9674 RTAM 09 Davidson

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

9674 RTAM 09 Davidson The Vita Beata: Ambrose, De Officiis 2.1-21 And the Synthesis of Classical and Christian Thought in the Late Fourth Century In his Sermo 150, Augustine argues that the desire to attain the vita beata has been the motivation for all types of philosophy, and that it is also the reason that people would give if asked why they became Christians; the quest is common to all human beings, whether good or evil. Appetitio…beatae vitae philosophis Christianisque communis est1. The truth of Augustine’s claims is illustrated in a variety of Latin Christian works from the fourth century, which take up the traditional philosophical theme of hap- piness and the summum bonum. Lactantius relates the highest good to the immortality of the soul, and calls upon his readers to find their destiny by devoting themselves to the worship of the true God; the worship of God is the greatest virtue, and it wins the blessedness of eternal reward2. Augustine’s De beata vita, written at Cassiciacum in November, 386, and dedicated to the cultured neo-Platonist, Manlius Theodorus, presents a blend of Plotinian thought with Catholic orthodoxy: the blessed life con- sists in the knowledge of the triune God3. Ambrose’s De Iacob et vita beata, based upon sermons to which Augustine may well have listened earlier in 386, concentrates on the virtues of blessedness as illustrated in the narratives of the Maccabees and of the patriarch Jacob. Ambrose offers an amalgam of Stoic and neo-Platonist sentiments as he sketches the character of the per- son who proceeds towards eternal fellowship with God by ratio- nal control of his passions, detachment from his external circum- stances, and finally, like the faithful martyr, remaining steadfast 1. Augustine, Serm. 150.4. Augustine goes on to present Christ as the way to blessedness: haec est doctrina Christianorum, non plane conferenda, sed incom- parabiliter praeferenda, doctrinis philosophorum, immunditiae Epicureorum, superbiae Stoicorum (150.10). 2. Lactantius, Inst. 3.7ff.; 7. 3. See the edition of J. Doignon, Oeuvres de saint Augustin: Dialogues philosophiques: De beata vita — la vie heureuse (Bibliothèque augustinienne 4.1, Paris 1986). 200 RECHERCHES DE THÉOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MÉDIÉVALE as he faces death4. All these works have received justifiable atten- tion for their assimilation of major points from classical philoso- phy. However, one striking example of the way in which classi- cal perspectives and biblical teaching coexist in a fourth-century Christian mind has been relatively neglected by scholars: namely, the opening section of book 2 of Ambrose’s De Officiis (2.1-21). The passage repays careful study as an illustration of Christian humanism at work5. Ambrose models his De Officiis on Cicero’s work of the same name, which is in turn based upon the writing of the middle Stoic Panaetius, with some further influence from Posidonius and Heca- ton of Rhodes6. Ambrose follows the basic structure of Cicero’s three books, on the honourable, the expedient, and the relationship between the two. As Cicero wrote to his son Marcus, and beyond him to the ambitious young men who were witnessing the collapse of the Republic, so Ambrose addresses his spiritual ‘sons’, the younger clergy of Milan, setting out ideals of moral conduct which would foster the influence of the church in North Italian 4. On the composition of the work, see G. Nauroy, ‘La méthode de composi- tion d’Ambroise de Milan et la structure du De Iacob et vita beata,’ in Y.-M. Duval (ed.), Ambroise de Milan. XVIe centenaire de son élection épiscopale. Dix études (Paris 1974), pp. 115-153. On the neo-Platonism, see A. Solignac, ‘Nou- veaux parallèles entre saint Ambroise et Plotin: Le “De Iacob et vita beata“ et le Peri eudaimonias (Ennéade I,iv ),’ Archives de philosophie 19 (1956), pp. 148- 156. 