The Proper Forcing Axiom and the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Proper Forcing Axiom and the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis The Erwin Schr¨odinger International Boltzmanngasse 9 ESI Institute for Mathematical Physics A-1090 Wien, Austria The Proper Forcing Axiom and the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis Matteo Viale Vienna, Preprint ESI 1697 (2005) September 14, 2005 Supported by the Austrian Federal Ministry of Education, Science and Culture Available via http://www.esi.ac.at The Proper Forcing Axiom and the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis Matteo Viale ∗ Abstract We show that the Proper Forcing Axiom implies the Singular Cardinal Hy- pothesis. The proof uses ideas of Moore from [11] and the notion of a relativized trace function on pairs of ordinals. Introduction In one of the first applications of the forcing techniques, Easton [3] showed that the exponential function κ 7→ 2κ on regular cardinals can be arbitrary modulo some mild restrictions. The situation for singular cardinals is much more subtle. For instance, Silver [14] showed that the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis SCH cannot first fail at a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Recall that SCH states that 2κ = κ+, for all singular strong limit cardinals κ. However, it is known that SCH can first fail even at ℵω. The role of large cardinals in this context is twofold. On the one hand they are necessary for the construction of models of the negation of SCH (see [5] for a survey of Prikry type forcings and applications to SCH). On the other hand it is a theorem of Solovay [15] that SCH holds above a strongly compact cardinal. Forcing axioms imply reflection principles similar to the one used in Solovay’s proof, thus it was reasonable to expect that they would also settle SCH. Indeed, in [4], Foreman, Magidor and Shelah showed that the strongest forcing axiom, Martin’s Maximum MM, implies SCH. This was later improved by Veliˇckovi´c [17] who also showed that SCH follows from PFA+. In fact, what is shown in [17] ω is that if θ > ℵ1 is regular and stationary subsets of [θ] reflect to an internally closed and unbounded set, then θω = θ. This, combined with Silver’s theorem, implies SCH. At this point, it was left open whether SCH is a consequence of PFA. Very little progress was made on this problem for over fifteen years. Then, in 2003, Moore [10] introduced a new reflection principle, the Mapping Reflection Principle MRP and deduced it from PFA. He showed that MRP implies the continuum is equal to ℵ2 and the failure of 2(κ), for all κ > ℵ1. MRP has ∗ Dipartimento di Matematica, Universit´adi Torino and Equipe de Logique Math´ematique, Uni- versit´eParis 7, email: [email protected]. 2000 Mathematical Subject Classification: 03E05, 03E10, 03E65, 03E75. Key words: MRP, PFA, SCH, minimal walks. 1 many features in common with the reflection principles which follow from MM, so it should be expected that MRP could affect the behaviour of the exponential function also on higher cardinals. In fact, Moore showed in [11] that if MRP holds and κ > ω1 is a regular cardinal with a nonreflecting stationary set consisting of points of countable cofinality, then κω1 = κ. This, combined with the above result of Veliˇckovi´c, strongly suggests that PFA implies SCH. In this paper we confirm this conjecture. The new technical tool we introduce is the notion of a relativized trace function defined on pairs of ordinals. This allows us to get rid of the nonreflecting stationary set in Moore’s argument. The paper is organized as follows. In section §1 we introduce the relativized trace, which is a generalization of the functions considered in [16], and we outline the properties of this function which are relevant for our purposes. In section ω §2 we prove that if MRP holds then κ = κ for all regular cardinals κ > ω1. This, together with Silver’s theorem, implies that SCH follows from PFA. In the final section we show that the techniques introduced in this paper can be applied to study another interesting problem in the area of forcing axioms, i.e. to investigate what kind of forcing notions can preserve this type of axioms. Our notation is standard and follows [7] and [11]. For a regular cardinal θ, we use H(θ) to denote the structure (H(θ), ∈, <) whose domain is the collection of sets whose transitive closure is of size less than θ and where < is a predicate for a fixed well ordering of H(θ). If X is an uncountable set, C ⊆ [X]ω is closed and unbounded (club) if there is f : [X]<ω → X such that C is the set of all Y ∈ [X]ω such that f[Y ]<ω ⊆ Y . S ⊆ [X]ω is stationary if it intersects all club subsets of [X]ω. The f-closure of X is the smallest Y containing X such that f[Y ]<ω ⊆ Y . If X is a set of ordinals then X denotes the topological closure of X in the order topology. 