<<

Thesis_Ginges_H.txt

THE ACT OF KNOWING:

AND THE NEO-KANTIAN TRADITION

Hal Jon Ginges

Page 1 Thesis_Ginges_H.txt

A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of

University of Western Sydney

February 2012

Page 2 2 Certificate.txt

Certificate

This work has not been submitted previously for a higher degree at any other institution. The work contained in this thesis is entirely my own, except for references to the works of others as indicated in the text.

Signed:

Date:

Page 1 3 Abstract.txt

Abstract

A central claim of Kantian critical idealism is that our knowledge is limited to appearances, and that we cannot show we have knowledge of things-in-themselves. All of our knowledge of the given world is mediated to us through the sensory intuitions of space and time, and our intellect is discursive rather than archetypal. As a result, we cannot know things spontaneously, and we cannot have holistic knowledge of natural phenomena. Although unmediated knowledge by way of intellectual intuition must be counted as a rational possibility that is not a capacity we possess. Similarly, while an archetypal intellect must be a rational possibility, according to Kant we do not have one.

Rudolf Steiner is well known as an educator. In his early career Steiner was trained as a natural scientist, took a doctorate in neo-Kantian philosophy and sought to demonstrate that we do have direct access to knowledge of essences. Steiner was greatly influenced by Goethe and Fichte and attempted to overcome the limit Kant placed upon possible knowledge by adapting Goethe’s concept of the archetypal phenomenon to claim that we do possess an intellectus archetypus and by extrapolating from Fichte’s argument for intellectual intuition to argue for what he calls intuitive thinking.

This dissertation examines Steiner’s arguments as a series of disjunctions from the propositions of the critical philosophy. The thesis of the dissertation is that Steiner is ultimately unsuccessful in his attempts to establish the capacities for an intellectus archetypus and intuitive thinking from within the context of critical idealism, but that his work opens up ways in which neo-Kantian scholarship may be further developed.

Page 1 4 CONTENTS.txt Contents

Acknowledgements ii

Abbreviations iv

Texts and translations vi

Introduction:

Rudolf Steiner the Philosopher 1

PART 1

Chapter 1: Intuition and Archetype 23

Chapter 2: Goethe’s Way of Seeing 32

Chapter 3: The Kantian Legacy 58

PART 2

Chapter 4: Monism and Dualism 72

Chapter 5: Perceiving the Archetype 108

Chapter 6: Intellectual Intuition 155

Chapter 7: Intuitive Thinking 209

Page 1 4 CONTENTS.txt

Conclusion 247

Bibliography 254

Page 2 5 Acknowledgements.txt Acknowledgements

I was introduced to the thought and work of Rudolf Steiner in about 1970, when I was an undergraduate student at Sydney University. I have had an ambivalent relationship with Steiner’s ever since. I have been attracted from the start to the practical aspects of Anthroposophy such as the Waldorf school curriculum, and Steiner’s socio-political concept of the threefold social order. I have met people I admire and respect through Anthroposophy and have formed strong friendships with some of them. At the same time my natural scepticism and my training in Philosophy have made me incapable of accepting on faith much of the world view that many anthroposophists take for granted.

My ambivalent relationship with Anthroposophy eventually drove me to read Steiner’s Philosophy of Freedom carefully. I was astonished to find that this thinker, branded as a theosophist and a mystic, displayed an impressive familiarity with the work of Kant, the post-Kantians and his contemporary Neo-Kantians, and was attempting to argue for his spiritual science as a philosopher. I wanted to know whether Steiner’s spiritual science, and the practical activities which had arisen from it, could indeed be legitimised as a form of knowledge from within the mainstream Western tradition. I was surprised, though perhaps I ought not to have been, that there appeared to be almost no academic work undertaken on the subject.

In late 2005 I approached Dr Michael Symonds at the University of Western Sydney about his supervising a doctoral dissertation on the epistemology of Rudolf Steiner. I commenced as a part-time student in 2006, and was awarded a scholarship by the

University from 2007 to mid 2009. Throughout the six years of my research I have enjoyed Michael’s support and enthusiasm for the project, and have benefited greatly from his helpful criticisms and his clear insights. I was able to visit the , the international headquarters of the in Dornach, Switzerland in January 2008 with assistance from the University. I wish to acknowledge with gratitude the constant encouragement, well beyond the call of duty, which I have received from Dr Michael Symonds and the support I have had from the Research Unit of the University.

Outside of the University I have received support and encouragement from persons associated with Anthroposophy. The Eileen Mac Pherson Trust provided me with some financial support, Dr Walter Kugler and his staff at the Rudolf Steiner Archiv in Dornach were very accommodating, and Rudolf Steiner House in Sydney has assisted me by arranging for me to lecture on Steiner’s epistemology in an open forum. Numerous of

Page 1 5 Acknowledgements.txt my friends, including John Shaw, Arthur Marshall and Jacob van Gent have expressed a continuing interest in my project and a desire to read the final product.

On a personal and on a practical level I wish to acknowledge the love and support I have received from my wife, Heather. She has read my drafts and provided me with valuable suggestions, and challenged me on many points so as to sharpen my thinking. She has also had to carry the larger load of the responsibilities we bear towards our ever expanding family, and I thank her for ensuring that I have had time available to me to complete this labour of love. It only remains to thank our children and grandchildren for their continuing love and interest in what Papa is doing despite his absences: thank you, to all of you, for your kindness and understanding.

Page 2 6 Abbreviations.txt Abbreviations

Fichte, J.

IWL Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre. Translated by D. Breazeale. (Cornell

University Press: Ithaca and London, 1992).

Goethe, J.

GOS Goethe on Science: An Anthology of Goethe’s Scientific Writings. (Floris Books:

Edinburgh, 2000)

GSW Goethes Sämtliche Werke. (Max Hesses Verlag: Leipzig).

Henrich, D.

FOI Fichte’s Original Insight. In Contemporary German Philosophy vol 1.

(Pennsylvania State University Press, pp15-53)

Kant, I.

CJ Critique of Judgment. Translated by W. Pluhar. (Hackett Publishing Company:

Page 1 6 Abbreviations.txt

Indianapolis, 1987).

CPR Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. (Palgrave

Macmillan: London, 1993).

CPrR Critique of Practical Reason. Translated by Lewis White Beck. (Prentice Hall:

New Jersey, 1993).

GW The Moral Law: Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, Edited by

Paton. (Hutchinson University Library: London, 1972)

KPV Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1974)

KRV Kritik der reinen Vernunft. (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1974)

KU Kritik der Urteilskraft. (Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, 1974)

Steiner, R.

CML Autobiography: The Course of my Life. Translated R. Stebbing.

Page 2 6 Abbreviations.txt

(Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, NY, 1983)

GNS Einleitungen zu Goethes Naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften, (Rudolf

Steiner Verlag: Dornach, 1999)

GWV Goethe’s World View. Translated by W. Lindeman. (Mercury Press: Spring

Valley, 2004)

ITSP Intuitive Thinking as a Spiritual Path. Translated by M. Lipson.

(Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, NY, 1995)

NOS Nature’s Open Secret. Translated by J. Barnes and M. Spiegler,

(Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, NY, 1995).

Ph F Die Philosophie der Freiheit. (Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach, 2005).

Ph FE The Philosophy of Freedom. Translated by M. Wilson. (Rudolf Steiner Press:

Forest Row, 2001).

RP Riddles of Philosophy. Introduced by F. Koelln. (Anthroposophic Press: Spring

Page 3 6 Abbreviations.txt

Valley, NY, 1973).

SK The Science of Knowing. Translated by W. Lindeman. (Mercury Press: Spring

Valley, NY, 1988).

TK Truth and Knowledge. Translated by R. Stebbing. (Steinerbooks: Blauvelt, NY,

1981).

WW Wahrheit und Wissenschaft. (Rudolf Steiner Online Archiv, 2010).

Page 4 7 Texts and translations.txt Texts and Translations

Original sources

Rudolf Steiner’s works have been collected and authorised for publication by the Rudolf Steiner Nachlassverwaltung in Dornach, Switzerland. Unless otherwise indicated references to the original texts are to the volumes of the 7th edition of the Gesamtausgabe published by Rudolf Steiner Verlag, Dornach.

The texts used for the Kant’s Critiques are the 1974 Suhrkamp paperback editions published by Insel Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. The texts used for Goethe are the Gesamtausgabe published by Max Hesse Verlag in Leipzig. Fichte’s works have not been consulted in the original.

Sources in translation

Much of Steiner’s work has been translated into English. The principal publishers are in the United Kingdom – London, Edinburgh and Forest Row – and at Spring Valley in New York. Some of Steiner’s principal works are available in several translations and editions. Philosophie der Freiheit was originally translated by Alfred Hoernle in 1916, and published as Philosophy of Freedom. A revised edition, with a translation by Hermann Poppelbaum was published in 1939 under the title The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity. The original translation was revisited by Michael Wilson, whose 1964 edition also restored the original title. Wilson’s translation is the accepted British version, and is now in its seventh edition. In the United States a new translation by Michael Lipson has been published recently under the title Intuitive Thinking as a Spiritual Path. Both the Wilson and the Lipson translations have been consulted but citations are to the Lipson translation.

Steiner’s introductions to Goethe’s scientific works were originally published in translation by Anthroposophic Press as Goethe the Scientist in 1950. The more recent American translation by J. Barnes and M. Spiegler is published as Nature’s Open Secret Anthroposophic Press. This translation has been consulted throughout.

The translations of Kant’s three Critiques, which have been consulted, are respectively the Kemp Smith, White Beck and Pluhar translations.

Page 1 7 Texts and translations.txt Some of Goethe’s scientific work is available in translation, though much of it in an incomplete form. Extensive use has been made of the anthology contained in Jeremy Naydler’s Goethe on Science. At times this writer has undertaken his own translations.

Page 2 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt INTRODUCTION: RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER

Rudolf Steiner is a fairly well-known figure in the intellectual life of Continental Europe of the early 20th century. Steiner is most commonly associated with the Waldorf, or Rudolf Steiner, schools for which he provided the curriculum and with biodynamic (advanced organic) agriculture. Were this dissertation to be a study of some aspect of Steiner’s educational philosophy or of the relative efficacy of Steiner’s form of organic agriculture it would not be particularly remarkable. There are many academic and other studies of ,1 and there are numerous tracts on the efficacy of biodynamic agriculture.2 Outside of these fields, however, and despite the substantial volume of his work3 and his evident familiarity with the Western intellectual tradition Steiner has largely been ignored by the academy.4 In his later career Steiner became a theosophist and a spiritual scientist, and it seems that his contributions to neo-Kantian philosophy have been judged by this later career and have therefore been overlooked.

1 See, for example, Carlgren, F. (2008) Education Towards Freedom: Rudolf Steiner Education, Floris Books: Edinburgh; Mazzone, A. (2010) A Passionate Education, Griffin Press: Salisbury, South Australia.

2 See, for example, Pfeiffer, E. (1983) Biodynamic Gardening and Farming, Mercury Press: London.

3 There are about 400 volumes of the Gesamtausgabe published by the Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach.

4 Of this phenomenon see, for example, Davenport R. (1955) The Dignity of Man, Harper Bros: New York, pp335-336: That the academic world has managed to dismiss Steiner’s works as inconsequential and irrelevant, is one of the intellectual wonders of the twentieth century. Anyone who is willing to study those vast works with an open mind (let us say, a hundred of his titles) will find himself faced with one of the greatest thinkers of all time, whose grasp of the modern sciences is equaled only by his profound learning in the ancient ones. Steiner was no more of a mystic than Albert Einstein; he was a scientist, rather – but a scientist who dared to enter into the mysteries of life.

In his early career Steiner was an aspiring philosopher. He wrote on Kant and the neo- Kantian tradition in a way which reveals a clear understanding of the epistemological problems within it, and which demonstrates a familiarity with the thinking and arguments of his contemporary neo-Kantians and of more popular writers such as Schopenhauer and

Nietzsche.5 At that early stage Steiner’s primary interest was in knowledge in the strictest sense of the word, and in finding a way to overcome the unsatisfying conclusion of Kantian critical idealism, namely that we cannot claim to have knowledge of essences. It is the thesis of this dissertation that Steiner is entitled to have his early work regarded as a creditable attempt to address the epistemological issues which arise from the critical project, and that his contributions to Continental epistemology carry the promise of further developments in the idealist tradition.

Page 1 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt 5Steiner, R. (1999) Autobiography: Chapters in the Course of my Life, Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, NY hereinafter CML, p167: My affinity with Nietzsche allowed me to describe in my book about him my relationship to him in the very words he uses to describe his relationship with Schopenhauer: I am among those readers of Nietzsche who, once they read a page, know absolutely that they will read every page and listen to every word he has ever spoken. I felt immediate confidence in him … I understood him as though he had written in place of me, to clearly express me, though without presumption and foolishness. Steiner’s book about Nietzsche is Friedrich Nietzsche, Ein Kämpfer gegen seiner Zeit GA5 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach is translated as Friedrich Nietzsche: A Fighter against his Times and available in Steiner, R. (1985) Friedrich Nietzsche, Fighter for Freedom, Spiritual Science Library: Blauvelt, N.Y.

6 Steiner dedicates his doctoral thesis Wahrheit und Wissenschaft [Truth and Knowledge] To Dr Eduard von Hartmann with the warm regard of the author.

Rudolf Steiner was born in 1861 in Krajkevic, Croatia, in what was then part of the Austro-Hungarian Empire. His parents were Austrian, and the language of his written works is therefore German. Upon finishing school Steiner studied natural science at the University of Vienna and attended philosophy courses given by Franz Brentano. When he graduated in 1882 he was offered a position as the editor of Goethe’s scientific works for the Kürschner edition of German literature. This assignment took him to Weimar, where he undertook research in the Goethe-Schiller archives, was drawn to the transcendental realism of Eduard von Hartmann6 and to Nietzsche’s world view, completed his doctoral thesis and published his principal philosophical works. Steiner’s early career had unfolded within the arena of conventional intellectual life, and he sought an academic post, but was unsuccessful in obtaining one. When he finished his work in

the Goethe-Schiller Archives, he moved from Weimar to Berlin, edited an avant-garde magazine, Die Kommenden [The Coming Ones], was a member of the Bohemian literary and artistic cafe scene and taught at the Workers’ Institute.

From 1901 Steiner began to publish a series of books and articles, in which he set out what he claimed to be the results of his clairvoyant observations, and which he described as knowledge of higher worlds. In these works Steiner describes a path of inner development as a way of obtaining knowledge of essences. Steiner joined, and then led, the German branch of the Theosophical Society, out of which he formed the Anthroposophical Society in 1913. From then until his death in 1925 Steiner wrote and lectured extensively on the results of what he called anthroposophische Geisteswissenschaft [anthroposophical spiritual science]. His increasing reputation as a public figure who claimed to have spiritual knowledge brought him a considerable personal following, but it cost him the respect and friendship of many of his former associations amongst philosophers and other intellectuals. Another consequence has been that Steiner’s early work as a serious commentator on neo-Kantian epistemology has been largely ignored or forgotten.

Page 2 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt Primary sources

Steiner’s epistemological works appeared in the last two decades of the 19th century, at a time when there were strong neo-Kantian movements in the mainstream of German philosophy. Between 1885 and 1897 Steiner wrote five works which might be said to comprise his specifically epistemological output. They are Grundlinien einer Erkenntnistheorie der Goetheschen Weltanschauung mit besonderer Rücksicht auf

Schiller [Foundations of a theory of knowledge of Goethe’s world view with particular reference to Schiller] (1885)7, Einleitungen in Goethes naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften [Introductions to Goethe’s writings on natural science] (1885- 1897)8, Wahrheit und Wissenschaft [Truth and Knowledge] (1892)9, Die Philosophie der Freiheit [Philosophy of Freedom] (1894)10 and Goethes Weltanschauung [Goethe’s World View] (1897)11. Steiner’s first publication was written while he was engaged in preparing commentaries on Goethe’s scientific works, and is his first attempt to identify the theory of knowledge, which he believed underlay Goethe’s approach to the study of nature. The second publication is those commentaries themselves, which appeared in three batches between 1885 and 1897. Although the commentaries are intended as introductions to Goethe’s scientific works they also set out some of the arguments central to Steiner’s own epistemological position. The third is Steiner’s doctoral thesis, the fourth, Philosophy of Freedom, is his principal philosophical work and the fifth is his last publication before embarking upon spiritual science.

7Steiner, R (1999) Grundlinien einer Erkenntnistheorie der Goetheshen Weltanschauung mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Schiller, GA 2 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach, now translated as Steiner, R.(1988) The Science of Knowing, Mercury Press: Spring Valley, NY and hereinafter SK.

8Steiner, R. (1999) Einleitungen in Goethes naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften, GA 1 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach, now translated as Steiner, R. (2000) Nature’s Open Secret, Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, NY and hereinafter NOS.

9Steiner, R. (1999) Wahrheit und Wissenschaft , GA 3 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach, in translation as Steiner, R. (1981) Truth and Knowledge, Steinerbooks: Blauvelt, NY hereinafter TK.

1010Steiner, R. (2005) Die Philosophie der Freiheit, GA 4 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach hereinafter PhF, in translation as Steiner, R. (2001) The Philosophy of Freedom, Rudolf Steiner Press: Forest Row, hereinafter PhFE and as Steiner, R. (1995) Intuitive Thinking as a Spiritual Path, Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, NY hereinafter ITSP. This is the translation most cited in the present work, largely because the editor has helpfully enumerated the paragraphs.

11 Steiner, R. (1999) Goethes Weltanschauung, GA 6 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach in translation as Steiner, R. (2004) Goethe’s World View, Mercury Press: Spring Valley, NY hereinafter GWV.

These first works are an attempt to create a theory of knowledge out of Goethe’s scientific methodology and independent of the Kantian tradition. The following excerpt

Page 3 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt from the first section of The Science of Knowing demonstrates Steiner’s early antipathy to Kantianism and his attachment to the cultural heritage represented by Goethe and Schiller. At this stage he has not yet attempted to incorporate Goethean thinking into neo-Kantianism, and could say:12

12 SK pp 17-18.

13 TK, p. 9.

14 TK pp 11-12.

In accordance with current scientific terminology, our work must be considered to be one of epistemology. To be sure, the questions with which it deals will in many ways be of a different nature from those usually raised by this science. We have seen why this is the case. Whenever similar investigations arise today, they take their start almost entirely from Kant. In scientific circles the fact has been completely overlooked that in addition to the science of knowledge founded by the great thinker of Koenigsberg, there is yet another direction, at least potentially, that is no less capable than the Kantian one of being deepened in an objective manner. In the early 1860’s Otto Liebmann made the statement that we must go back to Kant if we wish to arrive at a world view free of contradiction. This is why today we have a literature on Kant almost too vast to encompass.

