7.1.1 Essentialism and Truthmaking 233 7.1.2 Essential Being 239 7.1.3 Theological Objections 248 7.2 Conceptualist Essentialism 252 7.3 Truthmaker Theism 259 7.4 Francisco Peinado on Merely Possible Truthmakers 275 vii 7.4.1 Super Wide-Base Truthmaking and Peinado’s Theory of Truth 285 7.5 Conclusion 288 Excursus: Peinado’s Account of Truthmaking 290 8 Conclusion 298 Works Cited: Primary Sources 304 Works Cited: Contemporary Sources 310 viii Abbreviations Used in Citations ch. Chapter concl. Conclusion contr. Controversy cst. Consectarium cv. Controversy d. Disputation diss. Dissertation div. Division dub. Dubium fn. Footnote lib. Book n. Number p. Page princ. Principle prop. Proposition pt. Point s. Section subs. Subsection t. Tractatus ix Abbreviations for Aquinas’s Works QDV Questiones disputatae de veritate SCG Summa contra gentiles ST Summa theologiae In I Sent. Scriptum super libros sententiarum, in primum librum De ente De ente et essentia In meta. In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio Abbreviations for Ockham’s Works Expos. Praedicam. Expositio in librum Praedicamentorum Aristotelis Quodl. Quodlibeta OP Opera philosophica Abbreviations for Suárez’s Works DM Disputationes Metaphysicae, vols. 25-26 in Opera omnia x A Note on Translations All translations are my own except in a few cases where a translation is cited. I provide the Latin in the footnotes. In reproducing the Latin, I sometimes alter the original punctuation to make the sentence structure more perspicuous. xi INTRODUCTION The notion of a truthmaker has recently gained such prominence in metaphysics that Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra has called truthmaker theory “one of the most important metaphysical topics of the late 20th-century and early 21st-century philosophy.”1 At a first approximation, a truthmaker is something that makes a proposition true. As D. M. Armstrong and Ross Cameron explain: The idea of a truthmaker for a particular truth, then, is just some existent, some portion of reality, in virtue of which that truth is true.2 When there is truth, there must be some thing (or things) to account for that truth: some thing(s) that couldn’t exist and the true proposition fail to be true. That is the truthmaker principle. True propositions are made true by entities in the mind- independently existing external world.3 For example, Obama is the portion of reality in virtue of which it is true that Obama exists, so Obama is the truthmaker for that proposition. There are also non-trivial examples of truthmakers. The fact that Obama is tall, for example, might be the truthmaker for the proposition that Obama is tall.4 Advocates tout truthmaker theory as a good way to regiment ontological inquiry—to find out what our ontological commitments are by way of what we take to be truthmakers for various sorts of truths. There are many questions we might raise about truthmaker theory, and I raise them in subsequent chapters, but for now I want to focus on the history of the notion of a truthmaker. 1 “Truthmakers,” 186. For more on truthmaking, see Armstrong, Truth and Truthmakers; Merricks, Truth and Ontology; Beebee and Dodd, Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate; Lowe and Rami, eds., Truth and Truth-Making; Mulligan, Simons, and Smith, “Truth-Makers.” 2 Armstrong, Truth and Truthmakers, 5. 3 Cameron, “How To Be a Truthmaker Maximalist,” 410. 4 In the contemporary literature one may sometimes find it said that the claim that the fact that p makes it true that p is a trivial claim. In my view, no claim is trivial if it entails something controversial, and “the fact that p makes it true that p” entails the controversial claim that there are facts. At any rate, I am prepared to grant that “the fact that p makes it true that p” is trivial if you are prepared to grant that it is true. For the triviality objection, see Peter Forrest and Drew Khlentzos, “Introduction: Truth Maker and Its Varieties,” 8.
Recommended publications
  • Beaneyanalyticphil Historyphil.Pdf
    King’s Research Portal DOI: 10.1007/978-1-137-30487-2 Document Version Peer reviewed version Link to publication record in King's Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Beaney, M. (2013). Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy: The Development of the Idea of Rational Reconstruction . In E. Reck (Ed.), The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy (1 ed., pp. 231–260). (History of Analytic Philosophy). Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-30487-2 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on King's Research Portal is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Post-Print version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version for pagination, volume/issue, and date of publication details. And where the final published version is provided on the Research Portal, if citing you are again advised to check the publisher's website for any subsequent corrections. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognize and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. •Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research. •You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain •You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Research Portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.
