Bounding 2D Functions by Products of 1D Functions 3

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bounding 2D Functions by Products of 1D Functions 3 BOUNDING 2D FUNCTIONS BY PRODUCTS OF 1D FUNCTIONS FRANC¸OIS DORAIS AND DAN HATHAWAY Abstract. Given sets X, Y and a regular cardinal µ, let Φ(X,Y,µ) be the statement that for any function f : X × Y → µ, there are functions g1 : X → µ and g2 : Y → µ such that for all (x, y) ∈ X × Y , f(x, y) ≤ max{g1(x),g2(y)}. In ZFC, the statement Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is false. However, we show the theory ZF + “the club filter on ω1 is normal” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is equiconsistent with ZFC + “there exists a measurable cardinal”. 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice allows us to define objects of size ω1 that do not behave like objects of size ω. For infinite cardinals λ1 and λ2, we introduce a statement Φ(λ1,λ2,ω) which implies in some sense that functions from λ1 × λ2 to ω behave like functions from ω × ω to ω. In Section 2 we show in ZFC that Φ(λ,ω,ω) is true iff λ < b, where b is the bounding number. We also show that in ZF that Φ(R,ω,ω) is false. In Section 3 we show that Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is false in ZF assuming ω1 is regular and there is an injection of ω1 into R. Thus, if ZF + “ω1 is regular” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) holds, then ω1 is inaccessible in every inner model that satisfies the Axiom of Choice. On the other hand consider AD, the Axiom of Determinacy. This is arXiv:1601.05454v3 [math.LO] 23 Jan 2020 an axiom which contradicts the Axiom of Choice. It imposes regularity properties on both subsets of R and on bounded subsets of Θ, which is the smallest ordinal that R cannot be surjected onto. AD implies in some sense that subsets of ω1 behave like subsets of ω. Contrasting with the Axiom of Choice, in Section 4 show that AD implies Φ(ω1,ω1,ω). In fact, we show that ZF+DC + “ω1 is a measurable cardinal” implies Φ(ω1,ω1,ω). In Section 5, we aim to show that ZF+Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) implies that there are inner models with large cardinals. We show that ZF + “the club filter on ω1 is normal” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) implies 1) every real has a sharp and 2) there is an inner model with a measurable cardinal. Combining 1 2 FRANC¸OISDORAISANDDANHATHAWAY this with Section 4, we have that the theory ZF + “the club filter on ω1 is normal” + Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) is equiconsistent with ZFC + “there is a measurable cardinal”. We will use the following concepts several times: Definition 1.1. An inner model is a transitive model of ZF which contains all the ordinals. L is the smallest inner model. Definition 1.2. Given a set of ordinals A ⊆ Ord, L[A] is the smallest inner model N such that A ∈ N. In general, given any inner model M and a set of ordinals A, M[A] is the smallest inner model N such that M ⊆ N and A ∈ N. If A is a set of ordinals, then L[A] satisfies the Axiom of Choice. We will need the following strengthening (see [5] page 451 for a proof): Proposition 1.3. Let M be an inner model. Let A be a set of ordinals. Then M[A] exists. If moreover M satisfies the Axiom of Choice, then so does M[A]. 1.1. Acknowledgments. We would like to thank Cody Dance and Trevor Wilson for discussions relating to this paper, especially con- cerning the behavior of sets of ordinals assuming AD. I would also like to thank Phil Tosteson who originally asked about the status of Φ(λ1,λ2,ω). 