But this Kantian path will not help the science of philosophy. Philosophy will play a part in cultural life again only when, instead of going back to Kant, it immerses itself in the scientific conception of Goethe and Schiller.

By the time Truth and Knowledge was published in 1892 Steiner has moved to approaching the issue of the limits to knowledge from within the context of the Kantian and post-Kantian traditions. Although he claims that present-day philosophy suffers from an unhealthy faith in Kant,13 Steiner sets up his argument as a response to the foundations of critical idealism and as an extension of Fichte’s work on intellectual intuition. He is also able to articulate the difference of perspective between his position and the Kantian. In the Preface to Truth and Knowledge Steiner sets out his view of knowledge and the act of knowing in the following terms:14

The outcome of what follows is that truth is not, as is usually assumed, an ideal reflection of something real, but is a product of the human spirit, created by an

activity which is free; this product would exist nowhere if we did not create it ourselves. The object of knowledge is not to repeat in conceptual form something which already exists, but rather to create a completely new sphere, which when combined with the world given to our senses constitutes complete

Page 4 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt reality. Thus man’s highest activity, his spiritual creativeness, is an organic part of the universal world-process. The world-process should not be considered a complete, enclosed totality without this activity. Man is not a passive onlooker in relation to evolution, merely repeating in mental pictures cosmic events taking place without his participation; he is the active co-creator of the world-process, and cognition is the most perfect link in the organism of the universe.

This statement of Steiner’s epistemological position can also be read as an expression of what Steiner took his life’s mission to be, namely the reunification of matter and spirit within the sciences.

Steiner’s principal philosophical work, Philosophy of Freedom, appeared in 1894 and contains the clearest expression of Steiner’s arguments against Kantian epistemology. Philosophy of Freedom purports to be a demonstration that human beings are inwardly (spiritually) free, but it, too, is written as a response to critical idealism. The first half of the book argues for Steiner’s theory of knowledge against the backdrop of the dualism of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft [Critique of Pure Reason]15, while the second half presents Steiner’s argument for ethical individualism as a counter to Kant’s deontological categorical imperative in the Kritik der praktischen Vernunft [Critique of Practical Reason]16. Philosophy of Freedom has been reprinted many times both in German and in English translation. Steiner recommended that the title be translated as The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity, so as to avoid the socio-political connotations most commonly

15 Kant, I. (1974) Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt aM. The translation used is by Lewis White Beck, annotated by Howard Caygill, (2003) Critique of Pure Reason, Palgrave MacMillan: Basingstoke, Hampshire, hereinafter the First Critique and CPR.

16 Kant, I. (1974 ) Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt aM. The translation used is by Lewis White Beck, (1993) Critique of Practical Reason, Prentice Hall: New Jersey, hereinafter the Second Critique and CPrR.

associated with freedom in English. He did not appreciate that the connotations of spiritual are equally likely to lead to misunderstanding.

The final specifically epistemological work is Goethe’s World View, which was published in 1897. By this time Steiner had published his book on Nietzsche and the last of his Introductions to Goethe’s scientific oeuvres, and was coming to the end of his time in Weimar. In Goethe’s World View Steiner distinguishes his own epistemological position from the theory of knowledge implicit in Goethe’s natural science, argues that Plato’s concept of forms and Ideas has been consistently misunderstood, and claims that Goethe’s search for the archetypes in his perception of natural phenomena is the true form of Platonism.

Page 5 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt

Despite his turn to theosophy and esoteric wisdom at the beginning of the 20th century, Steiner continued to publish works of a philosophical nature. These works tend to restate Steiner’s epistemological position rather than develop it any further. Between 1899 and 1910 Steiner composed Die Rätsel der Philosophie [Riddles of Philosophy],17 which is an overview of philosophical world views from classical Greece to the late nineteenth century. At the conclusion of this work Steiner argues that the future of philosophy does not lie in academic philosophy, but in his anthroposophy. This theme is continued in the lectures collected as Philosophie und Anthroposophie, GA35 in the Gesamtausgabe18, including Philosophie und Anthroposophie (1908)19 and Steiner’s

17 Steiner, R. (1973) Riddles of Philosophy, Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, NY hereinafter RP.

18 Steiner, R. (1984) Philosophie und Anthroposophie GA 35 Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach.

19 Ibid, Philosophie und Anthroposophie pp 66-110 and available in translation as Steiner, R. (undated) Philosophy and Anthroposophy, Kessinger Publishing: USA.

contributions to the 4th International Congress of Philosophy at Bologna in 1911.20 Riddles of Philosophy was reprinted in 1914 and again in 1918, when The Philosophy of Freedom was also reprinted with some significant additions and alterations. Later lectures, such as the series on Thomas Aquinas given in 1919 and available in translation as The Redemption of Thinking,21 restate the argument of Goethe’s World View that Plato’s concept of forms had been misunderstood until Goethe’s endeavours to perceive the archetype.

20 Ibid, Die psychologischen Grundlagen und die erkenntnistheoretische Stellung der Anthroposophie

pp 111-144, Die Theosophie und das Geistesleben der Gegenwart, pp 145-151, Ein Wort über Theosophie auf dem IV. Internationalen Kongreß für Philosophie, pp 152-155.

21 Steiner, R. (1983) The Redemption of Thinking, Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, NY.

22 SK pp 122-123.

Steiner’s claim that it is one and the same epistemological position, which he espouses in all of his work, is repeated in the new edition of his first work, The Science of Knowing, which was published in 1924, forty years after its first appearance. In a note to this largely unaltered edition Steiner says of his position and of philosophy since the 1880’s:22

All these views [of philosophers], after all, presuppose that reality is present somewhere outside of the activity of knowing, and that in the activity of knowing a human, copied representation of this reality is to result, or perhaps cannot result. The fact that this reality cannot be found by knowing activity – because it is first

Page 6 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt made into reality in the activity of knowing – is experienced hardly anywhere. Those who think philosophically seek life and real existence outside of knowing activity; Goethe stands within creative life and real existence by engaging in the activity of knowing. Therefore even the more recent attempts at a world view stand outside the Goethean creation of ideas. Our epistemology wants to stand inside of it, because philosophy becomes a content of life thereby, and an interest in philosophy becomes necessary for life.

Steiner can claim that his epistemological position has remained unchanged, but in the forty years between 1884 and 1924 he had said a great deal else about the nature of life and the cosmos, much of which did little to enhance his reputation as a philosopher.

Secondary sources in English

There is almost no secondary literature in English dealing with Steiner as a philosopher. This is surprising, as Steiner qualifies for entries in the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy and the Penguin Companion to Philosophy, though the emphasis in both these compendia is upon Steiner’s contributions to education and biodynamic agriculture, his involvement with the Theosophical Society and founding of the anthroposophical movement.23 There are occasional passing references to Steiner in studies of some of his contemporaries, such as Brentano, Husserl and Nietzsche.24 Outside of the academy there are many works about Steiner’s way of thinking and his engagement in various aspects of practical life, but these, almost without exception, are uncritical presentations of Steiner’s world view from within the orbit of the Anthroposophical Society or those who are sympathetic to it. Some of these, particularly those by practising scientists25 and the Inkling-group

23See, for example, the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy: … German anthroposophist. Steiner’s doctoral dissertation from Vienna concerned the philosophy of Fichte; he also studied Goethe intensively. He eventually evolved a speculative and oracular metaphysic, anthroposophy, akin to theosophy, and postulating different levels of psychical and astral realms …; and the Penguin entry: … German thinker and theosophist, born in what was then Hungary and is currently Croatia. He held a prominent position in the theosophical movement at the beginning of the century, but broke away to develop an alternative system of thought, and of mental and bodily culture, which he called anthroposophy. Its organizational centre in Dornach (near Basel) in Switzerland is named Goetheanum, a clear indication of the strong influence of Goethe’s nature-philosophy on Steiner, who rejected mainstream mechanistic and materialistic science, which he considered to be at best one-sided and in need of a more organic and spiritual supplementation. Genuine knowledge, he thought, must always include intuitive and aesthetic elements. Although Steiner’s anthroposophical system is replete with esoteric and occult mystifications, impartial observers have found much of value in his ideas for schooling (including an emphasis on the development of children’s aesthetic and creative potential), practised in the so-called Waldorf or Steiner schools. The aim is to assist and encourage a many-sided and harmonious development of the individual’s potential.

24See, for example, Rollinger, R. Brentano and Husserl in Jacquette, D. (2004) Cambridge Companion to

Page 7 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt Brentano, Cambridge UP: Cambridge, pp255-276: [Husserl’s] rejection of mysticism in philosophy is also to be found throughout his comments on Heidegger, Scheler and Steiner as well as others.

25 See, for example, Lehrs, E. (1985) Man or matter? Introduction to a Spiritual Understanding of Nature based upon Goethe’s Method of Training, Observation and Thought, Rudolf Steiner Press: London.

writer and critic Owen Barfield26, do nevertheless demonstrate that Steiner’s way of thinking can be adapted to inform the study of natural science, literature and etymology.

26See, for example, Barfield, O. (1965) Saving the Appearances, Harcourt, Brace and World: New York; (1977) The Rediscovery of Meaning and other Essays, Wesleyan University Press: Middletown, Conn.

27 Welburn, A. (2004) Rudolf Steiner’s Philosophy, Floris Books: Edinburgh.

28 Tarnas, R. (1993) The Passion of the Western Mind, Ballantine Books: New York.

29 Hammer, O. (2004) Claiming Knowledge, Brill: Leiden.

30 Tarnas’ more recent work is entitled : Intimations of a New World View.

This writer has been able to locate only three substantial English-language secondary sources, which overtly purport to locate Steiner’s work within the philosophical tradition. Two of them are sympathetic to Steiner, and one is not. They are Andrew Welburn’s recent Rudolf Steiner’s Philosophy27, Richard Tarnas’ The Passion of the Western Mind28and Olav Hammer’s Claiming Knowledge29. Welburn holds an academic post at Oxford, and it is therefore perhaps noteworthy that his book is not published by a recognised academic publishing house, but by an anthroposophical press, which specialises in religious exegesis. His Rudolf Steiner’s Philosophy offers a comprehensive overview of Steiner’s world view, but it is an insider’s introduction to Anthroposophy for a general audience rather than a critique of Steiner’s philosophical work. Welburn does provide an account of Steiner’s epistemological work, but it is descriptive rather than critical and takes the form of an appendix for the reader with a more specialised interest.

Richard Tarnas is a Californian philosopher, who appears to have a growing interest in the less acknowledged strands of the Western intellectual tradition.30 The Passion of the Western Mind is a broad canvas approach to Western thought from the pre-Socratics to post-modernism. Tarnas is not writing specifically about Steiner, but he accords Steiner a significant role in the development of modern Western thought. Tarnas claims Steiner

as the primary 20th century exponent of an alternative philosophical tradition. Having sketched the inherent problems in Kantian dualism Tarnas introduces Steiner by saying:31

31 Tarnas (1993), p. 433.

Page 8 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt 32Ibid., pp 433-434.

All of this suggests that another, more sophisticated and comprehensive epistemological perspective is called for. Although the Cartesian-Kantian epistemological position has been the dominant paradigm of the modern mind, it has not been the only one, for at almost precisely the same time that the Enlightenment reached its philosophical climax in Kant, a radically different epistemological perspective began to emerge – first visible in Goethe with his study of natural forms, developed in new directions by Schiller, Schelling, Hegel, Coleridge, and Emerson, and articulated within the past century by Rudolf Steiner. Each of these thinkers gave his own distinct emphasis to the developing perspective, but common to all was a fundamental conviction that the relation of the human mind to the world was ultimately not dualistic but participatory.

In the following paragraphs Tarnas qualifies his claim that what is being put forward is a radically different epistemological perspective by identifying it as a variant of critical idealism, which appears to encompass Fichtean subjective idealism, Schelling’s nature- philosophy and Hegelian absolutism. The position which Tarnas claims Steiner has articulated within the last century is the following:32

In essence this alternative conception did not oppose the Kantian epistemology but rather went beyond it, subsuming it in a larger and subtler understanding of human knowledge. The new conception fully acknowledged the validity of Kant’s critical insight, that all human knowledge of the world is in some sense determined by subjective principles; but instead of considering these principles as belonging ultimately to the separate human subject, and therefore not grounded in the world independent of human cognition, this participatory conception held that these subjective principles are in fact an expression of the world’s own being, and that the human mind is ultimately the organ of the world’s own process of self- revelation. In this view, the essential reality of nature is not separate, self- contained, and complete in itself, so that the human mind can examine it objectively and register it from without. Rather, nature’s unfolding truth emerges only with the active participation of the human mind.

In addition to the claim that this alternative conception acknowledges the validity of Kant’s critical insight and goes beyond it, Tarnas claims that it overcomes the evident

problems arising from the dualism inherent in any form of transcendental idealism. Tarnas characterizes Steiner’s alternative conception as a modern form of participatory consciousness:33

33 Ibid., pp 434-435.

Page 9 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt 34 The others are the Theosophy of Helena Blavatsky, the neo-theosophist Alice Bailey, the mentalist Edgar Cayce and a cluster of representatives of the broadly described New Age movement.

This participatory epistemology, developed in different ways by Goethe, Hegel, Steiner, and others, can be understood not as a regression to na„ve participation mystique, but as the dialectical synthesis of the long evolution from the primordial undifferentiated consciousness through the dualistic alienation. It incorporates the postmodern understanding of knowledge and yet goes beyond it. The interpretive and constructive character of human cognition is fully acknowledged, but the intimate, interpenetrating and all-permeating relationship of nature to the human being and human mind allows the Kantian consequence of epistemological alienation to be entirely overcome.

Although Tarnas clearly locates Steiner within the mainstream philosophical tradition, and adds some weight to the argument for Steiner to be taken seriously as a philosopher, he, too, does not offer any critical analysis of Steiner’s epistemological contributions.

Olav Hammer is a Swedish philosopher of religion working in Denmark, whose field of research includes an interest in what he calls the Modern Esoteric Tradition. Hammer sees this tradition as commencing with the foundation of the Theosophical Society in 1880 and stretching to the various manifestations of the New Age movement of the 1970s and beyond. Claiming Knowledge is a critique of five forms of modern esotericism, all of which claim knowledge of essences on the basis of reconstituted histories and traditions, supposedly scientific arguments and the immediacy of personal experience. One of these traditions is Steiner’s Anthroposophy.34 Although Hammer’s interest is in the cosmological, mystical and pseudo-religious aspects of Steiner’s legacy, his study does also acknowledge and discuss Steiner as a neo-Kantian. Hammer purports to be

neither sympathetic to nor dismissive of his subjects, but the criterion against which the respective traditions are measured is the empirical science of the Enlightenment. As a consequence Hammer criticises Steiner’s epistemological position without examining the arguments for it.

In addition to these three books there are recent papers published in journals or delivered at conferences, which attempt to relate Steiner’s epistemological work to more familiar trends in contemporary Continental philosophy. These papers include, for example, studies of Goethean science with allusion to Steiner and a comparison between Steiner’s concept of intuitive thinking and the re-examination of thinking in the later works of Heidegger.35 Again, however, this writer has not been able to find any papers which offer a critical analysis of Steiner’s position.

35See, for example, Fischer, L. (2011) Goethe contra Hegel: The Question of the End of Art, Goethe Yearbook XVIII pp127-156; Dahlin, B. and Majorek, M. (2008) On the path towards thinking: learning

Page 10 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt from Martin Heidegger and Rudolf Steiner, EERA Conference in Gothenburg, Info3 Verlag; Frankfurt am Main.

Secondary sources in German

There is a significantly larger secondary literature in German on Steiner as a philosopher. Most of the material until quite recently is, like the English language corpus, merely explicatory. It, too, is mostly written by anthroposophists or others committed to Steiner’s world view. With few exceptions it does not attempt to offer any critique of Steiner’s arguments and his epistemological position. One exceptional writer is Michael Muschalle, who has published books, articles and an online newsletter, which attempt to acknowledge and to respond to the philosophical problems in Steiner’s epistemology. Commencing with his doctoral thesis, Die Beobachtung des Denkens [The Observation of

Thinking],36 through numerous articles37 and to his most recent Beobachtung des Denkens bei Rudolf Steiner38 [Rudolf Steiner’s Observation of Thinking] Muschalle explores the philosophical issues, which emerge from Steiner’s view of the nature of thinking. Another recent contributor to Steiner exegesis is Michael Kirn, whose books Das grosse Denk-Ereignis [The Turning Point in Thinking] and Freiheit im Leib? [Physically Free?]39 are explorations of the philosophical implications of the first three chapters of Philosophy of Freedom. Marcello da Veiga Greuel’s Wirklichkeit und Freiheit [Reality and Freedom]40 is a comparative study of the concepts and methodologies of Fichte’s and Steiner’s epistemologies. Although da Veiga Greuel is clearly sympathetic to Steiner Wirklichkeit und Freiheit is the closest attempt this writer has found to a critique of Steiner from within the context of the idealist tradition. Marek Majorek, the co-author of one of the recent papers mentioned earlier, has published a work on the concept of objectivity, in which he argues for Steiner’s spiritual science from within the context of objectivity as a philosophical problem.41 In addition to these efforts to place Steiner within his philosophical context there are criticisms of Steiner’s epistemology from those attached to a perspective which it appears to challenge.42 The German secondary literature appears to have reached the stage at which Steiner’s epistemological work is

36 Muschalle, M. (1988) Die Beobachtung des Denkens: Universitaet Bielefeld: online.

37 See, for example, Muschalle, M. (2007) Goethe, Kant und das intuitive Denken in Rudolf Steiners Philosophie der Freiheit, Studien zur Anthroposophie: online; (2009) The Causality of Thinking, trans. T. Boardman and G. Savier: online.

38 Muschalle, M. (2007) Beobachtung des Denkens bei Rudolf Steiner: Books on Demand GmbH: Norderstedt.

39 Kirn, M. (1998) Das grosse Denk-Ereignis, Verlag am Goetheanum: Dornach; (1999) Freiheit im Leib?, Verlag am Goetheanum: Dornach.

40 Veiga Greuel, M. da (1990) Wirklichkeit und Freiheit, Gideon Spicker Verlag: Dornach.

41 Majorek, M. (2002) Objektivitaet: ein Erkenntnisideal auf dem Prüfstand – Rudolf Steiners

Page 11 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt Geisteswissenschaft als ein Ausweg aus der Sackgasse [Objectivity: An ideal of knowledge on trial – Rudolf Steiner’s Spiritual Science as a Way out of the Dead End], Francke Verlag: Tuebingen & Basel.

