? PDF Free on the Happy Life: De Vita Beata

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

? PDF Free on the Happy Life: De Vita Beata Register Free To Download Files | File Name : On The Happy Life: De Vita Beata PDF ON THE HAPPY LIFE: DE VITA BEATA Paperback January 26, 2016 Author : Seneca De Vita Beata or On the Happy Life is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira ('On Anger'). It is divided into 28 chapters that present the moral thoughts of Seneca at their most mature. De Vita Beata ("On the Happy Life") is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira ("On Anger"). It is divided into 28 chapters that present the moral thoughts of Seneca at their most mature. Seneca's 'One the Happy Life' (De Vita Beata) 1. Defining Happiness (1) Seneca's beata renders the Greek eudaimonia. This means something like 'well-spirited' or 'well looked after the gods'; instead of 'happiness', we could say 'flourishing', which emphasizes the dynamic nature\u2014'happy-ing' is not a state. A Of a Happy Life (De Vita Beata) (1900) by Seneca, translated by Aubrey Stewart. sister projects: Wikidata item. From: Lucius Annaeus Seneca, Minor Dialogs Together with the Dialog "On Clemency"; translated by Aubrey Stewart, pp. 204-239. Bohn's Classical Library Edition; London, George Bell and Sons, 1900; scanned and digitized by Google from ... The Happy Life (De Beata Vita) by. Augustine of Hippo, Ludwig Schopp (translator) 3.96 \u00b7 Rating details \u00b7 101 ratings \u00b7 6 reviews. Contains: The Happy Life, Schopp. Answer to Skeptics, D.J. Kavanaugh. Divine Providence & the Problem of Evil, T.F. Gilligan. 1 - Prologue. Augustine's reasons for writing de Beata Vita are rooted in his quest for a happy life , by way of philosophy. The text leans on a linkage between the pursuit of wisdom and the pursuit of happiness. In the first lines of this text, Augustine acknowledges that this quest cannot rely on reason only. On the Happy Life (Illustrated): De Vita Beata. by Seneca. Write a review. How are ratings calculated? See All Buying Options. Add to Wish List. Search. Sort by. Top reviews. Filter by. All reviewers. All stars. Text, image, video. 82 global ratings | 41 global reviews There was a problem filtering reviews right now. ... Find helpful customer reviews and review ratings for On the Happy Life: De Vita Beata at Amazon.com. Read honest and unbiased product reviews from our users. The Happy Life Quotes Showing 1-2 of 2 "Hence to be happy is nothing but not to be in need, that is, to be wise. But if you seek what wisdom is, reason has already explained and declared this as far as presently possible. De Vita Beata or On the Happy Life is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira (On Anger). It is divided into 28 chapters that present the moral thoughts of Seneca at their most mature. Good article, but your reference for the quote "I myself believe, though my Stoic comrades\u2026" and following is wrong. You say it is "Letters, 13" by which I presume you mean Epistulae Morales ad Lucilium. It is in fact from Of the Happy Life (De Vita Beata) 13. \u2014 Mike (De beata vita 2.10) From this statement, Augustine proceeds with questioning what a person should obtain to achieve happiness since happiness is a matter of having what one wants in order to be happy. The answer proposed by Augustine is that happiness constitutes something that can be had when it is wanted (De beata vita 2.11). With the ... Read "Of a Happy Life", by Seneca online on Bookmate - "Of a Happy Life (De Vita Beata)" by Seneca (translated by Aubrey Stewart). Published by Good Press. Good Press publishes a wide range of titles \u2026 Book VII To Gallio On The Happy Life. To live happily, my brother Gallio, a is the desire of all men, but their minds are blinded to a clear vision of just what it is that makes life happy; and so far from its being easy to attain the happy life, the more eagerly a man strives to reach it, the farther he recedes from it if he has made a mistake in the road; for when it leads in the opposite ... On the Happy Life (Illustrated): De Vita Beata: Seneca: Amazon.com.au: Books. Skip to main content.com.au. Hello Select your address Books Hello, Sign in. Account & Lists Account Returns & Orders. Cart All. Best Sellers Prime New Releases ... New Hard cover. Email to friends Share on Facebook - opens in a new window or tab Share on Twitter - opens in a new window or tab Share on Pinterest - opens in a new window or tab "On the Happy Life" (De Vita Beata) was a moral essay written to his brother Gallio. In a few words Seneca explains that the pursuit of happiness is the pursuit of the 'reason', which for him meant not only using logic, but also understanding the processes of nature. _____ The editor Augustine wrote four works during this period: Contra academicos (Against the Academics), De beata vita (On the Happy Life), De ordine (On Order) and Soliloquia (Soliloquies). But Augustine's account here of his time at Cassiciacum consists mainly of an extended analysis of Psalm 4, describing his emotion at breaking the hold Manichee ... On the Happy Life (Illustrated): De Vita Beata: Seneca: 9781549824982: Books - Amazon.ca. Skip to main content.ca Hello, Sign in. Account & Lists Account Returns & Orders. Try. Prime Cart. Books. Go Search Hello Select your address ... De Vita Beata ("On the Happy Life") is a dialogue written by Seneca the Younger around the year 58 AD. It was intended for his older brother Gallio, to whom Seneca also dedicated his dialogue entitled De Ira ("On Anger"). ... Content and tradition. The seventh book from Seneca's Dialogi is known as ad Gallionem de vita beata (in German "To Gallio about the happy life"). This title, which was later mentioned by Quintilian, is in tension with the origin of the collection, since Seneca calls his short letter-like writings sermones (German "conversations"). In this pamphlet, which was probably written at the beginning ... On the Happy Life: De Vita Beata (Paperback) Published January 26th 2016 by Createspace Independent Publishing Platform Paperback, 38 pages Author(s): Seneca, Aubrey Stewart (Translation), William Smith (Introduction) ISBN: 1523719753 (ISBN13 ... Seneca 1159571 Of a Happy Life \u2014 Book I 1900 Aubrey Stewart. I. A LL men, brother Gallio, wish to live happily, but are dull at perceiving exactly what it is that makes life happy: and so far is it from being easy to attain to happiness that the more eagerly a man struggles to reach it the further he departs from it, if he takes the wrong ... .
Recommended publications
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. Paper 641. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason in Seneca Gould, Josiah, 1928
    Reason in Seneca Gould, Josiah, 1928- Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 3, Number 1, April 1965, pp. 13-25 (Article) Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/hph/summary/v003/3.1gould.html Access Provided by Università degli Studi di Palermo at 04/20/12 11:37AM GMT Reason m Seneca JOSIAH B. GOULD MAx POHLENZ, in his last great work on the Stoa, 1 maintained that Logos is the central concept of Stoic philosophy (I, 34). Neither Mette 2 nor Edelstein, 3 each of whom reviewed Pohlenz's study, notes the author's frequent reminders that Stoi- cism is "eine Logosphilosophie" and his contention, set forth early in Volume I, that the concept of Logos has in Stoic philosophy "pushed wholly to one side the Aristotelian J,o~s in doctrine as well as in terminology." One who is familiar with the fragments of the writings of the early Stoics hardly needs to be told that for Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus, Logos is a fundamental notion. Help is needed when one tries to make clear to himself the content of this notion. An example is the moral philosophy of Chrysippus as we have reconstructed it from the fragments of his writings. For Chrysippus the basic expression in Stoic moral philosophy, "life in accord- ance with nature" (zb ~arh ~b~Lu ~'~u) becomes "life in accordance with reason" (r~ KaTh ~,bTou ~'~). I have, however, found it difficult to render an account of what, for Chrysippus, it would be to live in accordance with Logos or reason.