    [Show full text]
  • Rule and Foundational Documents
    Rule and Foundational Documents Frontispiece: facsimile reproduction of a page—chapter 22, “Rules Concern- ing the Good Order and Management of the Institute”—from the Rule of the Brothers of the Christian Schools, the 1718 manuscript preserved in the Rome archives of the Institute. Photo E. Rousset (Jean-Baptiste de La Salle; Icono- graphie, Boulogne: Limet, 1979, plate 52). Rule and Foundational Documents John Baptist de La Salle Translated and edited by Augustine Loes, FSC, and Ronald Isetti Lasallian Publications Christian Brothers Conference Landover, Maryland Lasallian Publications Sponsored by the Regional Conference of Christian Brothers of the United States and Toronto Editorial Board Luke Salm, FSC, Chairman Paul Grass, FSC, Executive Director Daniel Burke, FSC William Mann, FSC Miguel Campos, FSC Donald C. Mouton, FSC Ronald Isetti Joseph Schmidt, FSC Augustine Loes, FSC From the French manuscripts, Pratique du Règlement journalier, Règles communes des Frères des Écoles chrétiennes, Règle du Frère Directeur d’une Maison de l’Institut d’après les manuscrits de 1705, 1713, 1718, et l’édition princeps de 1726 (Cahiers lasalliens 25; Rome: Maison Saint Jean-Baptiste de La Salle, 1966); Mémoire sur l’Habit (Cahiers lasalliens 11, 349–54; Rome: Maison Saint Jean-Baptiste de La Salle, 1962); Règles que je me suis imposées (Cahiers lasalliens 10, 114–16; Rome: Maison Saint Jean-Baptiste de La Salle, 1979). Rule and Foundational Documents is volume 7 of Lasallian Sources: The Complete Works of John Baptist de La Salle Copyright © 2002 by Christian Brothers Conference All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Control Number: 2002101169 ISBN 0-944808-25-5 (cloth) ISBN 0-944808-26-3 (paper) Cover: Portrait of M.
    [Show full text]
  • Antoine De Chandieu (1534-1591): One of the Fathers Of
    CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY ANTOINE DE CHANDIEU (1534-1591): ONE OF THE FATHERS OF REFORMED SCHOLASTICISM? A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY THEODORE GERARD VAN RAALTE GRAND RAPIDS, MICHIGAN MAY 2013 CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY 3233 Burton SE • Grand Rapids, Michigan • 49546-4301 800388-6034 fax: 616 957-8621 [email protected] www. calvinseminary. edu. This dissertation entitled ANTOINE DE CHANDIEU (1534-1591): L'UN DES PERES DE LA SCHOLASTIQUE REFORMEE? written by THEODORE GERARD VAN RAALTE and submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy has been accepted by the faculty of Calvin Theological Seminary upon the recommendation of the undersigned readers: Richard A. Muller, Ph.D. I Date ~ 4 ,,?tJ/3 Dean of Academic Programs Copyright © 2013 by Theodore G. (Ted) Van Raalte All rights reserved For Christine CONTENTS Preface .................................................................................................................. viii Abstract ................................................................................................................... xii Chapter 1 Introduction: Historiography and Scholastic Method Introduction .............................................................................................................1 State of Research on Chandieu ...............................................................................6 Published Research on Chandieu’s Contemporary
    [Show full text]
  • Truthmaker Monism
    Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science Vol.29 (2020) 61~73 61 Truthmaker Monism Taiji Yukimoto∗ and Tora Koyama∗∗ Abstract Monism is a metaphysical view according to which there is only one funda- mental object. This paper will explore monism within the context of truthmaker theory, or Truthmaker Monism, a view rarely discussed in literature. Although few truthmaker theorists defend monism, at least explicitly, some theories seem to share the spirit of monism to some extent. Interestingly, they are proposed as solutions for the same problem, called the problem of negative truth.Acloseexam- ination will show that while each of these solutions can account for the problem, they are unsatisfactory for different reasons. This paper will suggest a novel solu- tion to the problem of negative truth which preserves the advantages of existing solutions while avoiding the difficulties with which they are faced. Key words: monism, truthmaker, actuality, duplicate, the Humean denial of necessary connections Introduction Monism is a metaphysical view according to which there is only one fundamental object. Recent discussions of monism in analytic metaphysics began with the sem- inal paper by Jonathan Schaffer (2010b).1 Although his view is undoubtedly one of speculative metaphysics, the arguments raised in his paper invoke not only the stan- dard apparatus of metaphysics such as mereology and possible worlds, but also the history of philosophy (Aristotle, Spinoza, and Hegel, among other great figures) and contemporary physics (and particularly the phenomenon of entanglement in quantum ∗ Graduate School of Human Sciences, Osaka University, 1–3, Yamadaoka, Suita, 565– 0871, Japan ∗∗ Research Institute for Time Studies, Yamaguchi University, 1677-1, Yoshida, Yam- aguchi, 753–8511, Japan This paper is based on Yukimoto’s talk at the 8th annual conference of Japan As- sociation for the Contemporary and Applied Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • John Duns Scotus, Philosopher