42 See, for example, Dilloo-Heidger, E. (2005) Projekt: Grundlagen der Anthroposophie, www.dilloo.de/anthroindex.htm; Dilloo-Heidger’s project is to assess Steiner’s early work hermeneutically, and without reference to Steiner’s claims to intuitive sources for knowledge of higher worlds.

now the subject of serious intellectual argument. Even within the German corpus, however, there still seems to be little attempt to subject Steiner’s philosophical arguments to critical analysis.

Secondary sources in other languages

Although the largest part of the literature about Rudolf Steiner and Anthroposophy is written in German and English, there is a growing literature in other languages, including Dutch, French, Italian, Spanish, the Scandinavian languages and Polish, Hungarian and Russian. Most of the works this writer could decipher are translations of Steiner’s primary texts or of secondary literature already long available in German and English.43

43 The author visited the library at the Goetheanum, which houses collections in these other languages.

44 Steiner frequently cites Volkelt, and often refers to Cohen and Windelband.

The Kantian context

In this dissertation the view has been taken that Steiner’s epistemological work is best considered as a response to Kantian transcendental idealism, although Steiner would not have regarded himself as a neo-Kantian. The citations in his early works demonstrate that he was very familiar with the orientations of the Marburg and Baden schools of neo- Kantianism, though he distanced himself from them.44 His philosophical positions seem to have been most strongly influenced by his personal contacts with Brentano and von Hartmann and by his readings of the reinterpretations of Kantian idealism undertaken by Fichte and Schopenhauer. The outcome of these influences upon Steiner has resulted in an approach which Steiner, following on from Brentano, chooses to characterise as phenomenological, but which also bears the hallmarks of strong Idealist tendencies. Steiner is certainly not a phenomenologist in the style of Husserl or even of Brentano, for

it matters to Steiner to acknowledge the limits imposed upon possible knowledge by critical idealism.

Steiner appears to accept Kantian transcendental idealism as the necessary starting point for any epistemological investigation, including his own.45 In his autobiographical The

Page 12 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt Course of my Life, Steiner tells of saving his pocket money to buy the First Critique and reading it surreptitiously at school behind the covers of his history book.46 He then describes the effect the Critique of Pure Reason had upon the development of his own thinking:

45 See, for example, RP p. 445: Security and certainty of knowledge is being sought in many philosophical systems, and Kant’s ideas are more or less taken as its point of departure.

46 CML, p. 33.

47 Ibid., p. 34.

... the question concerning the scope of the human power of thought occupied me constantly. I felt that thinking could be developed into a power that truly includes the things and processes of the world. Subject matter that remains beyond thinking, as something merely reflected upon, was an unbearable idea to me. I told myself again and again that what is in the thing must enter one’s thoughts.

This feeling clashed continually with what I read in Kant, but I hardly noticed this conflict at the time. More than anything, through the Critique of Pure Reason I wanted to obtain a firm foundation that would enable me to come to terms with my own thinking. Whenever I went for walks during the holidays, I had to sit somewhere quiet, and repeatedly make clear to myself the exact process involved in the transition from simple surveyable concepts to mental images of natural manifestations. My attitude toward Kant was very uncritical at the time, but I got no further through him.47

Steiner subsequently distances himself from Kant, but he continues to use Kant’s epistemological architectonic and concepts as the structural framework for his own. In Truth and Knowledge Steiner stakes out his own ground by first criticizing the then widespread acceptance of Kantian thinking within academic philosophy. In Philosophy of Freedom his starting point is to show that any form of transcendental idealism is

untenable. In Riddles of Philosophy, in numerous lectures and in The Course of my Life, Steiner returns time and again to Kant, so as to have a context, within which to explain the positions of other philosophers and to account for his own. Indeed, Steiner seems to regard this as almost inevitable, for he says:

One thing is certain; Kant offered his contemporaries innumerable points for attack and interpretations. Precisely through his unclarities and contradictions, he became the father of the classical German world conceptions of Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, Hegel, Herbart and Schleiermacher. His unclarities became new questions for them. No matter how he endeavoured to limit

Page 13 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt knowledge in order to make place for belief, the human spirit can confess to be satisfied in the true sense of the word only through knowledge, through cognition.48

48RP, p. 122.

49CML, p. 33.

It is something of an irony that the subsequent neglect of Steiner as a philosopher appears to have arisen from his own expectation that the findings of his spiritual science would be regarded as knowledge and accepted on faith.

In Course of My Life Steiner describes his first encounters with the Critique of Pure Reason and his life-long passion to demonstrate that much more is knowable than is acknowledged within critical idealism. He describes his enthusiasm for Kant in the following terms:

While Kant was coming into my sphere of thinking, I was completely ignorant of his position in human intellectual history. All the views of him, whether for or against, were completely unknown to me. My unbounded interest in the Critique of Pure Reason arose entirely from my personal soul life. In my boyish way I tried to understand to what degree human reason is capable of true understanding of the nature of things.49

That enthusiasm had waned by the time Steiner published his doctoral thesis, the Preface for which begins:

Present-day philosophy suffers from an unhealthy faith in Kant. This essay is intended to be a contribution toward overcoming this. It would be wrong to belittle this man’s lasting contributions toward the development of German philosophy and science. But the time has come to recognize that the foundation for a truly satisfying view of the world and of life can be laid only by adopting a position which contrasts strongly with Kant’s.50

50 TK, p. 9.

51 RP, p. 101.

52 CML, p. 112.

Later, in Riddles of Philosophy Steiner says of the Kantian legacy: Kant found an

Page 14 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt answer that saved the truth and certainty of human knowledge by sacrificing human insight into the grounds of the world.51 In The Course of my Life Steiner claims for himself a life-long interest in the problem of knowledge, and sums up his conception of knowledge in this way:

My primary concern in bringing forth my own insights was to refute the theory that there are limits to knowledge. I wanted to reject the path of knowledge that looks at the sensory world and then wants to go outward through the sensory world to break through to true reality. I wanted to show that true reality must be sought by going more deeply into the inner human being, not by attempting to break through toward the outer.52

The driving force of Steiner’s philosophical endeavours is to find a way to retain the truth and certainty of knowledge, and at the same time to justify a human capacity for insight into the grounds of the world.

Steiner therefore sees it as his task to show that the limits Kant imposes upon knowledge can be overcome within the context of the Kantian architectonic. His approach is to apply to Kant’s epistemology two interrelated concepts, which Steiner derives from Goethe and Fichte. From Goethe he takes the idea that it is possible to identify the archetypes, forms or Ideas of the sense-perceptible world within the perceived phenomena. In Kantian terms the thing-in-itself does not lie in some other world, but

is the perceptible phenomenon viewed as an instance of its archetype. The other concept is what Steiner calls intuitive thinking. Kant employed the concept of intuition, but reduced its ambit to what he called sensory intuitions, our constructs of space and time. Fichte expanded intuition to include intellectual intuition, by which he meant the starting point of our conscious processes, the point at which we recognize a separation between ourselves and the given, external world. Steiner adopts Fichte’s derivation of intellectual intuition, and attaches the immediacy, spontaneity and primacy of intuition to the cognitive process of thinking. Steiner’s intuitive thinking is the intellectual process which allows for perception of the archetypes, and which is intended to overcome the ontological distinctions between subject and object, and noumenon and phenomenon.

Dissertation

This dissertation is an examination of Rudolf Steiner’s responses to the limits Kant imposes upon the range of possible human knowledge. The dissertation canvasses the arguments Steiner mounts against the claims of critical idealism, and examines the extent to which those arguments are successful in challenging the conclusions of the critical philosophy. The thesis of the dissertation is that although Steiner is unable to extend the range of possible knowledge from within the context of Kantian idealism he does identify some points in the critical philosophy, from which the search for essences might be

Page 15 8 INTRODUCTION RUDOLF STEINER THE PHILOSOPHER.txt expanded. It is another question, of course, whether Steiner’s inability to arrive at essences from within the neo-Kantian tradition demonstrates a fault in Steiner’s epistemological project or in the enterprise of the critical philosophy.

There are two parts to this dissertation. Part 1 consists of three short introductory chapters. The first of these, Intuition and Archetype, is provided as a background to the two concepts, which are most central to Steiner’s contribution to epistemology. The second, Goethe’s Way of Seeing, describes the methodology of Goethe’s natural science, which Steiner sought to incorporate into Kantian idealism. The third introductory chapter, The Kantian Legacy, describes how Steiner understood the critical project and how he sought to respond to it. Steiner’s responses are described as disjunctions from the critical philosophy.

Part 2 contains four chapters, each of which addresses a disjunction between Kantian critical idealism and Steiner’s epistemological position. The chapters do not entirely follow the order of publication of Steiner’s five main epistemological works. They attempt instead to trace the argument of Steiner’s responses to Kant. The first chapter, Monism and Dualism, examines the fundamental disjunction between Kant and Steiner, namely Steiner’s rejection of the dualism, which is inherent in any form of transcendental idealism. The next two chapters deal with the two concepts Steiner is endeavouring to work into Continental idealism. The second chapter, Perceiving the Archetype, is concerned with Steiner’s attempt to incorporate insights from Goethe’s natural science into the critical philosophy. The third chapter, Intellectual Intuition, deals with Steiner’s extrapolation from Fichte’s intellectual intuition to intuition as an enhanced form of cognition. These two concepts, intuition and archetype, provide the ground from which Steiner then sets out to argue that human beings are spiritually free, and that freedom arises in the creativity of thinking. The final chapter, Intuitive Thinking, addresses Steiner’s concepts of freedom and intuitive thinking, and shows that by the time Steiner

is arguing for intuitive thinking he has moved away from the philosophical tradition and into his spiritual science.

The Conclusion of the dissertation points to recent developments in Continental idealism, which display some similarities to Steiner’s work. They indicate that, although Steiner did not succeed in reformulating critical idealism so that it could become the epistemological ground for his own world view, his disjunctions may have drawn attention to nodal points for further developments within the Kantian tradition.

Page 16 9 PART 1.txt

PART 1

Page 1 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt PART 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE

It will become clear, in the course of this dissertation, that the concepts of intuition [Anschauung] and archetype [Archtyp] play a central role in Steiner’s theory of knowledge. For Steiner there is an inherent connection between the exercise of intuitive thinking and the perception of archetypes. Kant also refers to intuition frequently, and makes occasional reference to archetypes, but his understanding of these concepts is very different from Steiner’s. Both terms are called upon from time to time within the general epistemological lexicon, but they are both to some extent fringe concepts and are prone to ambiguity and misinterpretation. There is also, of course, the issue of translation. When Steiner uses the term Anschauung [intuition] he means something quite different from what Kant means by Anschauung, and in addition Steiner introduces the term Intuition to convey a particular sense of intuition. Steiner’s employment of archetype overlaps with Kant’s use of that term, but it needs to be distinguished from the related Platonic concepts of Idea, Type and Form. Steiner’s archetype is not the same thing, for example, as the Platonic Idea as it is usually understood and as Kant understands it. It seems necessary, therefore, to say something at the outset about what intuition and archetype have been taken to mean in this dissertation.

Intuition

The word intuition is generally used in the sense that it is a mode of coming to know, which has some or all of the characteristics of spontaneity, immediacy, totality and inaccessibility to the processes of rational thinking. These various characteristics, however, can lead to unrelated or even contrary concepts of intuition. Three examples of attempts to define intuition will serve to demonstrate the difficulty in describing what intuition denotes. The first is to be found in the Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, which offers three meanings for intuition:

1. Immediate insight or knowledge, in contrast to insight or knowledge arrived at discursively, by means of analysis or proof. This is how the term is used by Descartes, Locke, Leibniz and Hume. Husserl saw the intuiting of essences as the task of phenomenology. The contrasting term used by Descartes for knowledge by way of analysis or proof was deduction, whereas Locke and Hume used demonstration.

As with other epistemic terms there is an act/content ambiguity: intuition can denote the manner in which something is known, or that which is known in a certain manner.

2. Direct perception of an object. This is roughly the meaning of intuition when used to translate the German Anschauung in Kant and others. According to him we have sensory intuitions, but no non-sensory, intellectual intuitions, and therefore no knowledge of super-empirical facts. On this last point, Fichte and Schelling took the opposite stand.

Page 1 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt

3. Immediate, unreflected belief that we find ready in ourselves as soon as we begin to reflect (Bertrand Russell). Intuitions, in this sense of the word, are simply non- inferential beliefs. But the term is sometimes reserved for non-inferential beliefs which are highly resistant, though not immune, to revision or rejection.1

1 Mautner, T. (2005) The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, Penguin: London, p. 310.

2 Nelson, L. (1970) Progress and Regress in Philosophy, Basil Blackwell: Oxford.

The second example is a discussion of varieties of intuition taken from Leonard Nelson’s Progress and Regress in Philosophy,2 a study of neo-Kantian idealism. Nelson points out the contradictory implications of definitions intuition understood as 1 and 3 above, as feeling and intuition as perception:

People talk of grasping a truth intuitively’. This can mean one of two things. It can express a contrast to logical mediation, i.e. to reaching the truth by inference from some other truth. Thus it may be said that great scientific discoveries or important artistic creations took place intuitively’. It is the contrast with conceptual thought that is intended here.

We must distinguish this feeling-for-truth from another and more appropriate sense of intuition’. If someone says that he has come to know some truth by intuition, this may mean that he can give a perfectly good account of the grounds of his assertion, by reference to perception, i.e. to a definite and immediate knowledge of the object, one which is clear without any reflection. This is just the opposite of the other sense, in which intuition’ denoted a claim to truth for which the claimant knew he could not give the grounds.

We must therefore distinguish two sorts of intuition’ which are confused in common speech and which are not usually separated in psychological analysis: the feeling, first, which is simply our confidence that grounds for our judgment could be found, so that

through a dim awareness of the truth we just take those grounds for granted; and secondly perception, which is a clear, definite and sufficient ground for the judgment.3

3 Ibid, pp88-89, writer’s emphasis.

4 Beck, L. W. (1965) The Fact of Reason: An Essay on Justification in Ethics, in Studies in the Philosophy of Kant, The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc: Indianapolis.

The third comes from Beck. In The Fact of Reason: A Essay on Justification in Ethics Beck is undertaking an analysis of the intuitive answer to what he calls the external question in ethics, the question Why ought I to be moral? In the course of this discussion he engages

Page 2 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt in a more general discussion of intuition, and says:

While these truths are not, of course, seen with one’s physical eyes, the act of apprehending them is more like seeing something than it is like thinking and inferring. To call it seeing is to make use of a metaphor, and all the other words which name it likewise seem to be metaphorical also: Anschauen, intueor, apprehend, grasp, see by the lumen naturale, etc. I shall here use the word intuition to two senses, which I shall distinguish as follows. An intuition in the real sense is a direct apprehension of an objective truth, value, or state of affairs. An intuition in the putative sense is an act which seems to be a real intuition but which in fact may or may not be.

... I submit that all we have in the way of data are intuitions in the putative sense, that contradictory judgments of intuitions in the putative sense exist, and that there is no valid intuitive means by which real intuitions can be distinguished from putative intuitions.4

Beck’s distinction between putative intuitions and real intuitions highlights the strength of the Kantian position by emphasising the looseness and uncertainty of intuitions, that is, of particular beliefs as to facts or values.

These various definitions provide some assistance in teasing out what Kant and Steiner mean by intuition, but they also demonstrate why it is so difficult to come to a clear understanding of what the term means. The distinction Nelson draws between intuition as feeling and intuition as perception is clear until we consider the elaborations of that distinction in the Penguin definitions. In the first definition, for example, intuition is defined as immediate insight or knowledge, in contrast to insight or knowledge arrived at discursively ..., and it is thereby being described as the content of something which is known, rather than as the

manner of knowing. The difficulty is that the term insight itself suffers from exactly the same ambiguity as intuition, in that it, likewise, can denote both a manner of knowing and the content of something known. It is true that we do not use insight as a transitive verb, though we do say we can see into something. Insight is, however, a more literal translation than intuit and intuition of the German anschauen [verb] and Anschauung [noun]. It does not make things any clearer, therefore, to define intuition in terms of insight.

The second definition is an attempt to present intuition in the way Kant uses the term, but it, too, bundles together intuition as an act and intuition as content. The characterisation of intuition as direct perception of an object could refer to either, but the remainder of the definition limits intuition to the content of a process, namely the direct perception of a sensory fact. This definition of intuition is doubly unfortunate, in that it bears little resemblance to our everyday use of the term, and nor does it convey accurately what Kant means by intuition. Indeed, this attempt at a definition suggests a limited understanding of the Kantian project, which is to account for how it is, in the absence of a faculty for intellectual intuition, that we do have knowledge of super-empirical facts.

The third definition is the non-technical meaning of intuition, which constitutes what Russell calls a non-inferential belief. This vernacular use of the term takes the form of expressions such as I had an intuition that you’d arrive today or She knew what to get for his birthday, she’s very intuitive, and is not so much a non-inferential belief as a non-

Page 3 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt inferential judgment. That is, intuition in this sense does not take the form of belief as opposed to knowledge, but is knowledge arrived at by the conjunction of ideas or concepts in a non-inferential judgment. Intuition, in this sense, is yet to be the subject of an epistemological investigation, and it is not what either Kant or Steiner means by intuition.

Steiner’s concept of intuition in his epistemological work accords with the first of the Penguin definitions, in that it emphasises the characteristics of knowledge known immediately and spontaneously, and allows for the existence of a faculty of intellectual intuition. Intuition is generally a translation of Anschauung in Steiner’s texts, but it should be noted that, in certain sections of Philosophy of Freedom, Steiner also uses the word Intuition. This writer has not been able to determine whether Steiner intends something different when he uses Intuition rather than Anschauung in this context. There is another context, however, in which Steiner does employ the term Intuition in a quite specific and idiosyncratic way. In his later, anthroposophical works Steiner uses the term Intuition to denote the final stage in the practice of spiritual science, following on from Imagination and Inspiration.5

5 See, for example, Steiner, R. (1976) Knowledge of Higher Worlds: How is it achieved? Rudolf Steiner Press: London; (1997) An Outline of Esoteric Science, Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, N. Y.

6CPR, A19, B33 p. 65: In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed. But intuition takes place only in so far as the object is given to us.

7 Ibid, B35-B36 pp 66-67: I term all representations pure (in the transcendental sense) in which there is nothing that belongs to sensation. ... In the course of this investigation it will be found that there are two pure forms of sensible intuitions, serving as principles of a priori knowledge, namely space and time.

8 Ibid, A734, B762 p590: Mathematics … derives its knowledge not from concepts but from the construction of them, that is, from intuition, which can be given a priori in accordance with the concepts.