    [Show full text]
  • 9674 RTAM 09 Davidson
    The Vita Beata: Ambrose, De Officiis 2.1-21 And the Synthesis of Classical and Christian Thought in the Late Fourth Century In his Sermo 150, Augustine argues that the desire to attain the vita beata has been the motivation for all types of philosophy, and that it is also the reason that people would give if asked why they became Christians; the quest is common to all human beings, whether good or evil. Appetitio…beatae vitae philosophis Christianisque communis est1. The truth of Augustine’s claims is illustrated in a variety of Latin Christian works from the fourth century, which take up the traditional philosophical theme of hap- piness and the summum bonum. Lactantius relates the highest good to the immortality of the soul, and calls upon his readers to find their destiny by devoting themselves to the worship of the true God; the worship of God is the greatest virtue, and it wins the blessedness of eternal reward2. Augustine’s De beata vita, written at Cassiciacum in November, 386, and dedicated to the cultured neo-Platonist, Manlius Theodorus, presents a blend of Plotinian thought with Catholic orthodoxy: the blessed life con- sists in the knowledge of the triune God3. Ambrose’s De Iacob et vita beata, based upon sermons to which Augustine may well have listened earlier in 386, concentrates on the virtues of blessedness as illustrated in the narratives of the Maccabees and of the patriarch Jacob. Ambrose offers an amalgam of Stoic and neo-Platonist sentiments as he sketches the character of the per- son who proceeds towards eternal fellowship with God by ratio- nal control of his passions, detachment from his external circum- stances, and finally, like the faithful martyr, remaining steadfast 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1941 Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca Gabriel Connery Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Connery, Gabriel, "Analysis of the Philosophy of Lucius Annaeus Seneca" (1941). Master's Theses. 111. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/111 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1941 Gabriel Connery .ANALYSIS OF THE PHILOSOPHY .OF LUCIUS ANNA:EUS SENECA .BY BROTHER GABRIEL CONNERY, F. S.C. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Ful~illment o~ the Requirements ~or the Degree o~ Master o~ Arts at LOYOLA UNIVERSITY APPRECIATION The writer gratefully acknowledges his indebtedness to Brother Julius Hugh, F.s.c., Ph.D., Brother Leo of Mary, Ph.D., and Brother Dennis, F.s.c., M.A., whose thorough understanding and efficient teach­ ing of the principles of Scholastic Philo­ sophy and Classical Latin were of invalu­ able aid in the development of this study. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION • • • • • • • • • PAGE 1 CHAPTER I Seneca: Education and Political Back- ground • • • • • • • • 4
    [Show full text]
  • A Commentary on the De Constantia Sapientis of Seneca the Younger
    1 A Commentary on the De Constantia Sapientis of Seneca the Younger Nigel Royden Hope Royal Holloway, University of London Submitted for the degree of PhD 1 2 Declaration of Authorship I, Nigel Royden Hope, hereby declare that this thesis and the work presented in it is entirely my own. Where I have consulted the work of others, this is always clearly stated. Signed: ______________________ Date: ________________________ 2 3 Abstract The present thesis is a commentary on Seneca the Younger’s De constantia sapientis, one of his so-called dialogi. The text on which I comment forms part of the Oxford Classical Texts edition of the dialogi by L. D. Reynolds. The thesis is in two main parts: an Introduction and the Commentary proper. Before the Introduction, there is a justificatory Preface, in which I explain why this thesis is a necessary addition to the scholarship on De constantia sapientis, on which the last detailed commentary was published in 1950. The Introduction covers the following topics: Date; Genre (involving discussion of what is meant by the term dialogus and the place of De constantia sapientis in the collection of Seneca’s Dialogi as a whole); Argumentation: Techniques and Strategies (including a discussion of S.’s views on the role of logic in philosophy); Language and Style; Imagery; Moral Psychology (an analysis of Seneca’s account of the passions); The Nature of Insult (including types of insult, appropriate responses to insults, and interpretation of the meanings of two of the verbal insults presented by Seneca); and Legal Aspects (the question of the distinction between iniuria and contumelia in legal terms and what sorts of actions were pursued by an actio iniuriarum in Seneca’s day).