1 The relativized trace function In this section we introduce a relativized version of the trace function considered by Todorˇcevi´c(see [16]) and outline some of its relevant properties. This function describes a descending walk from a larger ordinal β to a smaller ordinal α similar to the standard trace function. The rules of the walk are determined by a parameter X. This relativized trace function is designed in order to control very well its behavior on the points of the walk belonging to X. Given κ regular cardinal, fix a sequence (Cα : α ∈ κ & cof α = ω) such that Cα is a cofinal subset of α of order type ω for all α < κ of cofinality ω. ≤ω Definition 1 Let X ∈ [κ] , then for all α, β ∈ κ, trX (α, β) is defined as follows: (i) if β < α then trX (α, β) = ∅ (ii) trX (α, α) = {α} (iii) trX (α, β +1) = trX (α, β) ∪{β +1} (iv) if β > α is a limit ordinal then: if cof β > ω then trX (α, β) = trX (α, sup(β ∩ X)) ∪{β}, 2 if cof β = ω then set trX(α, β) = trX (α, min(Cβ \ α)) ∪{β}. So, walking from β to α we treat points which are either successors or of countable cofinality as in the usual walk. However, points of uncountable cofinality are treated as successors in the sense that we go from β to sup(β ∩ X). We now state the key properties of the function trX which we will use. Fact 1 For α, β < κ we have the following. (i) If α ∈ X and β ≥ α, then α ∈ trX (α, β) (ii) For all α ≤ β there is a γ < α such that trX (α, β) ⊆ trX (η,β), for all η ∈ (γ, α]. Proof: (i) If α ∈ X then sup(β ∩ X) ≥ α for any β > α. We proceed by induction. The base case is trivial by (ii) in the definition of trX. If the claim holds for all γ such that α ≤ γ<β, we have three cases, β successor, β of countable cofinality, β of uncountable cofinality. (a) If β = γ+1, the induction hypothesis applies to trX(α, γ). Since trX(α, β) = trX (α, γ) ∪{β} we are done. (b) If cof(β) = ω, then the induction hypothesis applies to trX (α, min(Cβ \ α)), since α ≤ min(Cβ \ α) < β. Now trX (α, β) = trX(α, sup(Cβ \ α)) ∪{β}, so we are done. (c) If cof(β) > ω then α ≤ sup(β ∩ X) <β and trX (α, β) = trX (α, sup(β ∩ X)) ∪{β} now the induction hypothesis applies to trX (α, sup(β ∩ X)). This concludes the proof of (i). (ii) We may assume that α is a limit ordinal. Then there are two cases: (a) sup(α ∩ X) = α. Then let γβ = max{max(Cη ∩ α) : η ∈ trX (α, β) ∩ cof(ω),η 6= α}. It is easy to check by induction on β ≥ α that if ρ ∈ (γβ, α] then trX(α, β) ⊆ trX(ρ,β), using the fact that γβ ≥ γη and that sup(η ∩ X) ≥ α, for all η ∈ trX(α, β). (b) sup(α ∩ X) < α. Then proceed as above taking γβ = max({sup(α ∩ X)}∪{max(Cη ∩ α) : η ∈ trX (α, β) ∩ cof(ω),η 6= α}). 3 2 The main result The purpose of this section is to show that MRP implies that λω = λ, for every cardinal λ > ω1 with cof(λ) > ω. We start by recalling the relevant definitions from [10]. Definition 2 Let θ be a regular cardinal, let X be uncountable, and let M ≺ H(θ) be countable such that [X]ω ∈ M. A subset Σ of [X]ω is M-stationary if for all E ∈ M such that E ⊆ [X]ω is club, Σ ∩ E ∩ M 6= ∅. Recall that the Ellentuck topology on [X]ω is obtained by declaring a set open if it is the union of sets of the form [x,N] = {Y ∈ [X]ω : x ⊆ Y ⊆ N} where N ∈ [X]ω and x ⊆ N is finite. When we say ‘open’ in this paper we refer to this topology. Definition 3 Σ is an open stationary set mapping if there is an uncountable set X and a regular cardinal θ such that [X]ω ∈ H(θ), the domain of Σ is a club in [H(θ)]ω of countable elementary submodels M such that X ∈ M and for all M, Σ(M) ⊆ [X]ω is open and M-stationary. The Mapping Reflection Principle (MRP) asserts that: If Σ is an open stationary set mapping, there is a continuous ∈-chain N~ = (Nξ : ξ < ω1) of elements in the domain of Σ such that for all limit ordinals ξ < ω1 there is ν<ξ such that Nη ∩ X ∈ Σ(Nξ) for all η such that ν<η<ξ.