2. Definition and the Bounding Number Definition 2.1. For sets X,Y and an infinite regular cardinal µ, let Φ(X,Y,µ) be the statement that whenever f : X × Y → µ, there are functions g1 : X → µ and g2 : Y → µ such that for all (x, y) ∈ X × Y , f(x, y) ≤ max{g1(x),g2(y)}. We will mostly consider the case that X and Y are cardinals (which are ordinals). When this happens, without loss of generality λ1,λ2 ≥ µ. In this section we will consider arbitrary µ, but for the rest of the paper we will focus on the µ = ω case. Theorem 2.2. Let µ be a regular cardinal. Let X be a set. Then Φ(X,µ,µ) holds iff each family hfx : x ∈ Xi of functions from µ to µ is eventually dominated (mod <µ) by some single function. Proof. First assume every such family indexed by X can be eventually dominated by a single function from µ to µ. Fix f : X × µ → µ. Let g2 : µ → µ be such that for each x ∈ X, the set Sx := {y<µ : f(x, y) > g2(y)} has size < µ. Let g1 : X → µ be such that for each x ∈ X, g1(x) ≥ sup{f(x, y): y ∈ Sx}. The functions g1 and g2 work. BOUNDING 2D FUNCTIONS BY PRODUCTS OF 1D FUNCTIONS 3 For the other direction, assume there is a family indexed by X of functions from µ to µ that cannot be eventually dominated by a single function. Using such a family, let f : X × µ → µ be such that the functions of the form y 7→ f(x, y) cannot be eventually dominated by a single function from µ to µ. By possibly increasing the values of the function f, we may assume that whenever x ∈ X and Y ∈ [µ]µ, the set f“{x} × Y is unbounded below µ. Now, consider any g2 : µ → µ. By hypothesis, fix some x ∈ X such that g2 does not eventually dominate the function y 7→ f(x, y). That is, Sx := {y ∈ µ : f(x, y) >g2(y)} is in µ [µ] , so f“{x} × Sx is unbounded below µ. Hence, there is no α<µ such that for all y<µ, f(x, y) ≤ max{α,g2(y)}, so there can be no function g1 which works (because no value of α = g1(x) works). Every family of size µ of functions from µ to µ is eventually domi- nated by a single function. On the other hand, there exists a family indexed by µ2 of functions from µ to µ that cannot be eventually dom- inated by any single function. This gives us the following: Corollary 2.3. (ZF) Let µ be a regular cardinal. Then Φ(µ,µ,µ) holds but Φ(µ2,µ,µ) does not. Corollary 2.4. (ZF) Let µ be a regular cardinal. Assume there is no injection of µ+ into µ2. Then for any cardinal λ (that is an ordinal), Φ(λ,µ,µ) holds. Proof. Any size λ family of functions from µ to µ has at most µ distinct members, and hence the family can be eventually dominated by a single function. Recall that in ZFC, b(µ) is the cardinality of the smallest family of functions from µ to µ that cannot be eventually dominated by a single function. See [1] for more on b(ω). Corollary 2.5. (ZFC) Let µ be a regular cardinal. Let λ be a cardinal. Then Φ(λ,µ,µ) holds iff λ< b(µ). 3. First Countable Topologies By Corollary 2.3, Φ(R,ω,ω) fails in ZF, and hence so does Φ(R,ω1,ω) and Φ(R, R,ω). In this section, we will show in ZF that if ω1 is regular and there is an injection of ω1 into R, then Φ(ω1,ω1,ω) fails as well. Given a topological space X and a point x ∈ X, we call B ⊆ P(X)a neighborhood basis for x iff 1) every U ∈ B is open and contains x and 2) for every open W ∋ x, there is some U ∈ B such that U ⊆ W . We call X first-countable iff every x ∈ X has a countable neighborhood basis. 4 FRANC¸OISDORAISANDDANHATHAWAY Definition 3.1. Let X be a topological space. We call X uniformly first-countable iff there is a function F with domain X such that for each x ∈ X, F (x) is a sequence hUx,n : n<ωi such that {Ux,n : n<ω} is a neighborhood basis for x. Assuming the Axiom of Choice, a topological space is first-countable iff it is uniformly first-countable. Recall that a topological space X is T1 iff for any distinct x, y ∈ X, there is an open set which contains x but not y. Theorem 3.2. (ZF) Let X be a T1 and uniformly first-countable topo- logical space. Let Y ⊆ X and assume Φ(X,Y,ω). Then we may write Y = n<ω Yn where each Yn is a closed discrete subset of Y and Y0 ⊆ Y1 ⊆ .... S Proof. Let the function F witness that Y is uniformly first-countable, where F (x) = hUx,n : n<ωi. Assume without loss of generality that for each x ∈ X, we have Ux,0 ⊇ Ux,1 ⊇ .... Let f : X × Y → ω be defined by min{n<ω : y 6∈ U } if x =6 y, f(x, y) := x,n (0 if x = y. Thus for all distinct x ∈ X and y ∈ Y , y 6∈ Ux,f(x,y). By Φ(X,Y,ω), there are functions g1 : X → ω and g2 : Y → ω such that f(x, y) ≤ max{g1(x),g2(y)} for all distinct x ∈ X and y ∈ Y .