    John Duns Scotus, Philosopher Proceedings of "The Quadruple Congress" on John Duns Scotus von Mary B Ingham, Oleg V Bychkov 1. Auflage John Duns Scotus, Philosopher – Ingham / Bychkov schnell und portofrei erhältlich bei beck-shop.de DIE FACHBUCHHANDLUNG Thematische Gliederung: Christliche Philosophie Aschendorff Verlag Münster 2010 Verlag C.H. Beck im Internet: www.beck.de ISBN 978 3 402 10213 8 Archa Verbi Subsidia, Vol. 3 Archa Verbi Yearbook for the Study of Medieval Theology Subsidia 3 Mary Beth Ingham and Oleg Bychkov (Eds) John Duns Scotus, Philosopher Proceedings of “The Quadruple Congress” on John Duns Scotus Part 1 Franciscan Institute Publications Archa Verbi Annuarium Societatis Internationalis pro Studiis Theologiae Medii Aevi promovendis Annuaire de la Société Internationale pour l‘Étude de la Théologie Médiévale Annuario della Società Internazionale per lo Studio della Teologia Medievale Anuario de la Sociedad Internacional para los Estudios de la Teología Medieval Jahrbuch der Internationalen Gesellschaft für Theologische Mediävistik Yearbook of the International Society for the Study of Medieval Theology Subsidia curator Riccardo Quinto Pavel Blažek Ursula Vones-Liebenstein directorium Societatis Volker Leppin praeses Societatis Bibliografi sche Information der Deutschen Bibliothek: Die Deutsche Bibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografi e; detailliert bibliografi sche Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.ddb.de abrufbar. Library of Congress Control Number: 2010925581 Cover illustration:
    [Show full text]
  • Haecceities, Quiddities, and Structure∗
    compiled on 18 December 2015 at 14:00 Haecceities, quiddities, and structure∗ Wolfgang Schwarz Draft, 18 December 2015 Abstract. Suppose all truths are made true by the distribution of funda- mental properties and relations over fundamental particulars. The world is then completely characterized by stating which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by which fundamental particulars. But do we have to mention the fundamental particulars by name? Arguably not. Arguably, all truths – or at least all truths we can ever know – are made true by the pattern in which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by fundamental particulars, irrespective of the identity (“haecceity”) of those particulars. Parallel arguments suggest that the identity (“quiddity”) of fundamental properties and relations can be omitted. It would follow that all truths (or all knowable truths) are made true by the abstract structure of the world, the pattern in which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by fundamental particulars, irrespective of the identity of the properties, relations, and particulars. I argue that this is almost correct: while not all truths are made true by the abstract structure of the world, the remaining truths are (in a certain sense) not made true by the world at all. 1 Introduction Most truths can be explained by other, more fundamental truths. That salt dissolves in water, for example, can be explained by the chemical composition of salt and water together with the general laws of physics. Explanations of this kind plausibly come to an end. At some point we reach a bottom level of fundamental facts that are not explainable in terms of anything more basic.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Holcot, O-P-, on Prophecy, the Contingency of Revelation, and the Freedom of God JOSEPH M
    Robert Holcot, O-P-, on Prophecy, the Contingency of Revelation, and the Freedom of God JOSEPH M. INCANDELA In a recent work, William Courtenay refers to the issues in Holcot's writings under discussion in this essay as "theological sophismata."1 That they are. But it is the burden of this essay to suggest that they are more: Holcot's interest in these questions had a funda- mentally practical import, and such seemingly esoteric philosophical and theological speculation was in the service of a pastoral program geared to preaching the faith to unbelievers. For someone in a religious order charged with this mission, questions that may initially appear only as sophismata may actually perform quite different functions when examined in context. Robert Holcot was best known in his own time as a comment tator on the Book of Wisdom. Wey writes that this work "made its author famous overnight and his fame held throughout the next two centuries."2 Wey also proposes that it was because of the rep- utation won with the Wisdom-commentary that Holcot's Sentences- commentary and some quodlibet questions were printed four times 1. William]. Courtenay, Schools and Scholars in Fourteenth Century England (Prince- ton: Princeton University Press, 1987), p. 303. 2. Joseph C. Wey, "The Sermo Finalis of Robert Holcot," Medieval Studies 11 (1949): 219-224, at p. 219. 165 166 JOSEPH M. INCANDELA between 1497 and 1518. His thought was also deemed important enough to be discussed and compared with that of Scotus and Ockham in a work by Jacques Almain printed in 1526.