5. I use the Budé text edited by M. Testard, Saint Ambroise, Les Devoirs 1-2 (Paris 1984, 1992). 2.1-21 has been studied by P.J. Couvée, Vita beata en vita aeterna. Een onderzoek naar de ontwikkeling van het begrip “vita beata” naast en tegenover “vita aeterna” bij Lactantius, Ambrosius en Augustinus, onder invloed van de romeinsche Stoa (Baarn 1947), pp. 131-173, esp. pp. 155ff., along with Iac. Couvée’s treatment is, however, far from comprehensive, and fails to note the neo-Platonist influences which sit alongside the Stoicism in Ambrose. Some details are also noted in J.E. Niederhuber, Die Lehre des hl. Ambrosius vom Reiche Gottes auf Erden. Eine patristische Studie (Mainz 1904), pp. 143- 159, and esp. pp. 191-204; F.H. Dudden, The Life and Times of St. Ambrose 2 (Oxford 1935), pp. 514-519 (again missing the neo-Platonism). See too: R. Holte, Béatitude et sagesse: saint Augustin et le problème de la fin de l’homme dans la philosophie ancienne (Paris 1962), pp. 63-70, 165-176, 193-231; E. Dassmann, Die Frömmigkeit des Kirchenvaters Ambrosius von Mailand: Quellen und Entfaltung (Münster 1965), pp. 261-267. 6. On Cicero’s sources, see M. Testard, Cicéron, Les Devoirs 1 (Paris 1965), pp. 25-49; on the work generally, P. Mackendrick, The Philosophical Books of Cicero (London 1989), pp. 232-257. THE VITA BEATA 201 society, where challenges were being experienced from both pagan revivalism and Arian doctrinal deviancy (1.24). Ambrose’s work almost certainly consists of a number of addresses to these clerics on Ciceronian ethical topics, which have subsequently been slightly revised and collected for publication as a treatise on eccle- siastical conduct7. Ambrose’s introduction to book 2 does not parallel a similar section in Cicero. In Off. 2.1-8, Cicero introduces the theme of expediency, and defends the study of philosophy as he has been pursuing it in his recent writings; he also seeks to defend his posi- tion as one who sympathizes with Academic scepticism, pointing to the pragmatic epistemology proposed in his Academica, where it is argued that we can act on the basis of probability, once both sides of a question have been examined. Cicero has the phrase ad bene beateque vivendum in Off. 2.6, as he describes the practical quest of the philosophers, but he says no more about the vita beata in this section (he had already dealt with the subject at a popular level in Stoic Paradoxes 6-19, and in a thorough fashion in De Finibus and in Tusculan Disputations 5). Ambrose evokes Cicero at the beginning and end of his discussion, in 2.1 (superiore libro de officiis tractavimus, quae convenire honestati arbitraremur: cf. Cicero, Off. 2.1) and in 2.21 (sed iam ad proposita pergamus: cf. Cicero, Off. 2.8), and he mentions honestas or the honestum in 2.1,3-4,8, but otherwise there is no allusion to Ciceronian lan- guage, not even to the theme of expediency which is to occupy 7. So, int. al., M. Ihm, ‘Studia Ambrosiana,’ Jahrbücher für klassisches Philologie suppl. bd. 17 (1890), p. 27; R. Thamin, Saint Ambroise et la morale chrétienne au IVe siècle. Etude comparée des traités “Des Devoirs” de Cicéron et de saint Ambroise (Paris 1895), pp. 216-217; Th. Schmidt, Ambrosius, sein Werk de Officiis Libri III und die Stoa (Augsburg 1897), pp. 12-13; O. Barden- hewer, Geschichte der altchristlichen Literatur 3 (Freiburg 1912), p. 529; J.-R. Palanque, Saint Ambroise et l’Empire romain: contribution à l’histoire des rap- ports de l’Eglise et de l’Etat à la fin du quatrième siècle (Paris 1933), pp. 452- 455; Dudden 2, p. 694; A. Paredi, Saint Ambrose: His Life and Times (Notre Dame, Ind. 1964) p. 316. On the other hand, W. Steidle, ‘Beobachtungen zum Gedankengang im 2. Buch von Ambrosius, De officiis,’ Vigiliae Christianae 39 (1985), pp. 280-298, argues that book 2 is carefully constructed. On the compo- sition of the work more broadly, see M. Testard, ‘Etude sur la composition dans le “De officiis ministrorum” de saint Ambroise,’ in Y.