Recommended publications
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • Singular Cardinals: from Hausdorff's Gaps to Shelah's Pcf Theory
    SINGULAR CARDINALS: FROM HAUSDORFF’S GAPS TO SHELAH’S PCF THEORY Menachem Kojman 1 PREFACE The mathematical subject of singular cardinals is young and many of the math- ematicians who made important contributions to it are still active. This makes writing a history of singular cardinals a somewhat riskier mission than writing the history of, say, Babylonian arithmetic. Yet exactly the discussions with some of the people who created the 20th century history of singular cardinals made the writing of this article fascinating. I am indebted to Moti Gitik, Ronald Jensen, Istv´an Juh´asz, Menachem Magidor and Saharon Shelah for the time and effort they spent on helping me understand the development of the subject and for many illuminations they provided. A lot of what I thought about the history of singular cardinals had to change as a result of these discussions. Special thanks are due to Istv´an Juh´asz, for his patient reading for me from the Russian text of Alexandrov and Urysohn’s Memoirs, to Salma Kuhlmann, who directed me to the definition of singular cardinals in Hausdorff’s writing, and to Stefan Geschke, who helped me with the German texts I needed to read and sometimes translate. I am also indebted to the Hausdorff project in Bonn, for publishing a beautiful annotated volume of Hausdorff’s monumental Grundz¨uge der Mengenlehre and for Springer Verlag, for rushing to me a free copy of this book; many important details about the early history of the subject were drawn from this volume. The wonderful library and archive of the Institute Mittag-Leffler are a treasure for anyone interested in mathematics at the turn of the 20th century; a particularly pleasant duty for me is to thank the institute for hosting me during my visit in September of 2009, which allowed me to verify various details in the early research literature, as well as providing me the company of many set theorists and model theorists who are interested in the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Universes for Category Theory
    Universes for category theory Zhen Lin Low 28 November 2014 Abstract The Grothendieck universe axiom asserts that every set is a member of some set-theoretic universe U that is itself a set. One can then work with entities like the category of all U-sets or even the category of all locally U-small categories, where U is an “arbitrary but fixed” universe, all without worrying about which set-theoretic operations one may le- gitimately apply to these entities. Unfortunately, as soon as one allows the possibility of changing U, one also has to face the fact that univer- sal constructions such as limits or adjoints or Kan extensions could, in principle, depend on the parameter U. We will prove this is not the case for adjoints of accessible functors between locally presentable categories (and hence, limits and Kan extensions), making explicit the idea that “bounded” constructions do not depend on the choice of U. Introduction In category theory it is often convenient to invoke a certain set-theoretic device commonly known as a ‘Grothendieck universe’, but we shall say simply ‘uni- verse’, so as to simplify exposition and proofs by eliminating various circum- arXiv:1304.5227v2 [math.CT] 28 Nov 2014 locutions involving cardinal bounds, proper classes etc. In [SGA 4a, Exposé I, §0], the authors adopt the following universe axiom: For each set x, there exists a universe U with x ∈ U. One then introduces a universe parameter U and speaks of U-sets, locally U- small categories, and so on, with the proviso that U is “arbitrary”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice. Cardinals and Cardinal Arithmetic