Recommended publications
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • Singular Cardinals: from Hausdorff's Gaps to Shelah's Pcf Theory
    SINGULAR CARDINALS: FROM HAUSDORFF’S GAPS TO SHELAH’S PCF THEORY Menachem Kojman 1 PREFACE The mathematical subject of singular cardinals is young and many of the math- ematicians who made important contributions to it are still active. This makes writing a history of singular cardinals a somewhat riskier mission than writing the history of, say, Babylonian arithmetic. Yet exactly the discussions with some of the people who created the 20th century history of singular cardinals made the writing of this article fascinating. I am indebted to Moti Gitik, Ronald Jensen, Istv´an Juh´asz, Menachem Magidor and Saharon Shelah for the time and effort they spent on helping me understand the development of the subject and for many illuminations they provided. A lot of what I thought about the history of singular cardinals had to change as a result of these discussions. Special thanks are due to Istv´an Juh´asz, for his patient reading for me from the Russian text of Alexandrov and Urysohn’s Memoirs, to Salma Kuhlmann, who directed me to the definition of singular cardinals in Hausdorff’s writing, and to Stefan Geschke, who helped me with the German texts I needed to read and sometimes translate. I am also indebted to the Hausdorff project in Bonn, for publishing a beautiful annotated volume of Hausdorff’s monumental Grundz¨uge der Mengenlehre and for Springer Verlag, for rushing to me a free copy of this book; many important details about the early history of the subject were drawn from this volume. The wonderful library and archive of the Institute Mittag-Leffler are a treasure for anyone interested in mathematics at the turn of the 20th century; a particularly pleasant duty for me is to thank the institute for hosting me during my visit in September of 2009, which allowed me to verify various details in the early research literature, as well as providing me the company of many set theorists and model theorists who are interested in the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Universes for Category Theory
    Universes for category theory Zhen Lin Low 28 November 2014 Abstract The Grothendieck universe axiom asserts that every set is a member of some set-theoretic universe U that is itself a set. One can then work with entities like the category of all U-sets or even the category of all locally U-small categories, where U is an “arbitrary but fixed” universe, all without worrying about which set-theoretic operations one may le- gitimately apply to these entities. Unfortunately, as soon as one allows the possibility of changing U, one also has to face the fact that univer- sal constructions such as limits or adjoints or Kan extensions could, in principle, depend on the parameter U. We will prove this is not the case for adjoints of accessible functors between locally presentable categories (and hence, limits and Kan extensions), making explicit the idea that “bounded” constructions do not depend on the choice of U. Introduction In category theory it is often convenient to invoke a certain set-theoretic device commonly known as a ‘Grothendieck universe’, but we shall say simply ‘uni- verse’, so as to simplify exposition and proofs by eliminating various circum- arXiv:1304.5227v2 [math.CT] 28 Nov 2014 locutions involving cardinal bounds, proper classes etc. In [SGA 4a, Exposé I, §0], the authors adopt the following universe axiom: For each set x, there exists a universe U with x ∈ U. One then introduces a universe parameter U and speaks of U-sets, locally U- small categories, and so on, with the proviso that U is “arbitrary”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice. Cardinals and Cardinal Arithmetic