-M. Duval, op. cit., pp. 155-197; id., ‘Recherches de quelques méthodes de travail de saint Ambroise dans le De officiis,’ Recherches Augustiniennes 24 (1989), pp. 65-122. 202 RECHERCHES DE THÉOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MÉDIÉVALE book 2. It is possible, though we cannot be sure, that 2.1-21 comes from an independent homily on the vita beata, which Ambrose has inserted into the published version of Off. by adding a little Ciceronian language. It is clear from even a cursory reading of 2.1-21 that Ambrose works with two distinct controlling concepts of the vita beata: (1) vita beata in a Christian sense, identified with eternal life; (2) vita beata in a non-Christian sense, associated with virtue, the bless- ings of a good conscience, and the moral benefits of suffering and privation. The coexistence of these two strands offers a fascinating glimpse into the way in which Ambrose combines biblical per- spectives with principles which he has inherited from classical philosophy. I shall consider his handling of each sense of vita beata in turn. (1) In 2.1, Ambrose sets the tone of his discussion by referring to his treatment of honestas in book 1: the honourable is the ideal in qua vitam beatam positam esse nulli dubitaverunt quam Scrip- tura appellat vitam aeternam. Scripture defines the blessed life as eternal life. Eternal life is called blessed ut non hominum opinion- ibus aestimandum relinqueretur sed divino iudicio committeretur (2.3). When it comes to defining this type of blessed life, Ambrose draws on the range of NT conceptions, depicting eternal life as a future reality with benefits in the present. A good deal of debate has, of course, taken place over the differences between the use of (eternal) life in the Synoptic Gospels and in the Fourth Gospel.
Recommended publications
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. Paper 641. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]
  • ? PDF Free on the Happy Life: De Vita Beata
    Register Free To Download Files | File Name : On The Happy Life: De Vita Beata PDF ON THE HAPPY LIFE: DE VITA BEATA Paperback January 26, 2016 Author : Seneca De Vita Beata or On the Happy Life is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira ('On Anger'). It is divided into 28 chapters that present the moral thoughts of Seneca at their most mature. De Vita Beata ("On the Happy Life") is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira ("On Anger"). It is divided into 28 chapters that present the moral thoughts of Seneca at their most mature. Seneca's 'One the Happy Life' (De Vita Beata) 1. Defining Happiness (1) Seneca's beata renders the Greek eudaimonia. This means something like 'well-spirited' or 'well looked after the gods'; instead of 'happiness', we could say 'flourishing', which emphasizes the dynamic nature\u2014'happy-ing' is not a state. A Of a Happy Life (De Vita Beata) (1900) by Seneca, translated by Aubrey Stewart. sister projects: Wikidata item. From: Lucius Annaeus Seneca, Minor Dialogs Together with the Dialog "On Clemency"; translated by Aubrey Stewart, pp. 204-239. Bohn's Classical Library Edition; London, George Bell and Sons, 1900; scanned and digitized by Google from ... The Happy Life (De Beata Vita) by. Augustine of Hippo, Ludwig Schopp (translator) 3.96 \u00b7 Rating details \u00b7 101 ratings \u00b7 6 reviews.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason in Seneca Gould, Josiah, 1928