    Set Theory (MATH 6730) The Axiom of Choice. Cardinals and Cardinal Arithmetic 1. The Axiom of Choice We will discuss several statements that are equivalent (in ZF) to the Axiom of Choice. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set of nonempty sets. A choice function for A is a function f with domain A such that f(a) 2 a for all a 2 A. Theorem 1.2. In ZF the following statement are equivalent: AC (The Axiom of Choice) For any set A of pairwise disjoint, nonempty sets there exists a set C which has exactly one element from every set in A. CFP (Choice Function Principle) For any set A of nonempty sets there exists a choice function for A. WOP (Well-Ordering Principle) For every set B there exists a well-ordering (B; ≺). ZLm (Zorn's Lemma) If (D; <) is a partial order such that (∗) every subset of D that is linearly ordered by < has an upper bound in D,1 then (D; <) has a maximal element. Corollary 1.3. ZFC ` CFP, WOP, ZLm. Proof of Theorem 1.2. AC)CFP: Assume AC, and let A be a set of nonempty sets. By the Axiom of Replacement, A = ffag × a : a 2 Ag is a set. Hence, by AC, there is a set C which has exactly one element from every set in A. • C is a choice function for A. 1Condition (∗) for the empty subset of D is equivalent to requiring that D 6= ;. 1 2 CFP) WOP: Assume CFP, and let B be a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Set Theory
    Elements of set theory April 1, 2014 ii Contents 1 Zermelo{Fraenkel axiomatization 1 1.1 Historical context . 1 1.2 The language of the theory . 3 1.3 The most basic axioms . 4 1.4 Axiom of Infinity . 4 1.5 Axiom schema of Comprehension . 5 1.6 Functions . 6 1.7 Axiom of Choice . 7 1.8 Axiom schema of Replacement . 9 1.9 Axiom of Regularity . 9 2 Basic notions 11 2.1 Transitive sets . 11 2.2 Von Neumann's natural numbers . 11 2.3 Finite and infinite sets . 15 2.4 Cardinality . 17 2.5 Countable and uncountable sets . 19 3 Ordinals 21 3.1 Basic definitions . 21 3.2 Transfinite induction and recursion . 25 3.3 Applications with choice . 26 3.4 Applications without choice . 29 3.5 Cardinal numbers . 31 4 Descriptive set theory 35 4.1 Rational and real numbers . 35 4.2 Topological spaces . 37 4.3 Polish spaces . 39 4.4 Borel sets . 43 4.5 Analytic sets . 46 4.6 Lebesgue's mistake . 48 iii iv CONTENTS 5 Formal logic 51 5.1 Propositional logic . 51 5.1.1 Propositional logic: syntax . 51 5.1.2 Propositional logic: semantics . 52 5.1.3 Propositional logic: completeness . 53 5.2 First order logic . 56 5.2.1 First order logic: syntax . 56 5.2.2 First order logic: semantics . 59 5.2.3 Completeness theorem . 60 6 Model theory 67 6.1 Basic notions . 67 6.2 Ultraproducts and nonstandard analysis . 68 6.3 Quantifier elimination and the real closed fields .
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Set Theory, Part 2
    §11 Regular cardinals In what follows, κ , λ , µ , ν , ρ always denote cardinals. A cardinal κ is said to be regular if κ is infinite, and the union of fewer than κ sets, each of whose cardinality is less than κ , is of cardinality less than κ . In symbols: κ is regular if κ is infinite, and κ 〈 〉 ¡ κ for any set I with I ¡ < and any family Ai i∈I of sets such that Ai < ¤¦¥ £¢ κ for all i ∈ I , we have A ¡ < . i∈I i (Among finite cardinals, only 0 , 1 and 2 satisfy the displayed condition; it is not worth including these among the cardinals that we want to call "regular".) ℵ To see two examples, we know that 0 is regular: this is just to say that the union of finitely ℵ many finite sets is finite. We have also seen that 1 is regular: the meaning of this is that the union of countably many countable sets is countable. For future use, let us note the simple fact that the ordinal-least-upper-bound of any set of cardinals is a cardinal; for any set I , and cardinals λ for i∈I , lub λ is a cardinal. i i∈I i α Indeed, if α=lub λ , and β<α , then for some i∈I , β<λ . If we had β § , then by i∈I i i β λ ≤α β § λ λ < i , and Cantor-Bernstein, we would have i , contradicting the facts that i is β λ β α β ¨ α α a cardinal and < i .