Kant’s use of the term is also somewhat idiosyncratic. He begins the Critique of Pure Reason with a definition of intuition6, describes space and time as intuitions [Anschauungen] and as pure representations, and as our only pure sensible intuitions.7 The remainder of our sensory intuitions are then described as having specific content within a spatiotemporal manifold, and these are the direct perceptions of an object to which the second dictionary definition refers. The other sense in which Kant speaks of intuitions relates to the formation of mathematical concepts.8 For Kant intuitions are immediate and singular, in contrast with

concepts, which are mediated and general.9 There is some further development of the concept of intuition in the Third Critique, but Kant is consistent in denying human consciousness the capacity for non-sensory intellectual (non mathematical) intuition, which is only available to God.10 In his A Kant Dictionary Howard Caygill points out that Kant’s concept of intuition is a radical departure from Descartes and Spinoza, for both of whom

Page 4 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt intuition existed as a distinct form of knowledge.11 Caygill argues that Kant’s concept of intuition amounts to a refinement of Aristotle’s use of the term12, but it is nevertheless an unconventional application of it.

9 CPR, A320, B377 p. 314. For Kant the singularity of intuitions is a further reason there can be no intellectual intuitions for human cognition.

10 Ibid, B72, p 90: ... intellectual intuition seems to belong solely to the primordial being, and can never be ascribed to a dependent being, which through that intuition determines its existence solely in relation to given objects.

11 Caygill, H. (1995) A Kant Dictionary, Blackwell Publishers Ltd: Oxford pp 262-266.

12 Ibid. p 266: … the critical philosophy both respects the received Aristotelian distinction, while reconfiguring it in accordance with a doctrine of intuition which combines sensible and intelligible aspects.

Archetype

The concept of archetype will be familiar as a translation of the Platonic notion of the form or Idea, which is claimed by Platonists to lie behind the sense-perceptible phenomenon. For this reason it will generally be associated with the Platonic or the Idealist tradition, or perhaps with the Kantian notion of the thing-in-itself. Steiner’s understanding of archetype comes, however, from Goethe’s use of the term in his scientific studies, and for Steiner the archetype is almost the antithesis of Kant’s thing-in-itself: the archetype is perceptible and knowable, while the thing-in-itself is neither. Again, in an attempt to clarify what archetype is intended to mean in this dissertation, two definitions of archetype are offered for consideration. They also demonstrate both the inherent difficulties in the term archetype and the consequent lack of attention to it. The definitions are taken from the Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy and Howard Caygill’s A Kant Dictionary.

The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy gives three accounts for archetype, the first of which relates to its use in epistemology, and describes various uses of the term as follows:13

13 Mautner, op. cit., p 40.

14 Caygill, op. cit., pp 83-84.

The concept occurs in Descartes, Malebranche, Cudworth, Locke, Berkeley and others. In the Meditations (III, 33), Descartes insists that a series of ideas that generate one another must have a beginning in an archetype. Locke uses the word pattern’ as a synonym, and takes an archetype to be that to which our ideas must conform in order to be adequate (Essay Concerning Human Understanding 2,20,1); but he also holds that most complex ideas are archetypes of the mind’s own making (4,4,5). In Malebranche and Berkeley, archetypes are ideas in God’s mind, independently of and prior to their being perceived by a human mind. Correlated term: ectype. An ectype relates to an archetype as a copy to its original.

Page 5 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt It will be seen that the kind of archetype to which Malebranche, Berkeley and Descartes refer distinguishes between what is available to human cognition and what must be presumed to emanate from outside of human cognition, while Locke uses the term to describe the relationship between ideas and perceptions and ideas and each other. The Dictionary of Philosophy definition does not associate archetype with the Platonic Idea, and there is no mention of what archetype means for Kant. Nor is it suggested that archetypes are realities, as they are for Goethe and Steiner, and by whom they are said to be available to heightened forms of human perception.

Caygill, again, describes two ways in which Kant uses the term archetype - one relating to the Platonic notion of forms, and the other to the archetype as a model for emulation of ethical behaviour. Caygill says the following:14

The archetype [archetypon, Urbild] for Kant is to the ectype as original is to copy, or as the possible holistic understanding of an intellectus archetypus to a discursive understanding that has need of images [intellectus ectypus]’ (CJ s77). Underlying these distinctions is a critical engagement with Platonism. In CPR Kant criticized Plato’s mystical deduction’ of the ideas’ which hypostatized them by making them into the archetypes of the things themselves’ (CPR A 313/B 370). Kant claims that Plato’s flight from the ectypal mode of reflecting upon the physical world-order to the architectonic ordering of it according to ends, that is, according to ideas’ (CPR A 318/ B 375) makes regulative principles’ for the systematic completion of knowledge into constitutive principles of the origin of things. Kant’s critique of Plato’s practical

philosophy follows similar lines, by arguing for an idea of the good which would serve as a regulative principle for any judgment as to moral worth’ but which would not itself be an archetype. Yet this principle can serve as an archetype when it serves as an ideal for imitation. In CPR Kant describes the wise man of the stoics as just such an archetype which serves for the complete determination of the copy; and we have no other standard for our actions than the conduct of this divine man within us, with which we compare and judge ourselves, and so reform ourselves, although we can never attain to the perfection thereby prescribed’ (CPR A 569/ B 597).

Caygill’s discussion of the ways in which Kant uses the term archetype provides some explanation, but does not mention Kant’s more extensive discussions of Platonic Ideas, ideals and archetypes in the later sections of the First Critique. In the first chapter of the Transcendental Dialectic, The Ideal of Pure Reason, Kant identifies what he means by an ideal with what Plato calls an Idea and relates both of these to the concept of an archetype.15

15 *

16 CPR A 811, B 839, p. 639: It is … only in the ideal of the supreme original good that pure reason can find the ground of this connection, which is necessary from the practical point of view, between the two elements of the supreme derivative good – the ground, namely, of an intelligible, that is, moral world. Now since we are necessarily constrained by reason to represent ourselves as belonging to such a world, while the senses present

Page 6 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt to us nothing but a world of appearances, we must assume that moral world to be a consequence of our conduct in the world of sense … and therefore to be for us a future world. Thus God and the future life are two postulates which, according to the principles of pure reason, are inseparable from the obligation which that same reason imposes upon us.

17 CPR A 838, B866, p. 657: Philosophy is the system of all philosophical knowledge. If we are to understand by it the archetype for the estimation of all attempts at philosophizing, and if this archetype is to serve for the

This thesis does not examine the other sense in which Kant uses the term archetype, archetype as moral exemplar, but it is interesting to note that in The Canon of Pure Reason of the First Critique Kant appears to engage in what might be called the archetypal thinking Steiner sets out to describe. Kant is providing the rational grounds for belief in God and an afterlife, and argues to the existence of a supreme being from the practical possibility of the supreme good, and the reality of a future life from the fact of a moral world independent of the world of the senses.16 In the following Architectonic of Pure Reason Kant is delineating the varieties of philosophy and uses the term archetype to characterise the idea of each particular field of knowledge. Kant’s use of archetype in these contexts appears to be consistent with the Platonic usage.17

estimation of each subjective philosophy, the structure of which is often so diverse and liable to alteration, it must be taken objectively. Thus regarded, philosophy is a mere idea of a possible science which nowhere exists in concreto, but to which, by many different paths, we eneavour to approximate, until the one true path … has achieved likeness to the archetype, so far as this is granted to [mortal] man.

18NOS, p. 45.

19Ibid., pp166 - 191.

20 GWV, pp 10-74.

Steiner refers to archetypes and archetypal thinking frequently. The concept of the archetype as the form or Idea of the phenomena plays a central role in Steiner’s epistemological works and arises from his studies of Goethe’s approach to nature. There is a discussion of Kant’s distinction between the intellectus ectypus and the intellectus archetypus in the fourth of Steiner’s introductions to Goethe’s nature studies,18 and a comprehensive account of the distinction Steiner draws between types, archetypes and Ideas in the 16th introduction.19 The last of Steiner’s epistemological studies, Goethe’s World View, contains an extended argument for a reinterpretation of Plato’s concept of the archetype along the lines of Goethe’s Urphaenomenon.20 To put it in Kantian terms, Steiner’s presentation of the archetype is an attempt to collapse the distinction between regulative principles and constitutive principles,

Page 7 10 Part 1 Chapter 1 INTUITION AND ARCHETYPE.txt and to ground the archetype as a regulative principle within the phenomena. Some of the background to Goethe’s concept of archetype is contained in Part 1 Chapter 2 following, and Steiner’s understanding of the archetype is developed in Part 2 Chapter 4.

Page 8 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt PART 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE’S WAY OF SEEING

When he finished his studies in natural science at the University of Vienna in 1882, Rudolf Steiner took up an offer to be the editor of Goethe’s scientific works in Joseph Kürschner’s National German Literature. Steiner was engaged on this project until 1890 in Vienna, and then undertook similar work in Weimar as the editor of the scientific section of the Weimar edition of Goethe’s collected works at the Goethe-Schiller archives until he left Weimar for Berlin in 1897.1 Steiner published all of his primary epistemological works over this period. It is not surprising, then, that Goethe’s scientific essays can be identified as one of the principal sources upon which Steiner draws for his responses to the epistemology of the critical philosophy. From early on Steiner was convinced that the methodology Goethe had employed in observing natural phenomena provided a way to reach beyond the limits to knowledge imposed by Kantian idealism. The holism of Goethe’s approach to natural science also provided Steiner with an intellectual grounding for his inherent aversion to dualism and to the Kantian notion that human consciousness does not have access to knowledge of essences. As Steiner’s epistemological arguments depend so much upon what he has taken from Goethe’s phenomenology of nature it seems necessary, at this stage, to provide some background about Goethe’s natural science and the methodology for the investigation of nature which Steiner claims to have derived from it.

1CML, pp77-121.

1. Goethe’s concept of natural science

Although J. W. von Goethe is most known for his lyric poetry, his version of the Faust legend and his other literary achievements, Goethe himself regarded his essays into the

investigation of nature as his greatest contribution to human culture. Like philosophers and other intellectuals of the time, including Kant2 and many of the post-Kantians, Goethe kept abreast of the rapid advances in science and technology of the late 18th and early 19th centuries, and contributed to scientific debates and discussions. Goethe’s orientation to natural phenomena was, however, much more practical than philosophical. He gathered botanical specimens from the garden of his summer house, collected and classified bones and minerals, attended anatomy lectures, performed autopsies and experiments in light and optics, and corresponded with other amateur and professional scientists. When it came to developing a theory to account for his observations Goethe’s initial response was to turn to Kant for an explanatory method.3 Later on, however, it became apparent that Goethe’s research method was very much at odds with Kant’s and that of other contemporary scientists and philosophers.

2 Kant had a particular interest in cosmology. His earlier work included an extensive treatise on the movement of the stars, which is acknowledged in references to the Kant-Laplace primordial nebula.

Page 1 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

3 Goethe, J. Campaign in France, cited in Naydler, J. (2000) Goethe on Science, hereinafter GOS, pp 57- 58: In Kant’s scientific writings I have grasped the idea that attraction and repulsion are essential constituents of matter and that neither can be divorced from the other in the concept of matter. This led me to the recognition of polarity as a basic feature of all creation, a principle permeating and animating the infinite range of phenomena.

4 Bacon, F. Novum Organum 1, 46.265 cited in Quinton, A. (1980) Francis Bacon, OUP: Oxford: The human understanding, when any proposition has been once laid down … forces everything else to add fresh support and confirmation; and although most cogent and abundant instances may exist to the contrary, yet either does not observe or despises them, or gets rid of and rejects them by some distinction, with violent and injurious prejudice, rather than sacrifice the authority of its first conclusions.

5 It is noteworthy that Kant dedicates the First Critique to Bacon and cites Bacon’s Great Instauration.

The research method for natural science which had come to be widely adopted by Goethe’s time was the eliminative induction,4 which had grown out of Francis Bacon’s Novum Organum and other scientific treatises, and had been so successful in precipitating the advancement of science and technology throughout the Enlightenment.5 This method emphasizes quantitative analysis of observations, and focuses therefore upon spatial

measurement and systematic categorization as the primary tools for the investigation of natural phenomena. Goethe reacted strongly against the notion that the scientific study of nature should be founded only upon the assessment of quantities, and that what are termed the secondary qualities of nature, such as colour, smell and taste, should be regarded as unscientific and subjective, and be relegated to forming the subject matter of poetry and art. For Goethe art and science were interdependent, and to him it seemed unscientific and irrational to look to measuring instruments rather than the finely tuned sensibilities of the human organism to explain natural phenomena.6 The gap between Goethe’s approach to nature and conventional science grew to the point that, in his late work on colour, the Farbenlehre [Theory of Colour]7, Goethe lampoons the methodology and the conclusions of Newton’s Optics and, in more general terms, criticises the scientific method of the Enlightenment.8

6 Goethe, J. The Human Being is the most exact Instrument cited in GOS, p. 29: In so far as we make use of our healthy senses, the human being is the most powerful and exact scientific instrument possible.

7 Goethe, J. (1970) Theory of Colours, MIT Press: Cambridge, Mass.

8Goethe’s approach to the observation of phenomena has found much more favour with 20th century physicists than it did with his contemporaries and their successors. The expansion of physics from Newton’s laws to relativity, quantum mechanics and Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle has demanded of physicists that they take account of the subject, as well, in the interpretation of subatomic phenomena. Heisenberg was himself aware of Goethe’s scientific work, and the implications of it. Referring to Goethe’s polemic against Newton he writes in Heisenberg (1979) Philosophic Problems of Quantum Physics, Ox Bow Press: Woodbridge, Connecticut: It would be superficial to neglect this struggle as unimportant; there is a good reason for one of the most eminent of men using all his power to combat the

Page 2 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt achievement of Newton’s optics. One can only charge Goethe with a lack of consistency. He should not only have combated Newton’s views but he should have said that the whole of Newton’s physics, optics, mechanics and gravitational theory was the work of the devil.

In his accounts of his observations of nature and his occasional essays into the methodology of natural science Goethe claims it is possible to engage in a qualitative approach to natural phenomena, which is nevertheless scientific. He also claims that the

proper study of nature requires the development of enhanced mental powers9 and the opening up of new organs10 of thinking and of perception. According to Goethe the scientific observer is obligated to engage in a process of inner transformation herself along with the phenomena which are being observed.11 This is an attitude towards the undertaking of scientific enquiry which is evidently completely at odds with the purportedly objective stance of conventional science.

9 GOS, p. 72: There is a delicate empiricism which makes itself utterly identical with the object, becoming true theory. But this enhancement of our mental powers belongs to a highly evolved age, citing Goethe, J. (1823) Maximen und Reflexionen, HA 12.509

10 Ibid, p. 102: Every new object, clearly seen, opens up a new organ of perception in us, citing Goethe, J.(1823) Bedeutende Foerdenis, HA 13.41-42

11Ibid, p. 50: When something has acquired a form it metamorphoses immediately to a new one. If we wish to arrive at some living perception of Nature we ourselves must remain as quick and flexible as Nature and follow the example she gives, citing Goethe, J. (1817) Die Absicht eingeleitet, HA 13.54-56

12 Goethe, J. Einwirkung der neuen Philosophie [Effects of the New Philosophy] in Sämtliche Werke in Max Hesses Verlag, vol 40, p. 27: Für Philosophie im eigentlichen Sinne hatte ich kein Organ

13 Ibid, pp 27-30.

14 Goethe, J. (1978) The Metamorphosis of Plants, op. cit., pp 51-53.

15 Foerster, E. (2001) Goethe and the Auge des Geistes, Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte pp 87-101.

Goethe claimed to have had no organ for philosophy12 but was, in fact, very familiar with contemporary developments in philosophical thinking, including Kant’s critical philosophy.13 He corresponded with Fichte, and was on friendly terms with Hegel. Goethe came to reject the Linnaean system of classifying plants, and Linnaeus’ theory of anticipation14, but that was only after he had, himself, made thousands of detailed drawings and descriptions of natural phenomena. His objection to the style of thinking underlying the philosophy and science of his time was a belief that it did injustice both to the object of observation and to the observer. Goethe subsequently shared this concern with those Romantics and post-Kantians, such as Schelling and Hegel, who also rejected

Page 3 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt the methodology of the science of their times, but for very different reasons.15 Unlike these Naturphilosophen, however, Goethe opposed orthodox science not for its emphasis

upon careful observation, but for what he saw as its failure to observe carefully enough: its failure to take proper account of the activities of the observer in the observation, and the effect those activities had upon the information one could draw from the phenomena. The organ for philosophy Goethe claimed to have lacked was what he saw as the propensity of both the Kantians and their nature-philosophy opponents to theorise about natural phenomena rather than to engage with them. The claim made by Steiner and others who regard Goethe as a significant natural scientist16 is that Goethe had the capacity to perceive the idea within the phenomena, and to enter into sense-perceptible phenomena in such a way as to participate in the phenomenology of nature.

16 , a physicist, and Craig Holdrege, a biologist, co-editors of two recent collections of essays on Goethean science, are scientists who promote Goethe’s methodology as a legitimate scientific method.

17 Rorty, R. (1979) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton U.P.: Princeton, p. 367: On the periphery of the history of modern philosophy, one finds figures who, without forming a tradition, resemble each other in their distrust of the notion that man’s essence is to be a knower of essences. Goethe, Kierkegaard, Santayana, William James, Dewey, the later Wittgenstein, the later Heidegger, are figures of this sort. Goethe was not a systematiser, but Rorty is mistaken to claim that Goethe did not seek to be a knower of essences.

18 Cassirer, E. (1979) The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, Princeton U.P.: Princeton.

19 Cassirer, E. (1970) Rousseau Kant Goethe, Princeton UP: Princeton pp 61-97.

20 Cassirer, E. (1974) The Problem of Knowledge, Yale U.P.: New Haven.

In addition to Steiner there are some philosophers who have acknowledged Goethe’s contribution to natural science and there has been a recent trend amongst some scientists to rehabilitate Goethe’s scientific method. Of the philosophers Richard Rorty in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature17 classes Goethe as one of his few edifying philosophers and Ernst Cassirer in The Philosophy of the Enlightenment18, Rousseau Kant Goethe19 and in The Problem of Knowledge20 explores the relationship between the critical philosophy and Goethe’s way of looking at the world. Rorty does not explain, however, what it is about Goethe’s way of seeing that earns Goethe his approbation, nor

why he qualifies Goethe as a philosopher at all. Cassirer, similarly, does not develop the epistemological implications of Goethe’s scientific work nor the interplay between Goethe’s methodology and the critical philosophy. Instead, in The Philosophy of the Enlightenment Cassirer focuses upon an apparent harmony between the aesthetics of the

Page 4 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt Critique of Judgment and Goethe’s poetic works21, and in Rousseau Kant Goethe, upon the tension between Kant’s mathematical metaphysics of nature and Goethe’s natural science22. In The Problem of Knowledge Cassirer does, however, hit upon a feature of Goethe’s way of seeing with epistemological implications when he says:

21Cassirer, E. (1979), op. cit., pp 277-278; there is also considerable tension between Kant’s analysis of the capacity for judgment and Goethe’s concept of anschauende Urteilskraft [intuitive judgment].