    Set Theory (MATH 6730) The Axiom of Choice. Cardinals and Cardinal Arithmetic 1. The Axiom of Choice We will discuss several statements that are equivalent (in ZF) to the Axiom of Choice. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set of nonempty sets. A choice function for A is a function f with domain A such that f(a) 2 a for all a 2 A. Theorem 1.2. In ZF the following statement are equivalent: AC (The Axiom of Choice) For any set A of pairwise disjoint, nonempty sets there exists a set C which has exactly one element from every set in A. CFP (Choice Function Principle) For any set A of nonempty sets there exists a choice function for A. WOP (Well-Ordering Principle) For every set B there exists a well-ordering (B; ≺). ZLm (Zorn's Lemma) If (D; <) is a partial order such that (∗) every subset of D that is linearly ordered by < has an upper bound in D,1 then (D; <) has a maximal element. Corollary 1.3. ZFC ` CFP, WOP, ZLm. Proof of Theorem 1.2. AC)CFP: Assume AC, and let A be a set of nonempty sets. By the Axiom of Replacement, A = ffag × a : a 2 Ag is a set. Hence, by AC, there is a set C which has exactly one element from every set in A. • C is a choice function for A. 1Condition (∗) for the empty subset of D is equivalent to requiring that D 6= ;. 1 2 CFP) WOP: Assume CFP, and let B be a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Set Theory
    Elements of set theory April 1, 2014 ii Contents 1 Zermelo{Fraenkel axiomatization 1 1.1 Historical context . 1 1.2 The language of the theory . 3 1.3 The most basic axioms . 4 1.4 Axiom of Infinity . 4 1.5 Axiom schema of Comprehension . 5 1.6 Functions . 6 1.7 Axiom of Choice . 7 1.8 Axiom schema of Replacement . 9 1.9 Axiom of Regularity . 9 2 Basic notions 11 2.1 Transitive sets . 11 2.2 Von Neumann's natural numbers . 11 2.3 Finite and infinite sets . 15 2.4 Cardinality . 17 2.5 Countable and uncountable sets . 19 3 Ordinals 21 3.1 Basic definitions . 21 3.2 Transfinite induction and recursion . 25 3.3 Applications with choice . 26 3.4 Applications without choice . 29 3.5 Cardinal numbers . 31 4 Descriptive set theory 35 4.1 Rational and real numbers . 35 4.2 Topological spaces . 37 4.3 Polish spaces . 39 4.4 Borel sets . 43 4.5 Analytic sets . 46 4.6 Lebesgue's mistake . 48 iii iv CONTENTS 5 Formal logic 51 5.1 Propositional logic . 51 5.1.1 Propositional logic: syntax . 51 5.1.2 Propositional logic: semantics . 52 5.1.3 Propositional logic: completeness . 53 5.2 First order logic . 56 5.2.1 First order logic: syntax . 56 5.2.2 First order logic: semantics . 59 5.2.3 Completeness theorem . 60 6 Model theory 67 6.1 Basic notions . 67 6.2 Ultraproducts and nonstandard analysis . 68 6.3 Quantifier elimination and the real closed fields .
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Set Theory, Part 2
    §11 Regular cardinals In what follows, κ , λ , µ , ν , ρ always denote cardinals. A cardinal κ is said to be regular if κ is infinite, and the union of fewer than κ sets, each of whose cardinality is less than κ , is of cardinality less than κ . In symbols: κ is regular if κ is infinite, and κ 〈 〉 ¡ κ for any set I with I ¡ < and any family Ai i∈I of sets such that Ai < ¤¦¥ £¢ κ for all i ∈ I , we have A ¡ < . i∈I i (Among finite cardinals, only 0 , 1 and 2 satisfy the displayed condition; it is not worth including these among the cardinals that we want to call "regular".) ℵ To see two examples, we know that 0 is regular: this is just to say that the union of finitely ℵ many finite sets is finite. We have also seen that 1 is regular: the meaning of this is that the union of countably many countable sets is countable. For future use, let us note the simple fact that the ordinal-least-upper-bound of any set of cardinals is a cardinal; for any set I , and cardinals λ for i∈I , lub λ is a cardinal. i i∈I i α Indeed, if α=lub λ , and β<α , then for some i∈I , β<λ . If we had β § , then by i∈I i i β λ ≤α β § λ λ < i , and Cantor-Bernstein, we would have i , contradicting the facts that i is β λ β α β ¨ α α a cardinal and < i .