    [Show full text]
  • 24. the Singular Cardinal Problem
    24. The Singular Cardinal Problem In this chapter we use combinatorial methods to prove theorems (in ZFC) on cardinal arithmetic of singular cardinals. We introduce a powerful theory of Shelah, the pcf theory, and apply the theory to present a most remarkable result of Shelah on powers of singular cardinals. The Galvin-Hajnal Theorem Following Silver’s Theorem 8.12 on singular cardinals of uncountable cofinal- ity, Galvin and Hajnal proved a related result: Theorem 24.1 (Galvin-Hajnal [1975]). Let ℵα be a strong limit singular ℵ |α| + cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Then 2 α < ℵγ where γ =(2 ) . Note that the theorem gives a nontrivial information only if ℵα is not a fixed point of the aleph function. In order to simplify the notation, we consider the special case α = ω1.The following lemma implies the theorem (as in the proof of Silver’s Theorem). Two functions f and g on ω1 are almost disjoint if {α : f(α)=g(α)} is at most countable. ℵ ℵ 1 ℵ Lemma 24.2. Assume that α < ω1 for all α<ω1.LetF be an almost disjoint family of functions F ⊂ Aα α<ω1 ℵ | | ℵ | | ℵ 1 + such that Aα < ω1 for all α<ω1.Then F < γ where γ =(2 ) . Proof. We first introduce the following relation among functions ϕ : ω1 → ω1 (24.1) ϕ<ψ if and only if {α<ω1 : ϕ(α) ≥ ψ(α)} is nonstationary. Since the closed unbounded filter is σ-complete, it follows that there is no infinite descending sequence ϕ0 >ϕ1 >ϕ2 >...
    [Show full text]
  • Cardinal Arithmetic: the Silver and Galvin-Hajnal Theorems
    B. Zwetsloot Cardinal arithmetic: The Silver and Galvin-Hajnal Theorems Bachelor thesis 22 June 2018 Thesis supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Leiden University Mathematical Institute Contents Introduction 1 1 Prerequisites 2 1.1 Cofinality . .2 1.2 Stationary sets . .5 2 Silver's theorem 8 3 The Galvin-Hajnal theorem 12 4 Appendix: Ordinal and cardinal numbers 17 References 21 Introduction When introduced to university-level mathematics for the first time, one of the first subjects to come up is basic set theory, as it is a necessary basis to understanding mathematics. In particular, the concept of cardinality of sets, being a measure of their size, is learned early. But what exactly are these cardinalities for objects? They turn out to be an extension of the natural numbers, originally introduced by Cantor: The cardinal numbers. These being called numbers, it is not strange to see that some standard arithmetical op- erations, like addition, multiplication and exponentiation have extensions to the cardinal numbers. The first two of these turn out to be rather uninteresting when generalized, as for infinite cardinals κ, λ we have κ + λ = κ · λ = max(κ, λ). However, exponentiation turns out to be a lot more complex, with statements like the (Generalized) Continuum Hypothesis that are independent of ZFC. As the body of results on the topic of cardinal exponentiation grew in the 60's and early 70's, set theorists became more and more convinced that except for a relatively basic in- equality, no real grip could be gained on cardinal exponentation. Jack Silver unexpectedly reversed this trend in 1974, when he showed that some cardinals, like @!1 , cannot be the first cardinal where GCH fails.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretical Background 1.1 Ordinals and Cardinals
    Set-Theoretical Background 11 February 2019 Our set-theoretical framework will be the Zermelo{Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of choice (ZFC): • Axiom of Extensionality. If X and Y have the same elements, then X = Y . • Axiom of Pairing. For all a and b there exists a set fa; bg that contains exactly a and b. • Axiom Schema of Separation. If P is a property (with a parameter p), then for all X and p there exists a set Y = fx 2 X : P (x; p)g that contains all those x 2 X that have the property P . • Axiom of Union. For any X there exists a set Y = S X, the union of all elements of X. • Axiom of Power Set. For any X there exists a set Y = P (X), the set of all subsets of X. • Axiom of Infinity. There exists an infinite set. • Axiom Schema of Replacement. If a class F is a function, then for any X there exists a set Y = F (X) = fF (x): x 2 Xg. • Axiom of Regularity. Every nonempty set has a minimal element for the membership relation. • Axiom of Choice. Every family of nonempty sets has a choice function. 1.1 Ordinals and cardinals A set X is well ordered if it is equipped with a total order relation such that every nonempty subset S ⊆ X has a smallest element. The statement that every set admits a well ordering is equivalent to the axiom of choice. A set X is transitive if every element of an element of X is an element of X.