    Reason in Seneca Gould, Josiah, 1928- Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 3, Number 1, April 1965, pp. 13-25 (Article) Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/hph/summary/v003/3.1gould.html Access Provided by Università degli Studi di Palermo at 04/20/12 11:37AM GMT Reason m Seneca JOSIAH B. GOULD MAx POHLENZ, in his last great work on the Stoa, 1 maintained that Logos is the central concept of Stoic philosophy (I, 34). Neither Mette 2 nor Edelstein, 3 each of whom reviewed Pohlenz's study, notes the author's frequent reminders that Stoi- cism is "eine Logosphilosophie" and his contention, set forth early in Volume I, that the concept of Logos has in Stoic philosophy "pushed wholly to one side the Aristotelian J,o~s in doctrine as well as in terminology." One who is familiar with the fragments of the writings of the early Stoics hardly needs to be told that for Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus, Logos is a fundamental notion. Help is needed when one tries to make clear to himself the content of this notion. An example is the moral philosophy of Chrysippus as we have reconstructed it from the fragments of his writings. For Chrysippus the basic expression in Stoic moral philosophy, "life in accord- ance with nature" (zb ~arh ~b~Lu ~'~u) becomes "life in accordance with reason" (r~ KaTh ~,bTou ~'~). I have, however, found it difficult to render an account of what, for Chrysippus, it would be to live in accordance with Logos or reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1941 Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca Gabriel Connery Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Connery, Gabriel, "Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca" (1941). Master's Theses. 111. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/111 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1941 Gabriel Connery .ANALYSIS OF THE PHILOSOPHY .OF LUCIUS ANNA:EUS SENECA .BY BROTHER GABRIEL CONNERY, F. S.C. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Ful~illment o~ the Requirements ~or the Degree o~ Master o~ Arts at LOYOLA UNIVERSITY APPRECIATION The writer gratefully acknowledges his indebtedness to Brother Julius Hugh, F.s.c., Ph.D., Brother Leo of Mary, Ph.D., and Brother Dennis, F.s.c., M.A., whose thorough understanding and efficient teach­ ing of the principles of Scholastic Philo­ sophy and Classical Latin were of invalu­ able aid in the development of this study. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION • • • • • • • • • PAGE 1 CHAPTER I Seneca: Education and Political Back- ground • • • • • • • • 4
    [Show full text]
  • A Commentary on the De Constantia Sapientis of Seneca the Younger
    1 A Commentary on the De Constantia Sapientis of Seneca the Younger Nigel Royden Hope Royal Holloway, University of London Submitted for the degree of PhD 1 2 Declaration of Authorship I, Nigel Royden Hope, hereby declare that this thesis and the work presented in it is entirely my own. Where I have consulted the work of others, this is always clearly stated. Signed: ______________________ Date: ________________________ 2 3 Abstract The present thesis is a commentary on Seneca the Younger’s De constantia sapientis, one of his so-called dialogi. The text on which I comment forms part of the Oxford Classical Texts edition of the dialogi by L. D. Reynolds. The thesis is in two main parts: an Introduction and the Commentary proper. Before the Introduction, there is a justificatory Preface, in which I explain why this thesis is a necessary addition to the scholarship on De constantia sapientis, on which the last detailed commentary was published in 1950. The Introduction covers the following topics: Date; Genre (involving discussion of what is meant by the term dialogus and the place of De constantia sapientis in the collection of Seneca’s Dialogi as a whole); Argumentation: Techniques and Strategies (including a discussion of S.’s views on the role of logic in philosophy); Language and Style; Imagery; Moral Psychology (an analysis of Seneca’s account of the passions); The Nature of Insult (including types of insult, appropriate responses to insults, and interpretation of the meanings of two of the verbal insults presented by Seneca); and Legal Aspects (the question of the distinction between iniuria and contumelia in legal terms and what sorts of actions were pursued by an actio iniuriarum in Seneca’s day).