22 Cassirer, E. (1970), op. cit., p. 62 describes Goethe’s approach as …one continuous attack upon Newton and Newtonian physics. This is something of an overstatement, for until the Theory of Colour Goethe’s attack was not so much on Newton, or even on Newtonian physics, as on the tendency in the science of his time to exclude qualities from scientific examination.

23 Cassirer, E. (1974), op. cit. p. 146.

24 Steiner, R. (2000) Nature’s Open Secret, op. cit., pp 86-87: Art was for [Goethe] one revelation of the primal lawfulness of the world, science the other. For him, art and science spring from a single source. Whereas researchers delve into the depths of reality to formulate its driving forces in the form of thoughts, artists seek to imbue their medium with these same driving forces.

25 Foerster, E. (2001) , op. cit., pp 87-101.

There prevails in his writings a relationship of the particular to the universal such as can hardly be found elsewhere in the history of philosophy or of natural science.23

Steiner says something similar in Nature’s Open Secret 24 and Foerster develops the interconnection between Goethe and the post-Kantians in Goethe and the Auge des Geistes.25

The recent trend amongst some natural scientists to rehabilitate Goethe as a scientist has come a century and a half after Goethe’s death in 1832. Between then and Steiner’s editorial introductions of the 1880’s and 1890’s Goethe’s scientific works were not taken

seriously by many thinkers,26 but over the last 30 years or so there has been a significant reassessment of Goethe’s scientific work. Recent studies of Goethean science include the sets of papers published as Goethe’s Way of Science27 in 1998 and Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism published in 200828. Many of the authors of these papers refer to Steiner’s work in bringing about recognition of Goethe’s contribution to scientific enquiry.29 It is probable that popular works such as Sheldrake’s The Rebirth of Nature30 have also been influenced by Steiner’s articulation of Goethe’s way of seeing. There are numerous works by science teachers from Rudolf Steiner schools which present Goethe’s approach to the study of nature.31 Overall it might be said that Goethe’s scientific work is now sufficiently in the public eye to be the subject of critical assessment.32 The gravamen of Steiner’s presentation of Goethe as a scientist is the claim that Goethe was able to steer a

Page 5 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt safe and intellectually sustainable course between the Scylla of scientific, but incomplete, empiricism and the Charybdis of participatory, but inexact, mental imaging.

26 Exceptions included Samuel Taylor Coleridge, who translated Goethe and promoted his scientific work, and the naturalist T. H. Huxley, who used a poem of Goethe’s to introduce the first edition of the magazine Nature in 1869.

27Seamon, D. & Zajonc, A. (eds) (1998) Goethe’s Way of Science, SUNY: New York.

28 Bywater, B. & Holdrege, C. (eds) (2005) Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism, Trivium Publications: Amherst, New York.

29 Holdrege, C. Doing Goethean Science; Wahl, D. Zarte Empirie: Goethean Science as a Way of Knowing; Sims, E-M. Goethe, Husserl and the Crisis of the European Sciences; and Root, C. The Proteus Within: Thoreau’s Practice of Goethe’s Phenomenology in Bywater, B. & Holdrege, C., op. cit., refer to Steiner’s contribution.

30 Sheldrake, N. (1990) The Rebirth of Nature, Century: London.

31 See, for example, Bortoft, H. (1996) The Wholeness of Nature, Lindisfarne Books: Great Barrington, Mass.; Edelglass, S. (2006) The Physics of Human Experience, Adonis Press: Hillsdale, NY.

32 Goethe claimed credit for the discovery of the intermaxillary bone in the human skeleton. Both the claims that there is a human intermaxillary bone and that the discovery was Goethe’s have been challenged in Wells, G. (1967) Goethe and the Intermaxillary Bone, The British Journal for the History of Science, vol 3, no 12 pp 348-361.

2. Goethe’s nature studies

Goethe’s scientific writings include occasional essays, notes and aphorisms on science and scientific method, longer essays on plant and animal morphology, and treatises on optics and the theory of colour. The longer essays and the treatises contain detailed descriptions of Goethe’s observations and the results of his exhaustive experimentation. Many of the catch-phrases which are said to distinguish Goethe’s scientific method from the conventional are contained in shorter notes and occasional commentaries. Goethe’s major scientific works include Die Metamorphosen der Pflanzen [The Metamorphosis of Plants] (1790)33, his essay on method, Der Versuch als Vermittler von Objekt und Subjekt [The Experiment as Mediator between Object and Subject] (1793)34, Osteologie (Osteology) (1795), Morphologie [Morphology] (1807)35, and the Farbenlehre [Theory of Colour] (1810)36. The following sections on the metamorphosis of plants, the essay on method and the theory of colour are provided to demonstrate Goethe’s approach to natural phenomena and the aspects of Goethe’s methodology from which Steiner could draw his epistemological implications.

Page 6 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

33 GSW vol 38 p. 13; in translation, Goethe, J. (1978), op. cit., p. 20.

34 GSW vol 40 p. 7; in translation, GOS, pp 75-83.

35 GSW vol 38, p. 5 and p. 152.

36 GSW 41-44; in translation Theory of Colours (1990), MIT Press: Cambridge, Mass.

2.1 The Metamorphosis of Plants.

Goethe’s interest in the forms of plants engaged him from the time he moved to Weimar in 1775. It was an abiding preoccupation throughout his Italian journey from 1786 to 1788. Goethe visited botanic gardens, and compared the plants he saw with the plants with which he was familiar from northern Europe. He kept extensive diaries of botanic descriptions and drawings, and conveyed them to acquaintances who shared his interest

in scientific investigation. Goethe’s findings are set out in his diarised Italienische Reise [Italian Journey]37 and in his letters to Herder and others. Early in the journey Goethe hypothesises about discovering the form of the Urpflanze [archetypal plant]:

37 Goethe, J. (1970) Italian Journey Penguin Books: London.

38 Ibid, p. 71, Padua 27th September, 1786.

39 Ibid, p. 310, Naples 17th May, 1787; this translation from NOS, p. 17.

40 Ibid, p. 366, Rome July 31, 1787.

Here, where I am confronted with a great variety of plants my hypothesis that it might be possible to derive all plant forms from one original plant becomes clearer to me and more exciting. Only when we have accepted this idea will it be possible to determine genera and species exactly.38

Subsequently he tells Herder he is close to describing the archetypal plant:

Moreover, I must confide to you that I have come very close to the secret of the generation and organization of plants and that it is the simplest thing one can imagine … The archetypal plant will be the most extraordinary creature in the world, for which nature herself will envy me. With this model and the key to it one will then be able to invent plants ad infinitum that must be consistent. In other words, even if they do not exist, they could exist and are not merely painterly or poetic whims but possess an inner truth and necessity. It will be

Page 7 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt possible to apply the same law to all living things.39

Finally he claims to have discovered the principle of organic metamorphosis:

While walking in the public gardens of Palermo it came to me in a flash that in the organ of the plant which we are accustomed to call the leaf lies the true Proteus, who can hide or reveal himself in vegetal forms. From first to last the plant is nothing but leaf, which is so inseparable from the future germ that one cannot think of one without the other.40

With these two ideas – the archetypal form of the plant and the principle of metamorphosis - Goethe embarks upon a phenomenology of nature. The first stage of scientific enquiry remains the accurate observation of the physical phenomena. The second stage is the recognition of the Gestalt [form] and Bildung [development], which constitute the Vorstellungen [mental images] of the spatial and temporal blueprints of the observed phenomena. In the case of plant life this will amount to recognition of the

principle of metamorphosis. As the archetypal plant is neither the original plant’ nor any specific physical plant it can best be understood as a particular instance of the Urphänomen [archetypal phenomenon]. Identification of the archetypal phenomenon becomes the third, and final, stage of abstraction from the perceived phenomena. The task of the scientist, therefore, will be the uncovering of the archetypal phenomenon within the specific aspect of nature under investigation.

In The Metamorphosis of Plants Goethe traces the growth of annual plants from seed to flower, to fruit and to seed again, and identifies six sequential stages: seed (and seed- leaf), stem-leaves, flower (calyx), corolla, stamens (nectaries, style and stigma) and fruit. Goethe observes that each stage metamorphoses into the next and that, therefore, all the plant’s organs can be seen to be variations on the leaf. There is also an alternation from expansion to contraction and back to expansion, and a progression towards ever greater refinement: the seed expands out into the stem-leaf, which contracts and concentrates its energy to produce the calyx and flower; the calyx expands out to produce the corolla, which then contracts into the sexual organs; they expand into the fruit, and the fruit contracts, finally, back into the seed.

Goethe does not articulate in any systematic way how he has come to conceive of plants as he does. To some extent, however, the method emerges from the language he employs. The following paragraphs from the chapter The Fruits is an example of Goethe’s way of approaching the observation of nature:41

Page 8 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

41 Goethe, J. (1978), op. cit. pp40-42.

74. It is now the fruit which we have to observe, and we shall soon be convinced that this too originates in the same way as the previous parts and is subject to the same laws. We speak here really of those vessels or capsules formed by

Nature to enclose the so-called covered seeds, or rather to develop through fructification within these vessels a greater or lesser number of seeds. It will be easy to show that these vessels may likewise be explained according to the nature and organisation of those parts of the plant we have already considered. 75. It is once more the retrogressive metamorphosis which brings to our notice this law of Nature. … 76. Furthermore even in normal and constant formations Nature reveals in manifold ways the fruitfulness that lies hidden in the leaf. … 77. 78. If we keep observations in mind we shall not fail to recognise the leaf-form in all seed-vessels, in spite of their manifold formations, their peculiar modifications and combinations. 79. Nature conceals this likeness to the leaf-form most when she forms soft and juicy or hard and woody seed-forms. But even then it will not escape our notice if we know how to follow this development carefully through all its transitions. Here it is enough to have indicated the general idea and to have shown by means of a few examples Nature’s unity of purpose.

These paragraphs indicate the following aspects of Goethe’s method:

(1) Observations of other parts of the plant have led Goethe to laws, which he anticipates will be evident in fruit as well; (2) Having deduced the phenomenon of metamorphosis, Goethe applies it both progressively and retrogressively; (3) Having concluded that every organ of the plant is a transformation of the leaf, Goethe seeks the leaf in formations, in which it is not immediately observable; (4) There is a general idea within the phenomena, which are a manifestation of Nature’s unity of purpose.

The method, in essence, requires a perception of the general, from which Goethe proceeds back to the particular. In this respect it runs counter to the usual understanding of the methodology of conventional natural science, which is held to be inductive, and which claims to develop its laws by proceeding from the particularity of experimental observation to the general. Goethe’s approach is more akin to deduction which, as a

Page 9 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt method for obtaining knowledge, is usually said to be limited to pure mathematics, or to the truths Kant categorised as the analytic a priori.

2.2 Goethe’s essays on method

Goethe wrote a few short essays on method, two of which have particular significance in relation to an enquiry into the theory of knowledge which the method implies. One of these, Die Absicht eingeleitet [The Intention Introduced], is an introduction to his botanical writings, and in it Goethe relates his observations of organic phenomena to several of the concepts he employs, such as Anschauung [intuition], Bildung [form] and morphology.42 The other is Der Versuch als Vermittler von Objekt und Subjekt [The Experiment as Mediator between Subject and Object], which is Goethe’s most complete attempt to describe and to justify his scientific method.43 The following is an extract from the former essay, in which Goethe contrasts his approach to the observation of natural phenomena with conventional scientific method:44

42 Goethe, J. (1817) Die Absicht eingeleitet, HA 13.54-56.

43 Goethe, J. (1823) Der Versuch als Vermittler von Objekt und Subjekt, HA 13.10-20.

44 Goethe, op. cit., cited GOS, pp 49-50.

In observing objects of Nature, especially those that are alive, we often think the best way of gaining insight into the relationship between their inner nature and the effects they produce is to divide them into their constituent parts. Such an approach may, in fact, bring us a long way toward our goal. In a word, those familiar with science can recall what chemistry and anatomy have contributed toward an understanding and overview of Nature.

But these attempts at division also produce many adverse effects when carried to an extreme. To be sure, what is alive can be dissected into its component parts, but from these parts it will be impossible to restore it and bring it back to life. This is true even of many inorganic substances, to say nothing of things organic in nature.

Thus scientific minds of every epoch have also exhibited an urge to understand living formations as such, to grasp their outward, visible, tangible parts in context, to see these parts as an indication of what lies within and thereby gain some

understanding of the whole through an exercise of intuitive perception. It is no doubt unnecessary to describe in detail the close relationship between this

Page 10 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt scientific desire and our need for art and imitation.

Thus the history of art, knowledge and science has produced many attempts to establish and develop a theory which we will call morphology’. The historical part of our discourse will deal with the different forms in which these attempts have appeared.

The Germans have a word for the complex of existence presented by a physical organism: Gestalt [structured form]. With this expression they exclude what is changeable and assume that an interrelated whole is identified, defined and fixed in character.

But if we look at all these Gestalten, especially the organic ones, we will discover that nothing in them is permanent, nothing is at rest or defined – everything is in a flux of continual motion. This is why German frequently and fittingly makes use of the word Bildung to describe the end product and what is in process of production as well.

Thus in setting forth a morphology we should not speak of Gestalt, or if we use the term we should at least do so only in reference to the idea, the concept, or to an empirical element held fast for a mere moment of time.

When something has acquired a form it metamorphoses immediately to a new one. If we wish to arrive at some living perception of Nature we ourselves must remain as quick and flexible as Nature and follow the example she gives.

In The Experiment as Mediator between Subject and Object Goethe moves from a of observation to the standpoint of the scientific observer and to the constituents of experimentation.45 This work reads as if were intended as a discussion paper, but although it is dated April 28, 1792 it was not published until 1823. The essay argues for the fairly uncontroversial proposition that science depends upon repeated, and not just repeatable, experiments:

45Goethe, op. cit., cited in GOS, p. 75: (1) As we become aware of objects in our environment we will relate them to ourselves, and rightly so since our fate hinges on whether these objects please or displease us

… (2) This yardstick of pleasure and displeasure, attraction and repulsion, help and harm, we must now renounce absolutely; as a neutral seemingly godlike being we must seek out and examine what it is, not

Page 11 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt what pleases. The constituents of experimentation are found in GSW, vol 40 pp 7-15, and translated in GOS, pp 75-83.

(13) The main value of an experiment lies in the fact that, simple or compound, it can be reproduced at any time given the requisite preparations, apparatus, and skill. After assembling the necessary materials we may perform the experiment as often as we wish. …

(14) As worthwhile as each experiment may be, it receives its real value only when united or combined with other experiments. … Two phenomena may be related, but not nearly so closely as we think. Although one experiment seems to follow from another, an extensive series of experiments might be required to put the two into an order actually conforming to nature.46

46 Goethe, op. cit., pp 10-11, translated in GOS p. 78.

47 Ibid., pp 11-13, translated in GOS pp 79-80

48CPR B xiii, p 20: Reason, holding in one hand its principles, according to which alone concordant appearances can be admitted as equivalent to laws, and in the other hand the experiment which it has

Goethe is alluding to his experiments rearranging the order of leaves, so as to show their metamorphoses, and to deficits he claimed to have identified in the methodology of Newton’s Optics. He also cautions against the imposition of theoretical constructs upon observed phenomena:

(18) Every piece of empirical evidence, every experiment, must be viewed as isolated, yet the human faculty of thought forcibly strives to unite all external objects known to it. It is easy to see the risk we run when we try to connect a single bit of evidence with an idea already formed, or use individual experiments to prove some relationship not fully perceptible to the senses but expressed through the creative power of the mind. …

(24) Nothing happens in living Nature that does not bear some relation to the whole. The empirical evidence may seem quite isolated, we may view our experiments as mere isolated facts, but this is not to say that they are, in fact, isolated. The question is: how can we find the connection between these phenomena, these events? 47

On the face of it Goethe’s conception of the experiment is in stark contrast with the relationship between observer and phenomenon Kant recommends in the First Critique,

Page 12 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt for which the scientist compels [nature] to answer questions which he has himself formulated.48 The opposition between Goethe and Kant as scientists is also highlighted in Goethe’s well-known description of his first meeting with Schiller.49

devised in conformity with these principles, must approach nature in order to be taught by it. It must not, however, do so in the character of a pupil who listens to everything that the teacher chooses to say, but of an appointed judge who compels the witnesses to answer questions which he has himself formulated. Goethe, in his note on types of humans, says something surprisingly similar: Naydler, op cit p38: By proceeding from ideas, [the comprehenders] simultaneously express the unity of the whole, and it is almost the obligation of Nature to conform to the ideas.

49 Goethe, J. Poetry and Truth, translated in GOS pp 96-97:Schiller had moved to Jena, where, as before, I saw nothing of him. It was about this time that Batsch, with unbelievable enterprise, had founded a scientific society, with fine collections and impressive apparatus. I usually attended its periodic meetings and one time found Schiller there. By chance we were left in the hall together, and began a conversation. He appeared to be interested in the lectures, but remarked with great insight, and to my pleasure, that such mangled methods regarding Nature could only repel a lay person who might otherwise be willing to venture into the subject. I answered that perhaps even to express such a method would be uncongenial and that there might be another way of considering Nature, not piecemeal and isolated but actively at work, as she proceeds from the whole to the parts. Schiller expressed the desire to have the point clarified through discussion, though not concealing his doubts and refusing to grant that my views owed their origins to experience.

We had reached his house; the conversation had lured me in. I gave a spirited explanation of my theory of the metamorphosis of plants with graphic pen sketches of a symbolic plant. He listened and looked with great interest, with unerring comprehension, but when I had ended he shook his head, saying, That is not an empiric experience, it is an idea. I was taken aback and somewhat irritated, for the disparity in our viewpoints was here sharply delineated. The statement from his essay On Grace and Dignity in Literature occurred to me again; the old antipathy was astir. Controlling myself, I replied, How splendid that I have ideas without knowing it, and can see them before my very eyes.

Schiller, who had far greater tact and urbanity than I, ... replied in the manner of a trained Kantian. My stubborn realism gave rise to a lively argument, and a great battle ensued. Though later an armistice was called, and neither could consider himself the victor, yet each considered himself invincible. Sentences like the following made me quite unhappy: How could any experience ever be gauged an idea, for the characteristic thing about an idea is that it can never be congruous with an experience. Yet if he termed an idea what I called an experience, then there must certainly be something negotiable, something in common between us.