    [Show full text]
  • 3. Cardinal Numbers
    3. Cardinal Numbers Cardinality Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal), (3.1) |X| = |Y |, if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X onto Y . The relation (3.1) is an equivalence relation. We assume that we can assign to each set X its cardinal number |X| so that two sets are assigned the same cardinal just in case they satisfy condition (3.1). Cardinal numbers can be defined either using the Axiom of Regularity (via equivalence classes of (3.1)), or using the Axiom of Choice. In this chapter we define cardinal numbers of well-orderable sets; as it follows from the Axiom of Choice that every set can be well-ordered, this defines cardinals in ZFC. We recall that a set X is finite if |X| = |n| for some n ∈ N;thenX is said to have n elements. Clearly, |n| = |m| if and only if n = m,andsowe define finite cardinals as natural numbers, i.e., |n| = n for all n ∈ N. The ordering of cardinal numbers is defined as follows: (3.2) |X|≤|Y | if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X into Y . We also define the strict ordering |X| < |Y | to mean that |X|≤|Y | while |X| = |Y |.Therelation≤ in (3.2) is clearly transitive. Theorem 3.2 below shows that it is indeed a par- tial ordering, and it follows from the Axiom of Choice that the ordering is linear—any two sets are comparable in this ordering. The concept of cardinality is central to the study of infinite sets.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing
    The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing Connor Lockhart December 2018 Abstract In this paper we introduce the problem of the continuum hypothesis and its solution via Cohen forcing. First, we introduce the basics of first order logic and standard ZFC set theory before elaborating on ordinals, cardinals and the forcing concept. The motivation of this paper is exposi- tory and should be approachable for anyone familiar with first order logic and set theory. Contents 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis 2 2 First Order Logic 2 2.1 Formal Languages . 2 2.2 Model Theory . 3 3 Set Theory and the ZFC axioms 6 3.1 List and Motivation of the Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms . 6 4 Ordinals and Cardinals 9 4.1 Orderings and Ordinal numbers . 9 4.2 Ordinal Arithmetic . 10 4.3 Cardinal Numbers . 11 5 Forcing 11 5.1 Tools of Forcing . 12 5.2 Useful Forcing Lemmas . 15 6 Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis 16 7 Acknowledgments 17 1 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis The continuum hypothesis (also referred to as CH) was first formulated in 1878 by Georg Cantor following his work on the foundations of set theory. Its for- mulation is often stated as There is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. This can also be reformulated to state that the successor cardinal to @0 is the cardinality of the reals. Such was suspected, but not proven, by Cantor and his contemporaries. The first major advance on the problem was presented by G¨odelin 1940 showing its consistency with ZFC axioms, and independence was finally shown in 1963 by Cohen.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Set Theory
    AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss November 21, 2014 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 23 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 29 4 The Natural Numbers 37 5 The Ordinal Numbers 47 6 Relations and Orderings 59 7 Cardinality 69 8 What's So Real About The Real Numbers? 79 9 Ultrafilters Are Useful 87 3 4 CONTENTS 10 The Universe 97 11 Reflection 103 12 Elementary Submodels 123 13 Constructibility 139 14 Appendices 155 .1 The Axioms of ZFC . 155 .2 Tentative Axioms . 156 CONTENTS 5 Preface These notes for a graduate course in set theory are on their way to be- coming a book. They originated as handwritten notes in a course at the University of Toronto given by Prof. William Weiss. Cynthia Church pro- duced the first electronic copy in December 2002. James Talmage Adams produced a major revision in February 2005. The manuscript has seen many changes since then, often due to generous comments by students, each of whom I here thank. Chapters 1 to 11 are now close to final form. Chapters 12 and 13 are quite readable, but should not be considered as a final draft. One more chapter will be added. 6 CONTENTS Chapter 0 Introduction Set Theory is the true study of infinity. This alone assures the subject of a place prominent in human culture. But even more, Set Theory is the milieu in which mathematics takes place today. As such, it is expected to provide a firm foundation for all the rest of mathematics.
    [Show full text]