    [Show full text]
  • 2012.11.21 JAMES KER, a Seneca Reader
    CJ -Online, 2012.11.21 BOOK REVIEW A Seneca Reader: Selections from Prose and Tragedy . By JAMES KER . Mundelein, Illinois: Bolchazy-Carducci Publishers, Inc., 2011. Pp. lvi + 166. Paper, $19.00. ISBN 978-0-86516-758-2. his articulate and helpful book offers four Senecan “scenarios” for stu- dents to get a taste of Seneca’s Latin style, philosophical thought, and Tpoetic power. The benefit of offering snippets of the Consolatio ad Helviam , de Clementia , Medea , and Epistulae Morales is that one appreciates the generic gymnastics that Seneca was capable of, and one gets a view of the various personae he assumed as a writer. The selections offer moments in which Seneca (or characters) advise others on how to overcome adversity and, generally, live according to Stoic ideals. Ker is an amiable guide to the intricacies of Seneca’s Latin and the commentary elucidates quite well the questions intermediate Latin students will have about these texts. Most importantly, Ker answers the question of why one should choose to read Seneca at all, especially in a second/third year Latin course (when we most desire the students to stick around for more Latin!): namely, that his innovative works show that his finger was firmly on the pulse of the exciting literary, philosophical, and cultural developments of the 1st c. CE, and this collection offers us the opportunity to “eavesdrop” (p. lii) on this im- portant thinker and creative author. The work begins with an ample introduction covering not only what one would expect (Seneca’s life and death, a section on his family entitled “Meet the Senecas”), but also effective summaries of the various genres Seneca explored, and concrete examples of some of the peculiarities of Seneca’s style such as ana- phoric repetition, “three favorite syntactic constructions,” and “three words to watch.” The introduction also includes an up-to-date bibliography and strong sections on Seneca’s reception, Stoicism, and the pattern of “misfortune, grief, and the power of the mind” that the excerpts explore.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Augustine's Debt to Stoicism in the Confessions
    The Routledge Handbook of the Stoic Tradition; edited by John Sellars Format: Pinched_Crown (174 × 246 mm); Style: Handbook_1; Font: Bembo; Dir: //integrafs1/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/TRH_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/ 9780415660754_text.3d; Created: 13/11/2015 @ 12:42:14 4 AUGUSTINE’S DEBT TO STOICISM IN THE CONFESSIONS Sarah Catherine Byers Seneca asserts in Letter 121 (14–16) that we mature by exercising self-care as we pass through successive psychosomatic “constitutions.” These are babyhood (infantia), childhood (pueritia), adolescence (adulescentia), and young adulthood (iuventus).1 Augustine, of course, divides the narrative of his own development into these stages in the Confessions,2 a text wherein he claims familiarity with more than a few works of Seneca (Conf. 5.6.11). This raises the question: Does Augustine use the renowned Stoic theory of “affiliation” (oikeiôsis, conciliatio), upon which Seneca’s account of maturation depends, as a motif in his own philosophical auto- biography? If he does, that will update our understanding of the Confessions as a work in the history of philosophy. Traditionally, interpretations of this work have tended to see it as containing exclusively Neoplatonic or uniquely Christian thought.3 Self-affiliation is the linchpin of the Stoic ethical system, which defines living well as living in harmony with nature, posits that altruism develops from self-interest, and allows that pleasure and pain are indicators of well-being while denying that happiness consists in pleasure and that pain is misery (Diog. Laert. 7.85–9). Humans are rational social animals, according to Stoic psychology, and like all animals, they have an affinity to their own natural constitution, spontaneously seeking out what serves their well-being and avoiding what harms them.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen
    PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen The following full text is a publisher's version. For additional information about this publication click this link. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/29587 Please be advised that this information was generated on 2021-10-01 and may be subject to change. LIBRI AD MNEMOSYNEN MISSI Seneca, Four dialogues, edited by C.D.N, C osta. W ar­ minster, Aris & Phillips, 1994. VI, 218 pp. Roman Stoicism is perhaps best illustrated by the works of Seneca, notably his letters and his so called dialogi. For diose who wish to study the ]atter5 only few special tools are available in English. Part of the gap is now filled by this new selection of dialogi with translation and commentary by C. Gosta. It is the com­ panion volume to his earlier selection of Seneca’s letters (1988). The book is, of course, most welcomc} but it is not ‘the first serious commentary in English on any of Seneca’s Dialogues since Duff (19L5)S, as the back cover claims. The full commentary on Ad Marciam by C.E. Manning (Brill, Leiden 1981) ought at least to have been mentioned. Prof. Costa has chosen the following pieces: De Vita Beata, De Tranquillitate Animi, De Constantia Sapientis, Ad Helviam Matrem De Consolatione. The text, which is basically that of the OCT, is not excerpted but printed completely, with an English translation on the adjacent page. It is preceded by a very short intro­ duction (5 pages) and a select bibliography, and followed by a concise com­ mentary (45 pages) and an index.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and the Stoics: Fate, Freedom, and Providence
    Leibniz and the Stoics: Fate, Freedom, and Providence David Forman forthcoming in The Routledge Handbook of the Stoic Tradition 1. Against “The Sect of the New Stoics” In an essay dated to the late 1670s, Leibniz declares his allegiance to Socrates and to the Plato of the Phaedo against the modern revival of the Stoic and the Epicurean sects. The Epicurean materialism of Hobbes represents an obvious danger to piety, but Leibniz claims that the “sect of the new Stoics” led by Spinoza (and, by implication, Descartes) is no less dangerous. Although the new Stoics reject materialism, they nevertheless assert “a mechanical necessity in all things” that rules out final causes or purposes in the world. On such a view, God could not be a transcendent, wise governor who chooses what is best, but at most a “blind” power immanent within the world (G VII 333 = AG 282). This complaint reflects an old worry about the Stoics, having appeared e.g. in late antiquity in Boethius and in modern times in Bramhall.1 Leibniz would have been familiar with a version of the worry as articulated by his former teacher in Leipzig, Jacob Thomasius.2 Accordingly, in criticizing the advocates of predestination among his contemporaries (in a text from 1698), Leibniz complains that that they speak “as the Stoics do about fate” insofar as they maintain an “absolute necessity” arising out of the nature of the world itself (ex natura rei) that thereby subjects even God to fate (A IV.vii 508). 1 On Boethius, see Colish 1990: 2.275.
    [Show full text]
  • “On the Shortness of Life and on the Happy Life” by Lucius Annaeus Seneca © 2009 Abbott Epublishing
    This eBook was Published by Abbott ePublishing Manchester, New Hampshire “On the Shortness of Life and On the Happy Life” by Lucius Annaeus Seneca © 2009 Abbott ePublishing. All rights reserved. Edited by Stephen Abbott. Material used that is subject to the GNU Free Documentation License. No part of this publication may be reproduced, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, recording or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher. The purchaser of this eBook may not resell it or redistribute it, but may read it for personal use and store it on electronic devices for that purpose. Introduction This eBook contains two classics of Stoic literature by Seneca, perhaps its greatest advocate in the first century of the Common Era. Lucius Annaeus Seneca (often known simply as Seneca, or Seneca the Younger) (c. 4 BC – AD 65) was a Roman Stoic philosopher, statesman, dramatist, and in one work humorist, of the Silver Age of Latin literature. He was tutor and later advisor to emperor Nero, who later executed him for complicity in a conspiracy to assassinate him. He was likely innocent of the crime. He was born in Cordoba, Spain, the second son of Helvia and Marcus (Lucius) Annaeus Seneca, a wealthy rhetorician known as Seneca the Elder. Seneca's older brother, Gallio, was proconsul at Achaia (where he encountered the apostle Paul about AD 53). Seneca was uncle to the poet Lucan, by his younger brother, Annaeus Mela. A sickly child, he was taken to Rome by an aunt for schooling. He was trained in rhetoric, and studied neo-Pythagorean and, principally, Stoic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. 641. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]