50 The final, didactic section of Theory of Colour is, admittedly, an unrelenting attack on Newton’s Optics.

2.3 The theory of colours

Goethe worked on the Theory of Colour from 1790 until 1810. He was familiar with Newton’s Optics50, which conceives of the colours as the manifestations of progressive refractions of white light. Goethe was averse to the reduction of colours to the status of a secondary quality, and to the description of them as quantifiable angles of what Newton called refrangibility. He also rejected the counter-intuitive assertions that the colour white contains all the other colours, and that black is not a colour at all. In the Theory of

Page 13 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt Colour Goethe embarks upon a phenomenology of the colours, both as to their sense- perceptible appearance and as to the psychological and moral effects of the colours. He replicates Newton’s colour experiments, obtains different results from Newton, and

lambasts Newton for what Goethe sees as the imposition of a theory upon the phenomena, and a failure to let the phenomena speak for themselves. Although the Theory of Colour does display some of the characteristics of amateur science – there are ad hominem attacks upon Newton, and appeals to the common sense of the reader - it also demonstrates in a very clear fashion the distinction Goethe is attempting to draw between looking at and looking into natural phenomena, between perceiving the phenomenon and apperceiving the Urphaenomenon [archetypal phenomenon] of which it is an instance.

This distinction might best be demonstrated by comparing Goethe’s colour-chart with Newton’s. Newton famously observed the spectrum of colours created when a source of light was refracted through a prism. The prism produced the familiar rainbow colours, and Newton concluded that pure white light consists of all the colours, that black is the absence of colour and that the colours can be designated by their respective angles of refraction. Goethe repeated Newton’s experiments, but also noted that the rainbow spectrum arose from the refraction of light through a prism onto the border between a white screen and a black background. Goethe inverted the experiment by placing a black screen against a white background. The effect was that the colours now ran from the blue end of the spectrum to yellow, contained the colour magenta between violet and red, and did not contain green. Goethe’s conclusion was that the colours do not represent the incremental changes in the angles of refrangibility of white light, but arise at the borders of light and dark, and as a result of the interplay between darkness and light. Goethe notes that we cannot look directly at the sun, which we understand to be made up of pure, white light, but see it as yellow. We believe space to be empty, and when we look at it

unilluminated, it appears to be black. On a clear, illuminated day, we see the sky as blue. We observe that blue arises when light is applied to darkness, and yellow arises when darkness confronts white light. The Urphaenomen, therefore, is that colours arise from the interplay between light and dark, which are opposing forces. Blue is the first lightening of the dark, yellow is the first darkening of the light, green is the natural union of blue and yellow, and magenta is the outcome of the intensification of blue and yellow. Goethe’s colours are depicted as a circle rather than as a spectrum, with graduations between twelve colours.

Throughout the Theory of Colour Goethe attempts to articulate the difference between his way of observing natural phenomena and Newton’s. In the Preface he claims there is an inevitable coalescence of theory and sense-experience, and says:

An extremely odd demand is often set forth but never met, even by those who make it: that is, that empirical data should be presented without any theoretical

Page 14 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt context, leaving the reader, the student, to his own devices in judging it. This demand seems odd because it is useless simply to look at something. Every act of looking turns into observation, every act of observation into reflection, every act of reflection into the making of associations; thus it is evident that we theorize every time we look carefully at the world. The ability to do this with clarity of mind, with self-knowledge, in a free way, and (if I may venture to put it so) with irony, is a skill we will need in order to avoid the pitfalls of abstraction and attain the results we desire, results which can find a living and practical application.51

51 Goethe, J. (1990) Theory of Colours translated by Miller, cited in GOS and edited by Judd, D., translated by Eastlake, C., M. I. T. Press: Cambridge, Mass pp xl-xli.

The steps Goethe describes in the progression from looking to observation to reflection and to the forming of associations forms the basis for what might be described as the methodology of his natural science.

3. The methodology of Goethe’s natural science

The methodology of Goethe’s natural science does not fit readily into any of the conventional categories of scientific method. It is clearly not inductive, for while Goethe made very careful observations of natural phenomena, he did not simply move from his observations to a hypothesis and then seek to draw conclusions from the observations he had made. His methodology requires somewhat greater involvement of the observer, yet is far too empiricist to be regarded as deductive, and nor is it what is described as Popper’s hypothetico-deductive methodology.52 As Naydler points out there is a fundamental difference between Goethe’s approach and any inductive or deductive methodology, for:

52 Popper, K. (1968) The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson: London p32: According to the view that will be put forward here, the method of critically testing theories, and selecting from them according to the results of tests, always proceeds on the following lines. From a new idea, put up tentatively, and not yet justified in any way – an anticipation, a hypothesis, a theoretical system, or what you will – conclusions are drawn by means of logical deduction.

53 GOS, p. 71.

54 Uberoi, J.(1984) The Other Mind of Europe: Goethe as a scientist, Oxford UP: Delhi.

What links inductivism and hypothetico-deductivism is the assumption that the

Page 15 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt human mind necessarily operates in a separate sphere from nature, formulating its ideas and theories from a position of relative detachment from phenomena. Goethe’s methodology, by contrast, is based on the assumption that the human mind has the capacity to enter into the essence of phenomena, and lay hold of principles which, once grasped, alter one’s perception of – and relationship to – these phenomena.53

Goethe’s methodology for natural science requires the engaged participation of the scientist. It is what Uberoi in The Other Mind of Europe: Goethe as a Scientist 54 refers to as participant observation. The scientist, in observing nature, must take account of her own part as a natural phenomenon and observe herself in the act of observing. She must also develop her inner capacities as a scientist. Holdrege, in his introduction to

Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism, suggests that Goethean science is actually a form of inner training:

Although Goethe is often portrayed in opposition to science, he viewed his efforts as a further refinement of scientific method. What has made this Goethe-inspired evolution of science both enticing and forbidding is that it involves, in Frederick Amrine’s words, the metamorphosis of the scientist. Goethe knew that his delicate empiricism entailed an enhancement of our mental powers and for that very reason it still remains in its infancy. It entails becoming aware of the object view of the world that so strongly informs both our everyday and scientific thinking. When we leave this natural attitude (Husserl) behind, we can begin to see how we participate within the world and then work to gain new bearings for our thinking and perceiving.55

55 Holdrege, C., Editorial, Bywater & Holdrege, op. cit., p. 12-13.

56 sinnlich, sensorial, as opposed to geistlich, intellectual; Phantasie is not the fantasy of wild imagination, but the imaginative recreation of the actual.

In The Metamorphosis of Plants, in Theory of Colours, in his short pieces on scientific method and in several aphorisms Goethe attempted to describe what it was that underlay his approach to nature. Although it was left to Steiner to provide a coherent account of Goethe’s methodology it is possible to identify features of a methodology from Goethe’s works and to distinguish these features as four separable phases in a process. The first of these is indistinguishable from the methodology of conventional science, and amounts to making what might be called exact sensorial observations. The second stage acknowledges the inherent theoretical aspect of any observation, but takes it further by requiring the conscious creation of an imaginative picture, which is extracted from the observed phenomena. This stage is characterised by Goethe’s term exakte sinnliche Phantasie [exact sensorial imagination]56. The third stage requires the scientist to recognize the idea or the archetype within the imaginative picture, and might be

Page 16 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt described by Goethe’s term anschauende Urteilskraft [intuitive judgment]57. The final stage, in which the scientist unites the idea with the original observed phenomena, might be characterised as objektives Denken [objective thinking], a term applied by another, but endorsed by Goethe, to describe Goethe’s way of thinking.58 Goethe described his overall approach to Nature as eine zarte Empirie [a delicate empiricism].59 Exact sensorial imagination, intuitive judgment and objective thinking require some further explanation.60

57 This expression is the title of an essay, in which Goethe claims to have developed the capacity to employ the intellectus archetypus described by Kant in the second part of the Critique of Judgment. anschauende is generally translated as intuitive, but is literally looking into; Urteilskraft is the capacity for making judgments.

58 In Goethe, J. Significant Help given by an Ingenious Turn of Phrase, cited in Wahl, op. cit. p. 70. Goethe acknowledges Johann Heinroth as the author of this description.

59Goethe, J. Wilhelm Meisters Wanderjahre, cited in NOS, op. cit. p. 72: There is a delicate empiricism which makes itself utterly identical with the object, thereby becoming true theory. But this enhancement of our mental powers belongs to a highly evolved age.

60 These stages are discussed in Wahl, op. cit. pp 61-65.

61 Cited in Zajonc, op. cit., p. 26.

3.1 Exact sensorial imagination

Goethe’s requirement that the scientist engage in exact sensorial imagination requires that there first be exact sensorial observation of natural phenomena, and that the scientist then form an imaginative picture out of the observations which have been made. The observations must be free of any presuppositions. Goethe warns against introducing assumptions about cause and effect into the observations, and says: ... man in thinking errs particularly when enquiring after cause and effect; the two constitute the indissoluble phenomenon.61 To do this actually requires a considerable capacity to withhold from forming judgments, for as Goethe also recognises, [e]very act of looking turns into observation, every act of observation into reflection, every act of reflection into the making of associations; thus it is evident that we theorize every time we look carefully at

the world. 62 Exact sensorial observation, then, is already more than a mere looking into the world, but should amount to no more than to look carefully at the world.

62 Goethe, (1990), op. cit., pp xl-xli.

63 Goethe, J. (1809) Der Kammerberg bei Eger trans Stephenson (1984) and cited in GOS, p. 128.

64 CPR A94 p127: There are three original sources (capacities or faculties of the soul) which contain the conditions of the possibility of all experience, and cannot themselves be derived from any other faculty of

Page 17 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt the mind, namely, sense, imagination, and apperception. Upon them are grounded (1) the synopsis of the manifold a priori through sense; (2) the synthesis of this manifold through imagination; finally (3) the unity of this synthesis through original apperception. All these faculties have a transcendental (as well as an empirical) employment which concerns the form alone, and is possible a priori. In the B edition of the First Critique imagination is subsumed into apperception.

When Goethe next speaks of imagination [Phantasie], in the context of exact sensory imagination, he is referring to a specific faculty of the mind, which is to be distinguished from thinking and intuition. Goethe sees imagination as a kind of helpmate to thinking in the formulation of truly representative concepts:

Intuitive perception (Anschauung) gives us at once the complete concept of an achieved form; the faculty of thought (Denk-Kraft), not wishing to lag behind, shows and articulates in its own way how such a form could and must be achieved …

Since [the faculty of thought] does not feel entirely adequate to the task, it calls on the imagination for help; and in this way conceptual entities (entia rationis) gradually arise whose great advantage it is to lead us back to perception and to pressure us into greater attention and complete insight.63

Goethe’s notion of imagination is thus nothing of the sort of free-floating imagination or the exercise of the power of imagination as a creative, artistic activity. It is the exercise of imagination as image-forming, and for the purpose of representing natural phenomena with a degree of accuracy unavailable to ideas and concepts. Although this dissertation does not extend to an enquiry into the faculty of imagination itself, it is interesting to note that, in the first edition of the Transcendental Deduction of the First Critique, Kant includes imagination as a separate faculty of cognition.64

3.2 Intuitive judgment

The phrase anschauende Urteilskraft [intuitive judgment] appears as the title to a short essay by Goethe on Kant.65 It is clear from the text that the title is a play on Kant’s Kritik der Urteilskraft [critique of judgment], but the expression does also seem to convey Goethe’s claim that thought and observation may be combined more immediately than in a sequential thinking about an observation. The sense of anschauende Urteilskraft is that intuitive activity is somehow contained within the cognitive process of judgment. Goethe’s essay is intended as a rejoinder to Kant’s claim that there are objectively defined limits to knowledge, and that what Kant calls the intellectus archetypus [archetypal intellect] is not available to a human consciousness. The essay is only short,

Page 18 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt and because of its relevance to the thesis of this dissertation the following translation of it is offered:

65 Goethe, J. Sämtliche Werke in Max Hesses Verlag edition, vol 40 pp 30-31.

When I tried to apply Kant’s teaching, if not to penetrate the meaning of it, I couldn’t resist the thought at times, that the dear man was proceeding in a mischievously ironic fashion, in that at the one time he seemed to be attempting to limit our capacity for knowledge in the narrowest way possible, and yet was pointing, with a wink and a nod, over the boundaries he had himself constructed. … In this sense the following part seemed to me to be highly significant:

We can imagine a kind of understanding, which, because it is not discursive like ours, but is intuitive, could move from the synthetic universal to the particular, observing the whole as such, and moving from the whole to the parts. With this, it is not necessary to show that an intellectus archetypus is possible, but only that, in the formulation of our discursive, image-dependent understanding (intellectus ectypus) and the chance that we are led, to be consistent, to that idea of an intellectus archetypus, that no contradiction is implied.

It is true that the author seems to refer here to a divine intellect. However, if in fact we seek, in the moral sphere – through faith in God, virtue and immortality – to raise ourselves up into a high realm and to approach the primal being, then may we not also, in the intellectual sphere – through the contemplation of an ever creating nature – make ourselves worthy of active [geistig] participation in her

productions? Since I had, after all, ceaselessly pressed on, at first unconsciously and out of an inner urge, toward the archetypal, the typical, since I had even succeeded in demonstrating how it unfolds in accordance with the laws of nature, there was nothing to stop me now from boldly embarking on the adventure of reason, as the sage of Königsberg himself called it.66

66 Goethe, op. cit.; writer’s translation, except for the last paragraph, which is adapted from John Barnes’ translation: NOS, p. 49. Geistig is rendered here as active, instead of as spiritual, which would seem to give a misleading sense to the text.

67 Goethe, J. Significant Help Given by an Ingenious Turn of Phrase cited in Wahl, op. cit. p. 70: Here he [Johann Heinroth] means that my thinking is not separate from the objects, that the elements of the object, the perceptions of the object, flow into my thinking and are fully permeated by it; that my perception itself is a way of thinking, and my thinking a perception.

68Goethe, J. Posthumous Notes, cited in NOS pp 37-38.

Page 19 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

Steiner accepts that Goethe has indeed succeeded in demonstrating how [the archetypal] unfolds in accordance with the laws of nature and attempts to apply Goethe’s intuitive judgment to the argument of the Third Critique. Steiner’s work in this area is discussed in Part 2 Chapter 5 of this dissertation.

3.3 Objective thinking

The expression objektives Denken [objective thinking] was applied to Goethe’s methodology by a contemporary, and was endorsed enthusiastically by Goethe as an accurate description of the fulfilment of his scientific method.67 The implication of the term is that Goethe had developed a way of engaging in thinking, which provides the thinker with an immediate and direct relationship with the objects of the world and in which thinking is no longer separated from sense experience. What Goethe appears to mean by objective thinking also emerges from notes he made in 1790, in which he distinguishes different types of humans, differing in their attitudes to their asking questions of nature:68

To orient ourselves somewhat among these various types [of human beings], let us divide them thus into four spheres: utilizers, fact-finders, contemplators, and comprehenders:

(1) The utilizers, advocates and seekers of things practical, are the first to plough the field of science, metaphorically speaking, and they aim at practical results. Self-confidence derived from experience gives them assurance; necessity gives them a certain breadth.

(2) Fact-finders, those who crave knowledge for its own sake, require a calm, disinterested gaze, an inquisitive unrest, a clear mind. They are in contrast with the first group, but work out the results from the scientific point of view exclusively.

(3) The contemplators are somewhat more original, for the mere increase of knowledge unwittingly fosters interpretation and crosses over into it. Even the fact-finders, however much they may make the sign of the crucifix at the very thought of imagination, before they realize it are compelled to call upon this selfsame power for assistance.

Page 20 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

(4) The comprehenders – in a deeper sense they might be called creators – are original in the highest sense of the term. By proceeding from ideas, they simultaneously express the unity of the whole, and it is almost the obligation of Nature to conform to the ideas.69

69 cited in NOS, pp37-38.

The utilizers are asking questions of Nature only to exploit her, and their questions are neither scientific nor methodological. The fact finders, epistemologically, are what might be called na„ve empiricists, and their scientific method is induction – they work from specific observations to a generalising theory. The contemplators are the rationalists, and Goethe’s description of them suggests that deduction will be their scientific method. In the 20th century deduction may have acquired a degree of renewed respectability in the form of Popper’s hypothetico-deductivism. Popper and others have argued that although scientists do not always recognize it, this is the way in which they do, in fact, do their science. Goethe’s comprehenders adopt an approach to nature, which goes beyond the empiricists and the rationalists, for while they proceed from ideas, they simultaneously express the unity of the whole. When this stage is

reached, according to Goethe, it is almost the obligation of Nature to conform to the ideas because the ideas live within Nature.70

70 The intimate association Goethe claims between the practice of science and the effect upon the scientist is reflected by a conversation Eckermann records between Goethe and Hegel:

The conversation turned to the nature of dialectics. Basically, said Hegel, it is nothing more than the regulated and methodically cultivated spirit of opposition inherent in every human being as a talent which shows its greatness in the distinction of the true from the false.

If only, interrupted Goethe, such intellectual arts and skills were not frequently misused and misemployed to make true what is false and false what is true!

I suppose that sort of thing is done, answered Hegel, but only by people who are intellectually sick.

That is why I prefer the study of nature, said Goethe, which does not allow such sickness to arise. For there we have to do with infinite and eternal truth that immediately rejects anyone who does not proceed neatly and honestly in observing and handling his subject. I am also certain that many a person who is dialectically sick could find a beneficial cure in the study of nature.

71 Foerster, E. Die Bedeutung von ss76,77 der Kritik der Urteilskraft, Teil II in Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, Band 56 (2002), 3 pp 321-345, discusses the influence of Goethe on Fichte, Schelling and Hegel.

Page 21 11 Part 1 Chapter 2 GOETHE'S WAY OF SEEING.txt

4. The epistemological implications of Goethe’s way of seeing

Although Goethe wrote some pieces on the methodology of his natural science, it cannot be said that he succeeded in formulating the epistemological implications of his way of seeing. Goethe was not interested in acquiring an organ for philosophy and there is no evidence to suggest that he drew any epistemological conclusions from his objective thinking or that he invited his philosopher friends, who included Schiller, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel and Friedrich and Wilhelm Schlegel, to do so. It is clear that Fichte and Hegel were greatly influenced by Goethe, but their interest lay in developing their own systems rather than incorporating Goethe’s insights into the Kantian tradition.71 It therefore remained for Steiner to apply the methodology of Goethean science to the critical philosophy and to make a connection between Goethe’s claim to be able to perceive archetypes and Kant’s references to an illusory intellectus archetypus in the Third Critique.

Steiner was quick to appreciate the epistemological implications of Goethe’s scientific work, as he demonstrates in the Introduction to Nature’s Open Secret, when he says:72

72 NOS, p. 3.

What is significant in the metamorphosis of plants, for example, is not the discovery of the single fact that leaf, calyx, corolla, and so on, are identical organs; rather, it is the magnificent thought structure of a living whole consisting of mutually interpenetrating, formative principles. This dynamic thought structure, which arises from that discovery, determines out of itself the details and individual stages of plant development. The greatness of this idea, – which Goethe then sought to extend to the animal world as well – dawns on us only when we try to bring it to life in our own mind and attempt to rethink it. That is when we become aware of how this thought is the very nature of the plant itself, translated into the form of an idea, and living in our mind just as it lives in the object. We observe also that we bring an organism to life for ourselves - right down to its smaller parts – when we picture it not as a dead, finished object, but as evolving and becoming and never at rest within itself.