    [Show full text]
  • Bounding 2D Functions by Products of 1D Functions 3
    BOUNDING 2D FUNCTIONS BY PRODUCTS OF 1D FUNCTIONS FRANC¸OIS DORAIS AND DAN HATHAWAY Abstract. Given sets X, Y and a regular cardinal µ, let Φ(X,Y,µ) be the statement that for any function f : X × Y → µ, there are functions g1 : X → µ and g2 : Y → µ such that for all (x, y) ∈ X × Y , f(x, y) ≤ max{g1(x),g2(y)}. In ZFC, the statement Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is false. However, we show the theory ZF + “the club filter on ω1 is normal” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is equiconsistent with ZFC + “there exists a measurable cardinal”. 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice allows us to define objects of size ω1 that do not behave like objects of size ω. For infinite cardinals λ1 and λ2, we introduce a statement Φ(λ1,λ2,ω) which implies in some sense that functions from λ1 × λ2 to ω behave like functions from ω × ω to ω. In Section 2 we show in ZFC that Φ(λ,ω,ω) is true iff λ < b, where b is the bounding number. We also show that in ZF that Φ(R,ω,ω) is false. In Section 3 we show that Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is false in ZF assuming ω1 is regular and there is an injection of ω1 into R. Thus, if ZF + “ω1 is regular” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) holds, then ω1 is inaccessible in every inner model that satisfies the Axiom of Choice. On the other hand consider AD, the Axiom of Determinacy. This is arXiv:1601.05454v3 [math.LO] 23 Jan 2020 an axiom which contradicts the Axiom of Choice.
    [Show full text]
  • 24. the Singular Cardinal Problem
    24. The Singular Cardinal Problem In this chapter we use combinatorial methods to prove theorems (in ZFC) on cardinal arithmetic of singular cardinals. We introduce a powerful theory of Shelah, the pcf theory, and apply the theory to present a most remarkable result of Shelah on powers of singular cardinals. The Galvin-Hajnal Theorem Following Silver’s Theorem 8.12 on singular cardinals of uncountable cofinal- ity, Galvin and Hajnal proved a related result: Theorem 24.1 (Galvin-Hajnal [1975]). Let ℵα be a strong limit singular ℵ |α| + cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Then 2 α < ℵγ where γ =(2 ) . Note that the theorem gives a nontrivial information only if ℵα is not a fixed point of the aleph function. In order to simplify the notation, we consider the special case α = ω1.The following lemma implies the theorem (as in the proof of Silver’s Theorem). Two functions f and g on ω1 are almost disjoint if {α : f(α)=g(α)} is at most countable. ℵ ℵ 1 ℵ Lemma 24.2. Assume that α < ω1 for all α<ω1.LetF be an almost disjoint family of functions F ⊂ Aα α<ω1 ℵ | | ℵ | | ℵ 1 + such that Aα < ω1 for all α<ω1.Then F < γ where γ =(2 ) . Proof. We first introduce the following relation among functions ϕ : ω1 → ω1 (24.1) ϕ<ψ if and only if {α<ω1 : ϕ(α) ≥ ψ(α)} is nonstationary. Since the closed unbounded filter is σ-complete, it follows that there is no infinite descending sequence ϕ0 >ϕ1 >ϕ2 >...
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinal Arithmetic: the Silver and Galvin-Hajnal Theorems
    B. Zwetsloot Cardinal arithmetic: The Silver and Galvin-Hajnal Theorems Bachelor thesis 22 June 2018 Thesis supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Leiden University Mathematical Institute Contents Introduction 1 1 Prerequisites 2 1.1 Cofinality . .2 1.2 Stationary sets . .5 2 Silver's theorem 8 3 The Galvin-Hajnal theorem 12 4 Appendix: Ordinal and cardinal numbers 17 References 21 Introduction When introduced to university-level mathematics for the first time, one of the first subjects to come up is basic set theory, as it is a necessary basis to understanding mathematics. In particular, the concept of cardinality of sets, being a measure of their size, is learned early. But what exactly are these cardinalities for objects? They turn out to be an extension of the natural numbers, originally introduced by Cantor: The cardinal numbers. These being called numbers, it is not strange to see that some standard arithmetical op- erations, like addition, multiplication and exponentiation have extensions to the cardinal numbers. The first two of these turn out to be rather uninteresting when generalized, as for infinite cardinals κ, λ we have κ + λ = κ · λ = max(κ, λ). However, exponentiation turns out to be a lot more complex, with statements like the (Generalized) Continuum Hypothesis that are independent of ZFC. As the body of results on the topic of cardinal exponentiation grew in the 60's and early 70's, set theorists became more and more convinced that except for a relatively basic in- equality, no real grip could be gained on cardinal exponentation. Jack Silver unexpectedly reversed this trend in 1974, when he showed that some cardinals, like @!1 , cannot be the first cardinal where GCH fails.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretical Background 1.1 Ordinals and Cardinals