    [Show full text]
  • Feng Youlan's Interpretation of Western Philosophy
    ASIANetwork Exchange | Fall 2014 | volume 22 | 1 Feng Youlan’s Interpretation of Western Philosophy: A Critical Examination from the Perspective of Metaphysical Methodology Derong Chen Abstract: This paper concentrates on Feng’s interpretation of Western philosophy from the perspective of metaphysical methodology and aims to display a limited observation of Feng’s interpretation of Western philosophy through the window of metaphysical methodology. Based on a brief review of the recent studies of Feng Youlan and Western philoso- phy, this paper analyzes the progress and insufficient aspects in current studies on this issue and particularly clarifies what are the metaphysics and metaphysical methods in the context of Feng Youlan’s philosophy. In clarifying Feng’s interpreta- tion of Western philosophy from the perspective of methodology, this paper further critically analyzes Feng’s positive metaphysical methods and negative metaphysical methods, and assumes that Feng’s negative metaphysical methods essentially is a kind of attitude towards metaphysics but neither a kind of metaphysics nor a kind of metaphysical methods. Instead of characterizing metaphysical methods as positive and negative as Feng did, this paper suggests an alternative division of metaphysical methods: direct and indirect methods of dealing with metaphysical issues. Keywords Feng Youlan; metaphysics; metaphysical methods; Western philosophy; negative metaphysics In the twentieth century, Feng Youlan was one of the Chinese intellectuals most deeply Derong Chen is a Sessional involved in the dialogue and interaction between Chinese and Western philosophies. In Lecturer II at the University of addition to studying Western philosophy at Columbia University, he systematically con- Toronto Mississauga. ducted research on Western philosophy, specifically the philosophy of life.
    [Show full text]
  • Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'brien
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1994 The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien. Donna Glee Williams Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Williams, Donna Glee, "The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien." (1994). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5768. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5768 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough,m asubstandard r gins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in Franciscantheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus
    Andrew V. Rosato The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in FranciscanTheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus Abstract: This chapter examines how the Summa Halensis’ analysis of Christ’ssorrow was adopted and modified by later Franciscan theologians.Accordingtothe teach- ing of Jerome, which Peter Lombardmade available to medieval theologians,Christ’s sorrow arose from an involuntary reaction to his physical suffering. In order to ex- pand upon Jerome’saccount,the Summa Halensis develops an elaborate map of Christ’ssoul by drawing on psychological principles found in Augustine and John Damascene. 13th century theologians debated whether Christ could experience sor- row over his ownsuffering not justasanatural and instinctual reaction, but also as the result of freelywillingthat he not suffer.Anobstacle to asserting this would be anyimplication that Christ did not will by his human willwhat God willed him to will. Richard of Middleton, Matthew of Aquasparta, and Duns Scotus do af- firm that Christ in some wayfreelynilled his own suffering, and experiencedsorrow over it because of that.Indifferent ways they employ the account of Christ’ssoul out- lined in the Summa Halensis to avoid anyimplication that Christ fell into sin by freely nilling his ownsuffering. The GospelofMatthew reports that Jesus experienced sorrow in the Garden of Geth- semane (26:37–38): ‘he began to be sorrowful [coepit contristari]and troubled. Then he said to them, “My soul is sorrowful [tristis]tothe point of death.”’ Jerome offered an influential interpretation of this passagewhen he statedthatChrist experienced the propassion of sorrow rather than afull-fledgedform of thatpassion. One differ- ence between apropassion and afull-fledgedpassion is that apropassion does not overwhelm one’sability to use reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Grounds for Negative Truths
    Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-016-0841-x Causal grounds for negative truths Robin Stenwall1 Ó The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract Among truthmaker theorists it is generally thought that we are not able to use the entailment principle (i.e. the principle according to which truthmaking distributes across entailment) to ground negative truths. But these theorists usually only discuss truthmakers for truth-functional complexes, thereby overlooking the fact that there are non-truth-functional complexes whose truth values are not solely determined by the truth or falsity of their atomic propositions. And once we expand the class of truths that require their own bespoke truthmakers to also include these, there is no reason to exempt negative truths from grounding. For given that truth- making is closed under entailment and every negative truths is entailed by some non-truth-functional complex or other, any resources rich enough to ground the truth of the latter will do the same job for the former. Keywords Truthmaking Á Causation Á Grounding Á Negative truth Á Maximalism 1 Introduction Let us, following Armstrong (2004, pp. 5–7), call the view that every true proposition has a truthmaker, Truthmaker Maximalism. Some truthmaker theorists deny maximalism in view of negative truths. In logical atomism, for example, the truth value of a truth-functional complex is explained in terms of its logical structure and the truth or falsity of its atomic propositions. This has led some philosophers to argue that true truth-functions do not need bespoke truthmakers: all it takes to fix the truth value of a truth-functional complex is to fix the truth value of its simpler constituents.
    [Show full text]