The question for Steiner, then, will be whether he can show that in speaking of the translation of the very nature of the plant into the form of an idea he is speaking the same language as Kant does, when he speaks of ideas – and the related notions of intuitions, archetypes and concepts – in the First and Third Critiques. In order to answer this question Steiner will need to show that there are certain points in the critical philosophy which might be seen as openings for an extension beyond the limits Kant purports to set to possible knowledge.

Page 22 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt PART 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY

Steiner’s epistemological work is very much a response to the Kantian legacy, the limits Kant imposes upon possible knowledge and the prevailing neo-Kantian schools of Steiner’s time.1 In the Preface to the published version of his doctoral thesis, Truth and Knowledge, Steiner laments that present-day philosophy suffers from an unhealthy faith in Kant.2 Steiner’s aim is to undermine that faith in Kant, and in particular in the Kantian notion that there are limits to knowledge. His aim is to lay a foundation for overcoming the subjectivism inherent in all theories of knowledge based on Kant’s philosophy3 and thereby to show that everything necessary to explain and account for the world is within the reach of our thinking.4 The task Steiner has set himself is what he sees as the need to redirect the epistemological discourse of the critical philosophy, for all propounders of theories of knowledge since Kant have been influenced to a greater or lesser degree by the mistaken way he formulated the problem of knowledge.5 The final preliminary point to be addressed in this dissertation, therefore, is to identify what Steiner sees as the mistakes in the Kantian formulation of the problem of knowledge. In order to do this something will need to be said about the nature of the critical project, its methodology and the context in which it arose. It should also be said at the outset that this writer is not presuming to contribute anything to Kantian scholarship, but merely to express in general terms what it is about the critical philosophy that leads Steiner to attempt to challenge it in the way that he does.

1 Steiner appears to have been familiar with the work of his contemporaries. He frequently refers to and cites the neo-Kantians Johann Volkelt and Otto Liebmann and dedicates Truth and Knowledge to Eduard von Hartmann.

2TK, p. 9.

3 Ibid, p. 11.

4 Ibid, p. 10.

5 Ibid, p. 39.

1. The critical project

On the face of it the First Critique appears to be no more or less than an account of the operation and the limitations of pure reason. It has certainly been read that way by some neo-Kantians and Kantian scholars.6 Were the critical philosophy no more than a logic derived from the architectonic of the mind, however, it is unlikely that Steiner would have embarked upon his own epistemological project by setting out to prove that Kant had formulated the problem of knowledge in a mistaken way. He could simply have built upon what he had taken from Goethe and Fichte. The need to respond to the critical project arises from Steiner’s perception that Kant, in setting the limits to the operation of pure reason, is also setting the limits to knowledge of essences and of any metaphysical propositions.

Page 1 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt 6 See, for example, Nelson, op. cit. Nelson argues that the true descendent of Kant is not the recognized post-Kantians, but Jakob Fries, who took a purely methodological view of the critical project.

7 The present writer is aware that there are many views about Kant’s intentions in the critical philosophy, ranging from the purely sceptical and methodological interpretations to those which emphasise Kant’s continuing metaphysical interests. Within all of these interpretations however there still remains the tension between these two tendencies of Kant’s.

8 CPR B xxii, p. 25: This attempt to alter the procedure which has hitherto prevailed in metaphysics, by completely revolutionising it in accordance with the example set by the geometers and physicists

[i.e. Kant’s Copernican revolution], forms indeed the main purpose of this critique of pure speculative reason. It is a treatise on the method, not a system of the science itself. But at the same time it marks out the whole plan of the science [of metaphysics], both as regards its limits and as regards its entire internal structure.

Despite the clinical appearance of the critical philosophy Kant’s Prefaces to both editions and to the Introduction to the First Critique demonstrate a tension between its skeptical orientation and an underlying desire to find a justification for certain metaphysical propositions.7 Indeed, Kant indicates that the express purpose of the critical philosophy is to investigate whether the possibility of formulating metaphysical propositions might better be determined by first establishing the parameters of pure reason.8 Kant does not

offer any conclusions as to the system of the science [of metaphysics] in the First Critique, but it is clear that what motivates his enquiry is a search for the ground for three specific metaphysical propositions, the reality of human moral freedom, the existence of a supreme intelligence and continuing existence of the soul.9 Kant will not allow the critical project to be contaminated by any unfounded metaphysical assumptions, but it is the science of metaphysics which is his interest.10 It is the tension between his commitment to the rigour of the critical project on the one hand and his need to allow for the possibility of metaphysical propositions on the other that allows Kant to say, in the Preface to the second edition of the First Critique, and in reference to the requirements of practical reason: I have therefore found it necessary to deny knowledge, in order to make room for faith.11 Steiner had reason to think, therefore, that for the critical philosophy, there could be no knowledge of essences or of the metaphysical.

9 Ibid, A3 B7, p. 46: These unavoidable problems set by pure reason itself are God, freedom and immortality. The science which, with all its preparations, is in its final intention directed solely to their solution is metaphysics ...

10 Ibid, B xxxi, p. 30: It is therefore the first and most important task of philosophy to deprive metaphysics, once and for all, of its injurious influence, by attacking its errors at their very source.

11 Ibid, B xxx, p. 29.

12Ibid, A 3-10, B6-14, pp 45-51.

Page 2 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt 13 Ibid, B14-18, pp 52-55. For Kant theoretical sciences of reason means mathematics, the natural sciences and metaphysics.

Such an impression is re-enforced by the way in which Kant frames his question as to possible forms of knowledge. Kant devotes the Introduction to the First Critique to the well-known categorization of knowledge into the a priori and the a posteriori and judgments into the analytic and the synthetic,12 before he arrives at the perplexing fact that in all theoretical sciences of reason synthetic a priori judgments are contained as principles.13 He then formulates the critical project in the form of what he calls the general problem of pure reason, namely How are synthetic a priori judgments

possible?14 It is this formulation of the problem of knowledge which Steiner regards as mistaken. From Steiner’s perspective the mistake is to assume that certain forms of knowledge are problematic and then to discount them, rather than to accept that all forms of knowledge are available to human consciousness and then to enquire into how that knowledge is to be attained. In Truth and Knowledge, therefore, Steiner recognizes that he will have to respond in a direct way to the critical philosophy and says in the Preface:15

14 Ibid, B19, p. 55.

15 TK, p. 11.

16 CPR, A xiv, p. 10: Yet they [my pretensions] are incomparably more moderate than the claims of all those writers who on the lines of the usual programme profess to prove the simple nature of the soul or the necessity of a first beginning of the world. ... The subject of the present enquiry is the [kindred] question, how much we can hope to achieve by reason, when all the material and assistance of experience are taken away.

17Loc. cit.

The aim of the following enquiry is to remedy the lack [in the systems of the post- Kantians] described above. Unlike Kant, the purpose here is not to show what our faculty of knowledge cannot do, but rather to show what it is really able to achieve.

Steiner is right to think that he has no choice but to find a way of responding to the critical project and his contemporary neo-Kantians if he is to argue for knowledge of essences and metaphysical truths. He is wrong, however, to have believed that Kant was not also trying to show what our faculty of knowledge is really able to achieve.16

Something also needs to be said at the outset about the methodology of the critical philosophy, because Steiner’s responses to it conclude with an argument for a new way

Page 3 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt of thinking, which, Steiner claims, resolves the fundamental dualism of Kantian idealism. Kant describes his methodology in the Preface to the First Edition of the First Critique and says of it:17

I have to deal with nothing save reason itself and its pure thinking; and to obtain complete knowledge of these, there is no need to go far afield, since I come upon them in my own self. Common logic itself supplies an example, how all the simple acts of reason can be enumerated completely and systematically.

Common logic leads Kant to deduce the pure intuitions of space and time of the Transcendental Aesthetic and then the Transcendental Logic, which generates the Transcendental Analytic and the Transcendental Dialectic in the completed enumeration of the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements. Kant does not appear to question the assumptions of his methodology in the bulk of the First Critique,18 but in the remaining division, the Transcendental Doctrine of Method, he offers a systematic enumeration of the simple acts of reason. Here again Steiner would have concern about both the negative orientation of Kant’s methodology and the results of its application. Kant cautions against the temptation to circumvent the discipline of pure reason and imagine we can know more than we do19; and in discussing disputation as to possible knowledge he returns to the distinction he draws in the Second Preface and says:20

18 Kant does not, for example, question the mind’s capacity to observe itself and does not appear to consider that the distinction he draws between the phenomena and the noumena of the sense-perceptible world might also apply to self-consciousness. These and other related methodological considerations are taken up by Fichte and Steiner, and are discussed in Part 2 Chapter 3 of this dissertation.

19 Ibid, A709, B737, pp 574-575: But where the limits of our possible knowledge are very narrow, where the temptation to judge is great, where the illusion that besets us is very deceptive and the harm that results from the error is considerable, there the negative instruction, which serves solely to guard us from errors, has even more importance that many a piece of positive information by which our knowledge is increased.

20 Ibid, A745, B773, p. 597.

For although we have to surrender the language of knowledge, we still have sufficient ground to employ, in the presence of the most exacting reason, the quite legitimate language of a firm faith.

It is understandable that Steiner would be looking for a different methodology from Kant’s so that he can find his way to knowledge of essences and metaphysical truths.

The final point to mention about the critical project is the philosophical and intellectual context in which it was formulated. It is well-known that Kant was educated into the

Page 4 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt rationalist tradition of Continental philosophy and that he claimed the British empiricist, David Hume, had awoken him from his dogmatic slumbers. What is not so well- known is that Kant, for a time, felt it necessary to respond to the claims of the Continental mystical metaphysical tradition, which was closely interwoven with academic philosophy and the intellectual life of central Europe. The strength of that tradition, and the threat it posed to a philosophical system constructed on the lines of Enlightenment science, is demonstrated by the efforts Kant made shortly before he embarked upon the critical project to discredit any form of mysticism, and to distance himself from it. In Träume eines Geistessehers [Dreams of a Spirit-Seer]21 Kant parodies Swedenborg, whose mixture of pseudo-science and parapsychology styling itself as metaphysics had acquired a very large popular following. Kant is at pains to protect his philosophical enterprise, and especially the metaphysics he ultimately wants to legitimize, from any source of irrationality, and sets up the critical project in such a way that its methodology will have the appearance of being the philosophical equivalent of Newtonian physics.22 It is no doubt for this reason that Kant insists that the results of

21 Kant, I. (1838) Träume eines Geistessehers in Kant, I. Sämtliche Werke, vol 7, Leopold Voss: Leipzig.

22 Kant discusses Swedenborg and the importance of metaphysics in a pre-critical letter to Mendelssohn of April 8, 1766 cited in Kant, I. (1967) Philosophical Correspondence, University of Chicago Press: Chicago, pp54-55: I don’t know whether, in reading this rather untidily completed book, you noticed certain indications of my reluctance to write it. For I saw that my prying inquiry into Swedenborg’s visions would make a great stir among people who knew him personally …

I am far from regarding metaphysics itself, objectively considered, to be trivial or dispensable; in fact I have been convinced for some time now that I understand its nature and its proper place in human knowledge and that the true and lasting welfare of the human race depends on it …

the critical project will have universal and lasting application.23 For this reason, as well, Steiner must find a new methodology in order to overcome the limitations Kant imposes upon possible knowledge. Steiner, like Kant, is drawn to mysticism and metaphysics, but unlike Kant he is convinced that it is possible to know essences and determined, at least in his early career, to find a path to knowledge of essences and metaphysical truths from within the context of the idealist tradition.

23 CPR, B xxxviii, pp 33-34: This system will, as I hope, maintain, throughout the future, this unchangeableness. It is not self-conceit which justifies me in this confidence, but the evidence experimentally obtained through the parity of the result …

24 TK, p. 39.

25 Ibid, p. 34.

2. Steiner’s disjunctions from the critical project

It will be remembered that, in Truth and Knowledge, Steiner claims that Kant had formulated the question of knowledge incorrectly.24 Kant’s mistake, according to

Page 5 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt Steiner, was not to recognize that the question: How are synthetic a priori judgments possible? contains within it two presuppositions which Kant has taken over from dogmatic epistemology. These presuppositions are that we need other means of gaining knowledge besides experience and that all knowledge gained through experience is only approximately valid.25 It will be clear from this that Steiner will be proposing an epistemology within which analytic a priori truths also arise from a form of experience and that knowledge which arises from experience is not merely an approximation of knowledge of things-in-themselves. It is also clear that, despite his very different view of the extent of possible knowledge, it matters to Steiner that his epistemological position is cast as a response to the critical project.

Once Steiner’s form of response to the critical project, and the tensions within the critical philosophy itself are taken into account, it becomes apparent why Tarnas should want to argue that Steiner had articulated an epistemology, which … did not oppose the Kantian epistemology but rather went beyond it, subsuming it in a larger and subtler understanding of human knowledge.26 There is a considerable degree of overlap between the two. If it is accepted that Kant’s ultimate endeavour is to find some solid ground for metaphysical propositions then it might also be said that the critical project itself is embedded in a larger and subtler understanding of human knowledge, and that Steiner’s essentially ontological argument is best understood as an extrapolation from the critical philosophy. Indeed, despite Steiner’s claims that The Philosophy of Freedom is written from personal experience, and that his approach is phenomenological,27 the text is structured as if it were a response to the First and Second Critiques, with the first seven chapters devoted to epistemological issues and the second seven chapters to ethics. Unlike the post-Kantians and his neo-Kantian contemporaries, however, Steiner does not attempt to create an improved version of the Kantian system. What he does, rather, is to identify certain specific junctions within the arguments of the Critiques from which he sets out in a different direction in an attempt to demonstrate that it is possible for human minds to have knowledge of essences. Steiner’s epistemology is not a system in its own right, but a kind of localized corrective to the critical project.

26 Tarnas, op. cit., p. 433.

27 T Ph F subtitle: Some results of introspective observation following the methods of Natural Science

Steiner does not set out his argument in this way, but it seems to this writer that his response to the critical project can be seen as a series of four distinct disjunctions from it. They are described as a series, because Steiner’s inability to resolve the dilemmas within

each of his disjunctions leads him on to the next one. The first disjunction is a challenge to the dualism which informs the whole of the transcendental philosophy. Steiner is committed to a world view which is monistic, and needs to show that the divisions Kant creates between phenomena and things-in-themselves, between intuitions and concepts and between thinking and experience are unsustainable and illusory. Steiner is,

Page 6 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt however, unable to show that any form of dualism is unsustainable, and then seeks out those points in the critical philosophy which are amenable to extrapolation. The second disjunction arises from Kant’s suggestive claim in the Third Critique that, although there must be the possibility of an intellectus archetypus, such an intellect is not available to human consciousness. Steiner argues for a human intellectus archetypus and the capacity to perceive archetypes, but is unable to make out his claims for those propositions. He then returns to the First Critique, in which Kant had made similar statements about the existence, but the unavailability, of intellectual intuition. Steiner had studied Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre closely, and was aware that Fichte’s form of transcendental idealism depends upon the availability of intellectual intuition. In the third disjunction Steiner adopts Fichte’s derivation of intellectual intuition, but then parts ways from Fichte at the point of determining what the activity is that generates and is generated by the intuition of self-consciousness. The fourth disjunction follows on from the third, and at this final stage Steiner argues that it is the activity of thinking, in the form of intuitive thinking, which leads us to knowledge of essences. By the time he has argued for intuitive thinking, however, Steiner can be seen to be departing from the discipline of philosophy and embarking upon the methodology and practice of what he subsequently calls anthroposophische Geisteswissenschaft [anthroposophical spiritual

science]. Steiner’s arguments for the four disjunctions are discussed in detail in Part 2 of this dissertation. The following is an outline of the approach taken by this writer to those arguments.

2.1 Monism and dualism

The most fundamental objection Steiner has to Kant’s critical philosophy is the dualism, which is inherent in any form of transcendental idealism.28 Steiner simply cannot accept that there is anything about which we could never have certain knowledge. It is essential for Steiner, therefore, to find a way of demonstrating that we have can knowledge of essences. Steiner’s first response to the critical project is to argue against dualism and for monism as a world view. Steiner recognizes that Kant’s methodology is also dualistic, and he therefore proposes a monistic methodology, which is his intuitive thinking. Steiner discusses the contrast between dualism and monism in The Science of Knowing and devotes substantial portions of several chapters of The Philosophy of Freedom to a refutation of dualism.

28Kant acknowledges this in the A version of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason, CPR A370, p. 346: The transcendental idealist, on the other hand, may be an empirical realist or, as he is called, a dualist …

Chapter 4 sets out Steiner’s arguments for monism and against dualism. The argument of the chapter is that the differences between Kantian dualism, and what Steiner calls monism, are not as great as Steiner makes them out to be. It is suggested that the dualism of the critical project is contingent, and that nothing could have given Kant more satisfaction than to have it demonstrated to him that our knowledge of appearances is also knowledge of things-in-themselves. It is suggested that the monism Steiner espouses

Page 7 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt itself rests upon an initial dualism, which operates as a device to facilitate understanding.

The chapter concludes that the difference between Kant’s depiction of the cognitive process and Steiner’s is not so much the difference between dualism and monism as between an emphasis upon different stages in the construction of an understanding of that process.

2.2 Perceiving the archetype

In the second part of the Third Critique Kant gives some attention to the logical possibility of what he variously calls architectonic understanding,29 intuitive understanding30 and the intellectus archetypus31. Kant distinguishes the intellectus archetypus from the intellectus ectypus (representational intellect), which, he argues, is the form of reasoning to which we are constrained. Kant introduces the intellectus archetypus to cover the range of logical possibilities, but not to imply that it is available to human consciousness. Steiner seizes upon the intellectus archetypus as a source of access to knowledge of essences. In The Science of Knowing, Nature’s Open Secret and Goethe’s World View Steiner claims that human consciousness has access to the perception of archetypes, and that in perceiving archetypes thinking functions as a sense organ.

29 Kant, I. (1987) Critique of Judgment, hereinafter CJ, Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, p. 269.

30 Ibid, p. 290.

31 Ibid, p. 292.

Chapter 5 shows how Steiner attempts to construct a theory of archetypal apperception from Goethe’s way of seeing. It explains what Kant means by the intellectus archetypus as a kind of intuitive understanding and how Steiner associates the intellectus archetypus with the perception of a reconstructed version of Platonic forms. The chapter sets out Steiner’s argument for the proposition that archetypes are apperceived by thinking in the

same way as spatial objects are perceived by sight, but concludes that this disjunction does not give Steiner access to essences, as thinking is not a sense organ.