    Set-Theoretical Background 11 February 2019 Our set-theoretical framework will be the Zermelo{Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of choice (ZFC): • Axiom of Extensionality. If X and Y have the same elements, then X = Y . • Axiom of Pairing. For all a and b there exists a set fa; bg that contains exactly a and b. • Axiom Schema of Separation. If P is a property (with a parameter p), then for all X and p there exists a set Y = fx 2 X : P (x; p)g that contains all those x 2 X that have the property P . • Axiom of Union. For any X there exists a set Y = S X, the union of all elements of X. • Axiom of Power Set. For any X there exists a set Y = P (X), the set of all subsets of X. • Axiom of Infinity. There exists an infinite set. • Axiom Schema of Replacement. If a class F is a function, then for any X there exists a set Y = F (X) = fF (x): x 2 Xg. • Axiom of Regularity. Every nonempty set has a minimal element for the membership relation. • Axiom of Choice. Every family of nonempty sets has a choice function. 1.1 Ordinals and cardinals A set X is well ordered if it is equipped with a total order relation such that every nonempty subset S ⊆ X has a smallest element. The statement that every set admits a well ordering is equivalent to the axiom of choice. A set X is transitive if every element of an element of X is an element of X.
    [Show full text]
  • 3. Cardinal Numbers
    3. Cardinal Numbers Cardinality Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal), (3.1) |X| = |Y |, if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X onto Y . The relation (3.1) is an equivalence relation. We assume that we can assign to each set X its cardinal number |X| so that two sets are assigned the same cardinal just in case they satisfy condition (3.1). Cardinal numbers can be defined either using the Axiom of Regularity (via equivalence classes of (3.1)), or using the Axiom of Choice. In this chapter we define cardinal numbers of well-orderable sets; as it follows from the Axiom of Choice that every set can be well-ordered, this defines cardinals in ZFC. We recall that a set X is finite if |X| = |n| for some n ∈ N;thenX is said to have n elements. Clearly, |n| = |m| if and only if n = m,andsowe define finite cardinals as natural numbers, i.e., |n| = n for all n ∈ N. The ordering of cardinal numbers is defined as follows: (3.2) |X|≤|Y | if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X into Y . We also define the strict ordering |X| < |Y | to mean that |X|≤|Y | while |X| = |Y |.Therelation≤ in (3.2) is clearly transitive. Theorem 3.2 below shows that it is indeed a par- tial ordering, and it follows from the Axiom of Choice that the ordering is linear—any two sets are comparable in this ordering. The concept of cardinality is central to the study of infinite sets.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing
    The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing Connor Lockhart December 2018 Abstract In this paper we introduce the problem of the continuum hypothesis and its solution via Cohen forcing. First, we introduce the basics of first order logic and standard ZFC set theory before elaborating on ordinals, cardinals and the forcing concept. The motivation of this paper is exposi- tory and should be approachable for anyone familiar with first order logic and set theory. Contents 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis 2 2 First Order Logic 2 2.1 Formal Languages . 2 2.2 Model Theory . 3 3 Set Theory and the ZFC axioms 6 3.1 List and Motivation of the Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms . 6 4 Ordinals and Cardinals 9 4.1 Orderings and Ordinal numbers . 9 4.2 Ordinal Arithmetic . 10 4.3 Cardinal Numbers . 11 5 Forcing 11 5.1 Tools of Forcing . 12 5.2 Useful Forcing Lemmas . 15 6 Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis 16 7 Acknowledgments 17 1 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis The continuum hypothesis (also referred to as CH) was first formulated in 1878 by Georg Cantor following his work on the foundations of set theory. Its for- mulation is often stated as There is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. This can also be reformulated to state that the successor cardinal to @0 is the cardinality of the reals. Such was suspected, but not proven, by Cantor and his contemporaries. The first major advance on the problem was presented by G¨odelin 1940 showing its consistency with ZFC axioms, and independence was finally shown in 1963 by Cohen.
    [Show full text]