    [Show full text]
  • 2012.11.21 JAMES KER, a Seneca Reader
    CJ -Online, 2012.11.21 BOOK REVIEW A Seneca Reader: Selections from Prose and Tragedy . By JAMES KER . Mundelein, Illinois: Bolchazy-Carducci Publishers, Inc., 2011. Pp. lvi + 166. Paper, $19.00. ISBN 978-0-86516-758-2. his articulate and helpful book offers four Senecan “scenarios” for stu- dents to get a taste of Seneca’s Latin style, philosophical thought, and Tpoetic power. The benefit of offering snippets of the Consolatio ad Helviam , de Clementia , Medea , and Epistulae Morales is that one appreciates the generic gymnastics that Seneca was capable of, and one gets a view of the various personae he assumed as a writer. The selections offer moments in which Seneca (or characters) advise others on how to overcome adversity and, generally, live according to Stoic ideals. Ker is an amiable guide to the intricacies of Seneca’s Latin and the commentary elucidates quite well the questions intermediate Latin students will have about these texts. Most importantly, Ker answers the question of why one should choose to read Seneca at all, especially in a second/third year Latin course (when we most desire the students to stick around for more Latin!): namely, that his innovative works show that his finger was firmly on the pulse of the exciting literary, philosophical, and cultural developments of the 1st c. CE, and this collection offers us the opportunity to “eavesdrop” (p. lii) on this im- portant thinker and creative author. The work begins with an ample introduction covering not only what one would expect (Seneca’s life and death, a section on his family entitled “Meet the Senecas”), but also effective summaries of the various genres Seneca explored, and concrete examples of some of the peculiarities of Seneca’s style such as ana- phoric repetition, “three favorite syntactic constructions,” and “three words to watch.” The introduction also includes an up-to-date bibliography and strong sections on Seneca’s reception, Stoicism, and the pattern of “misfortune, grief, and the power of the mind” that the excerpts explore.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Augustine's Debt to Stoicism in the Confessions
    The Routledge Handbook of the Stoic Tradition; edited by John Sellars Format: Pinched_Crown (174 × 246 mm); Style: Handbook_1; Font: Bembo; Dir: //integrafs1/kcg/2-Pagination/TandF/TRH_RAPS/ApplicationFiles/ 9780415660754_text.3d; Created: 13/11/2015 @ 12:42:14 4 AUGUSTINE’S DEBT TO STOICISM IN THE CONFESSIONS Sarah Catherine Byers Seneca asserts in Letter 121 (14–16) that we mature by exercising self-care as we pass through successive psychosomatic “constitutions.” These are babyhood (infantia), childhood (pueritia), adolescence (adulescentia), and young adulthood (iuventus).1 Augustine, of course, divides the narrative of his own development into these stages in the Confessions,2 a text wherein he claims familiarity with more than a few works of Seneca (Conf. 5.6.11). This raises the question: Does Augustine use the renowned Stoic theory of “affiliation” (oikeiôsis, conciliatio), upon which Seneca’s account of maturation depends, as a motif in his own philosophical auto- biography? If he does, that will update our understanding of the Confessions as a work in the history of philosophy. Traditionally, interpretations of this work have tended to see it as containing exclusively Neoplatonic or uniquely Christian thought.3 Self-affiliation is the linchpin of the Stoic ethical system, which defines living well as living in harmony with nature, posits that altruism develops from self-interest, and allows that pleasure and pain are indicators of well-being while denying that happiness consists in pleasure and that pain is misery (Diog. Laert. 7.85–9). Humans are rational social animals, according to Stoic psychology, and like all animals, they have an affinity to their own natural constitution, spontaneously seeking out what serves their well-being and avoiding what harms them.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen
    PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen The following full text is a publisher's version. For additional information about this publication click this link. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/29587 Please be advised that this information was generated on 2021-10-01 and may be subject to change. LIBRI AD MNEMOSYNEN MISSI Seneca, Four dialogues, edited by C.D.N, C osta. W ar­ minster, Aris & Phillips, 1994. VI, 218 pp. Roman Stoicism is perhaps best illustrated by the works of Seneca, notably his letters and his so called dialogi. For diose who wish to study the ]atter5 only few special tools are available in English. Part of the gap is now filled by this new selection of dialogi with translation and commentary by C. Gosta. It is the com­ panion volume to his earlier selection of Seneca’s letters (1988). The book is, of course, most welcomc} but it is not ‘the first serious commentary in English on any of Seneca’s Dialogues since Duff (19L5)S, as the back cover claims. The full commentary on Ad Marciam by C.E. Manning (Brill, Leiden 1981) ought at least to have been mentioned. Prof. Costa has chosen the following pieces: De Vita Beata, De Tranquillitate Animi, De Constantia Sapientis, Ad Helviam Matrem De Consolatione. The text, which is basically that of the OCT, is not excerpted but printed completely, with an English translation on the adjacent page. It is preceded by a very short intro­ duction (5 pages) and a select bibliography, and followed by a concise com­ mentary (45 pages) and an index.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and the Stoics: Fate, Freedom, and Providence
    Leibniz and the Stoics: Fate, Freedom, and Providence David Forman forthcoming in The Routledge Handbook of the Stoic Tradition 1. Against “The Sect of the New Stoics” In an essay dated to the late 1670s, Leibniz declares his allegiance to Socrates and to the Plato of the Phaedo against the modern revival of the Stoic and the Epicurean sects. The Epicurean materialism of Hobbes represents an obvious danger to piety, but Leibniz claims that the “sect of the new Stoics” led by Spinoza (and, by implication, Descartes) is no less dangerous. Although the new Stoics reject materialism, they nevertheless assert “a mechanical necessity in all things” that rules out final causes or purposes in the world. On such a view, God could not be a transcendent, wise governor who chooses what is best, but at most a “blind” power immanent within the world (G VII 333 = AG 282). This complaint reflects an old worry about the Stoics, having appeared e.g. in late antiquity in Boethius and in modern times in Bramhall.1 Leibniz would have been familiar with a version of the worry as articulated by his former teacher in Leipzig, Jacob Thomasius.2 Accordingly, in criticizing the advocates of predestination among his contemporaries (in a text from 1698), Leibniz complains that that they speak “as the Stoics do about fate” insofar as they maintain an “absolute necessity” arising out of the nature of the world itself (ex natura rei) that thereby subjects even God to fate (A IV.vii 508). 1 On Boethius, see Colish 1990: 2.275.
    [Show full text]
  • “On the Shortness of Life and on the Happy Life” by Lucius Annaeus Seneca © 2009 Abbott Epublishing
    This eBook was Published by Abbott ePublishing Manchester, New Hampshire “On the Shortness of Life and On the Happy Life” by Lucius Annaeus Seneca © 2009 Abbott ePublishing. All rights reserved. Edited by Stephen Abbott. Material used that is subject to the GNU Free Documentation License. No part of this publication may be reproduced, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, recording or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher. The purchaser of this eBook may not resell it or redistribute it, but may read it for personal use and store it on electronic devices for that purpose. Introduction This eBook contains two classics of Stoic literature by Seneca, perhaps its greatest advocate in the first century of the Common Era. Lucius Annaeus Seneca (often known simply as Seneca, or Seneca the Younger) (c. 4 BC – AD 65) was a Roman Stoic philosopher, statesman, dramatist, and in one work humorist, of the Silver Age of Latin literature. He was tutor and later advisor to emperor Nero, who later executed him for complicity in a conspiracy to assassinate him. He was likely innocent of the crime. He was born in Cordoba, Spain, the second son of Helvia and Marcus (Lucius) Annaeus Seneca, a wealthy rhetorician known as Seneca the Elder. Seneca's older brother, Gallio, was proconsul at Achaia (where he encountered the apostle Paul about AD 53). Seneca was uncle to the poet Lucan, by his younger brother, Annaeus Mela. A sickly child, he was taken to Rome by an aunt for schooling. He was trained in rhetoric, and studied neo-Pythagorean and, principally, Stoic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. 641. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]