2.3 Intellectual intuition

Page 8 12 Part 1 Chapter 3 THE KANTIAN LEGACY.txt In the First Critique Kant refers to another kind of intuitive understanding, intellectual intuition, which he also regards as logically possible but unavailable to human cognition. The post-Kantians disagreed with Kant in this regard, and Steiner was familiar with Fichte’s arguments for intellectual intuition in the Wissenschaftslehre. In Truth and Knowledge Steiner retraces Fichte’s arguments for intellectual intuition and relies on Fichte to claim that intellectual intuition is a generative element of consciousness, and that the activity which generates intellectual intuition is the activity of thinking.

Chapter 6 describes Fichte’s derivation of intellectual intuition and what Henrich32 calls Fichte’s original insight before agreeing with Steiner that there is a sustainable argument for intellectual intuition within the critical tradition. The chapter examines the steps Steiner takes in Truth and Knowledge to set the groundwork for the derivation of what he calls intuitive thinking from intellectual intuition. It argues that Steiner will have some way to go, however, before he can show that the activity Fichte identifies within intellectual intuition amounts to the same thing as Steiner’s intuitive thinking.

32 Henrich, D. (1982) Fichte’s Original Insight in Contemporary German Philosophy Vol. 1Pennsylvania State UP, hereinafter FOI, pp 15-53.

2.4 Intuitive thinking

By the conclusion of Truth and Knowledge it has become clear that Steiner will be seeking to derive freedom from thinking, and to characterise his intuitive thinking as the source of human freedom. Kant takes a very different view of the nature of freedom and

of its association with thinking. For Kant freedom is not so much a concept within the architectonic of cognition as a factor of practical reason.

Chapter 7 examines Kant’s concepts of thinking and freedom and Steiner’s derivation of freedom in Truth and Knowledge and Philosophy of Freedom. It contrasts Kant’s conceptions of thinking and freedom with Steiner’s and sets out the steps Steiner takes to move from intellectual intuition to intuitive thinking through his claims about the nature of thinking and the derivation of freedom. The chapter concludes by showing that the arguments Steiner employs to derive freedom from his critique of the observation of thinking and intuition are ultimately unsatisfactory, and that he cannot demonstrate that it is possible to arrive at essences through the extrapolation from intellectual intuition into intuitive thinking. The consequence for Steiner is that he must depart from philosophy as an academic discipline and embark upon the practice of his spiritual science.

Page 9 13 PART 2.txt

PART 2

Page 1 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt PART 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM

The first disjunction between the critical philosophy and Steiner’s approach to epistemology, which will be considered, is the distinction between Steiner’s monism and the dualism inherent in any form of transcendental idealism. This disjunction represents the fundamental rift between Steiner and Kant and his contemporary neo-Kantians, because dualism implies that there is some part, or some layer, of the given world which will remain unknowable, and Steiner makes it clear throughout his early work that his agenda is to show there are no limits to knowledge.1 It is also a disjunction to which Steiner returns throughout his philosophical writings, and which is most fully articulated in Philosophy of Freedom along with Steiner’s other arguments for his epistemological position. It is examined first for, had Steiner been successful in demonstrating dualism is fundamentally untenable, it could be said he would not have needed to take his epistemological project any further. He would have shown that human cognitive capacities allow for access to essences, and any further epistemological work of his could then have been directed to his other particular interest, which was to be the development of those capacities.

1 See, for example, TK, p. 10: … everything necessary to explain and account for the world is within the reach of our thinking; ITSP, Ch7 [7], p. 107: It follows from the concept of cognizing, as we have defined it, that we cannot speak of limits to cognition

The thesis of this chapter is that although Steiner offers an attractive account of monism as a world view he is unable to demonstrate that the dualism inherent in transcendental idealism is untenable either ontologically or as the methodology of the critical project. As a result, if he is to counter neo-Kantianism from within the idealist tradition Steiner will need to identify and then pursue further disjunctions from the critical philosophy to show that there are no limits to knowledge and that we have access to essences. The argument of the chapter is developed over four sections. There can be no doubt that the critical philosophy appears to

be fundamentally dualistic. The first section examines some passages from the First Critique, which confirm the dualism of the critical project, but which also show why it is that a mere assault upon the critical philosophy because it is dualistic will not demonstrate that human cognition extends to knowledge of essences. The second section sets out Steiner’s responses to dualism and especially his more extended arguments against dualism in Philosophy of Freedom. It is suggested that Steiner’s arguments are not sufficiently compelling to discredit dualism. In Philosophy of Freedom Steiner also explains and develops the argument for his own monistic world view. The third section examines Steiner’s arguments against other forms of monism and his presentation of a monistic view, in which the central role in cognition is taken by the unifying activity of thinking. The fourth section explains what it is about Steiner’s conception of thinking that leads him to look to thinking, in his further disjunctions from the critical philosophy, as the vehicle for access to essences.

1. The dualism of Kantian idealism

Throughout his philosophical writings Steiner identifies dualism with Kantian epistemology

Page 1 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt and characterises dualism and dualistic thinking as fundamentally misguided. It will be remembered that he complains, in Truth and Knowledge, that present day philosophy suffers from an unhealthy faith in Kant.2 Steiner is referring here to his contemporary neo-Kantians, and it is they he cites, rather than Kant, when he attacks dualism in Philosophy of Freedom. His reading of Liebman and Volkelt tells him that the Kantian view3 is that we are so organised that we can learn only of modifications in our own self, not of the things-in-

2 TK, p. 9.

3 Ph F, Ch 4 [23], ITSP pp 62-63; Steiner cites Otto Liebmann’s On the Analysis of Reality and Johannes Volkelt’s Immanuel Kant’s Epistemology as evidence that the Kantian view is dualistic.

themselves that cause them.4 Steiner also traces dualistic methodology within contemporary epistemology back to Kant and attributes dualistic ontological positions to Kant’s methodology when, further into his argument in Philosophy of Freedom, he says:5

4 Ph F, Ch 4 [23]; ITSP, p. 61.

5 Ph F, Ch 7[2]-[3]; ITSP, p. 105.

6 CPR, B xx, p. 24.

7 CPR, B xxvii, p. 28: But if our Critique is not in error in teaching that the object is to be taken in a twofold sense, namely as appearance and as thing in itself … then there is no contradiction in supposing that one and the

Dualism rests on a false conception of what we call cognition. It separates the whole of existence into two regions, each of which has its own laws, and lets those regions confront one another outwardly.

The distinction between the perceived object and the thing-in-itself, which Kant introduced into science [Wissenschaft] and which has not been overcome to this day, originates from this kind of dualism.

There can be no doubt that Steiner understood Kantian idealism to be irretrievably dualistic. It is clear from the First Critique that the world view Kant is presenting is indeed inherently dualistic and that Kant is employing reason in a way that amounts to what might be termed methodological dualism. Kant acknowledges as much in the Preface to the Second Edition (the Second Preface) of the First Critique, when he is reviewing the success of the experiments he has devised for the critical method and says:6

This situation yields, however, just the very experiment by which, indirectly, we are enabled to prove the truth of this first estimate of our a priori knowledge of reason, namely, that such knowledge has to do with appearances, and must leave the thing in itself as indeed real per se, but as not known by us.

That experiment is the test, which demonstrates the irreconcilable distinction between the

Page 2 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt conditioned world of experience and the unconditioned nature of things-in-themselves. Kant next refers to the distinction between appearances and things-in-themselves when he is discussing the twofold nature of freedom,7 and reinforces the distinction throughout the First Critique with repeated bifurcations within of the argument of the critical philosophy.

same will is, in the appearance, that is, in its visible acts, necessarily subject to the law of nature, as so far not free, while yet, as belonging to the thing in itself, it is not subject to that law, and is therefore free.

8 CPR A 19, B 33, p. 65: In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed.

9 CPR A 20, B 34, p. 65: The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far as we are affected by it, is sensation. That intuition which is in relation to the object through sensation, is entitled empirical. The undetermined object of an empirical intuition is entitled appearance.

10 CPR A 20, B 34, p. 66: That in the appearance which corresponds to sensation I term its matter; but that which so determines the manifold of appearance that it allows of being ordered in certain relations, I term the form of appearance.

11 Loc Cit.

12 Kant’s dualism is said by some commentators to be the consequence of his desire to embrace scientific naturalism without being committed to mental materialism. See, for example Guyer, P. Absolute idealism and the rejection of Kantian dualism in Ameriks, K. (ed) (2000) The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, Cambridge UP: Cambridge .

The form of argument in the opening paragraphs of the Transcendental Aesthetic of the First Critique is sufficient to demonstrate that the way of thinking of the critical philosophy is dualistic, both as to the mode of employment of reason and as to the world view being developed. The Transcendental Aesthetic begins with the juxtaposition of a mode of knowledge [eine Erkenntnis] against objects.8 Objects are then broken down into a two- fold distinction between objects per se and how they appear to us.9 Next the appearances themselves are broken down into a further two-fold distinction between form and matter10, matter being given to us a posteriori and through sensation, and form a priori and in the mind.11 Kant continues to employ the same form of either-or reasoning and process of definition throughout the argument of the First Critique, to the point that it is almost possible to open the First Critique at any page and find examples of it.12

The proofs of the critical philosophy also have a fundamentally dualistic quality to them. Kant’s style of argument throughout the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements of the First Critique is to juxtapose one argument of a polarity against another, demonstrate the logical flaws in one side of the argument and thereby prove the truth of the other. Kant refines this process further in the antinomies of the Transcendental Dialectic, which are constructed so as

Page 3 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt to give the appearance that neither argument can readily overcome the other. Underlying all

of these dichotomies is the sharp demarcation Kant appears to have drawn between the given world of sense-perceptible phenomena and the unknowable realm of things-in-themselves, which is itself the consequence of a division of possible forms of knowledge into analytic and synthetic. In addition to this there is the purportedly objective perspective from which Kant appears to be engaging in the critical philosophy, and which implies that there will also be an unbridgeable dichotomy between the observing, knowing subject and the objects of knowledge.

Yet although the methodology and the world view of the critical philosophy appear to be clearly dualistic it would nevertheless be possible to interpret the critical method as a technique, which has been devised to analyse the act of knowing, but to lead back ultimately to a unified, monistic world view. It may be, in other words, that the whole critical enterprise is a device for what Tarnas calls a larger and subtler understanding of human knowledge.13 Indeed, a consideration of the following passages from the First Critique suggests that what Steiner regards as the dualism inherent in the critical philosophy might plausibly be seen as a methodological device Kant has employed to clear a passage free of all presuppositions to certain specific metaphysical truths. That is, it may not be, as Steiner seems to think, that Kant is making a claim that there are no metaphysical truths, or that the world cannot be understood as a unified whole. Rather, what Steiner regards as Kant’s ontological and methodological dualism may be Kant’s way of demonstrating that only a portion of the totality of experience is accessible to the demands of pure reason.

13 Tarnas, op. cit., p. 433.

1.1 Kant’s ontological dualism

An examination of the principal argument of the First Critique lends support to the proposition that Kant’s purported dualism is not his final position, and that Kant is erecting a

dualistic framework for the specific purpose of avoiding unwarranted metaphysical assumptions. Indeed, the language of the Prefaces and the Introductions to the first and second editions of the First Critique, the discussion of metaphysical propositions in the Canon of Pure Reason and the descriptions of methodology in the Transcendental Doctrine of Method all strongly suggest that Kant, like Steiner, is engaging in an epistemological investigation, the ultimate purpose of which is to find a rational way into metaphysics and a unified world view.14 While the three Critiques proscribe the limits of reason, understanding and judgment they do so in such a way as to allow room for moral freedom, God and immortality of the soul. The critical philosophy, then, appears to serve two complementary purposes for Kant. One is that it establishes criteria for the elimination of irrational and unprovable propositions from the domain of philosophy altogether. The other is that, in so doing, it allows for the establishment on rational grounds of specific metaphysical propositions. It might be said that in the Critique of Practical Reason Kant opens the door to freedom, in the Critique of Judgment to teleology and in Religion within the Bounds of Reason Alone to some of the essentials of Kant’s Christian faith, namely God and immortality of the soul. On this interpretation of the underlying motif of the critical philosophy the apparent dualism with which it is suffused could be seen as a technique for the

Page 4 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt justification of a fundamentally monistic world view.

14 CPR, A xx, pp13-14: [Metaphysics] is nothing but the inventory of all our possessions through pure reason, systematically arranged.

Kant’s motivation is apparent from comments he makes in the Prefaces to the first (A) and second (B) editions of the First Critique. In the First Preface Kant introduces the critical philosophy as a criterion for metaphysical judgments. The critique of pure reason will decide as to the possibility or impossibility of metaphysics in general, and determine its

sources, its extent and its limits – all in accordance with principles.15 It will also provide a unified framework for the whole field of metaphysical enquiry.16 As a consequence, no further work will need to be done for metaphysics to be a complete and unified science, and:

15 CPR A xii, p. 9.

16 Ibid, A xiii, p.10.

17 Ibid, A xx, pp 13-14.

18 CPR, B xvi, p. 22: We should then be proceeding precisely on the lines of Copernicus’ primary hypothesis. Failing of satisfactory progress in explaining the movements of the heavenly bodies on the supposition that they all revolved round the spectator, he tried whether he might not have better success if he made the spectator to revolve and the stars to remain at rest.

19 CPR, B xx11, p. 25: This attempt to alter the procedure which has hitherto prevailed in metaphysics, by completely revolutionizing it in accordance with the example set by the geometers and physicists, forms indeed the main purpose of this critique of pure speculative reason.

20 CPR, B xxvii, p. 28.

21CPR, B xxiii, p. 26: Consequently, metaphysics has this singular advantage, such as falls to the lot of no other science which deals with objects (for logic is concerned only with the form of thought in general), that should it, through this critique, be set upon the secure path of a science, it is capable of acquiring exhaustive knowledge of its entire field.

Metaphysics, on the view we are adopting, is the only one of all the sciences which dare promise that through a small but concentrated effort it will attain, and this in a short time, such completion as will leave no task to our successors save that of

Page 5 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt adapting it in a didactic manner according to their own preferences, without their being able to add anything whatsoever to its content. For it is nothing but the inventory of all our possessions through pure reason, systematically arranged.17

In the Second Preface Kant confirms that his primary concern remains metaphysics. It is here that Kant makes his well-known comments about the critical philosophy amounting to an epistemological Copernican revolution.18 The rationale for engaging in such a revolution is to find a way of rescuing metaphysics.19 In the course of that rescue it will be necessary to teach that the object is to be taken in a twofold sense, namely as appearance and as thing in itself,20 but the main purpose remains the demonstration of the unity and totality of metaphysics.21

Kant’s explanation of the purpose of the critical philosophy is resumed in the later parts of the First Critique, in which he returns to what might be termed its metaphysical framework. This is particularly so in the second part of the Critique, the Transcendental Doctrine of

Method, in which Kant is building the passage from the exclusion of metaphysical truths in the First Critique to the bases for their justification in the Second and Third Critiques. In The Canon of Pure Reason Kant argues for the existence of God and the afterlife from the fact of the moral law. The following passage demonstrates both the essentially metaphysical import of the critical philosophy and the striving within it for a unified, monistic world view:22

22 CPR, A 811, B 439, p. 639.

Morality, by itself, constitutes a system. Happiness, however, does not do so, save insofar as it is distributed in exact proportion to morality. But this is possible only in the intelligible world, under a wise Author and Ruler. Such a Ruler, together with life in such a world, which we must regard as a future world, reason finds itself constrained to assume; otherwise it would have to regard the moral laws as empty figments of the brain, since without this postulate the necessary consequence which it itself connects with these laws could not follow. Hence also everyone regards the moral laws as commands; and this the moral could not be if they did not connect a priori suitable consequences with their rules, and thus carry with them promises and threats. But this again they could not do, if they did not reside in a necessary being, as the supreme good, which alone can make such a purposive unity possible.

What Kant appears to be straining to do, more than anything else, is to demonstrate the purposive unity of the manifold of experience. That is, although the critical method requires Kant to propose a division between the world of appearances and the world of things-in-themselves, it is another matter whether Kant’s ontological position necessarily follows from his epistemological method.

1.2 Kant’s methodological dualism

It is clear from the argument of the excerpts from the First Critique cited above that Steiner is also justified in describing the methodology of the critical philosophy as dualistic. It might however be said that Steiner’s criticism of Kant’s methodology as dualistic is nevertheless unwarranted, and that Kant’s methodology is nothing other than the intrinsic form of rational

Page 6 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt argument. It is, after all, not only Kant, who within the critical tradition employs the

dualistic operations of disjunctions, paradoxes and dichotomies as the methodological structures by which to advance his argument. Fichte’s critique of cognition as he presents it in the various formulations of the Wissenschaftslehre, for example, might also be described as dualistic, and it is put forward by Fichte as the natural and unavoidable progression in the realization of consciousness. Fichte has his own conception of what logic is, but he too commences from the intellectual intuition of an initial distinction between I and not-I, and progresses by way of further dichotomising operations to a conception of self- consciousness as the antithesis of the given world.23 It could be argued that methodological dualism is the form of any rational observation and any rational argument.

23 Fichte, J. G. Second Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre in IWL p. 83: To think and to determine an object (in the previously indicated sense of object): these are one and the same act. The two concepts are identical. Logic furnishes us with the rules that govern the act of determining an object; therefore, I should think, logic presupposes, as a fact of consciousness, this act of determining as such. That every act of thinking has an object is something that can be shown only within intuition. Think, and while you are thinking, pay attention to how you do this. You will undoubtedly discover in this case that you also posit an object of this act, which you posit over against or in opposition to this same act of thinking.

24 Ph F Ch 1 [1]; ITSP, p. 5.

25 Ph F Ch 1 [8]; ITSP, p. 12: If there is a difference between a conscious motive and an unconscious drive, then the conscious motive will bring with it an action that must be judged differently from an action done out of blind impulse. Our first question will concern this difference. The position we must take on freedom itself will depend on the result of this enquiry.

An initial examination of Steiner’s methodology within Philosophy of Freedom would suggest that his form of argument as well is fundamentally dualistic. Indeed, Steiner introduces the whole of the argument of Philosophy of Freedom with a disjunction: Is a human being spiritually free, or subject to the iron necessity of purely natural law?24 The first chapter of Philosophy of Freedom then proceeds, in a conventionally logical fashion, to present, consider and reject several arguments for the proposition that the human being is not free. This leads Steiner to a standpoint, from which he contrasts conscious motives with unconscious drives,25 and from this disjunction he generates the epistemological concern of Philosophy of Freedom: What does it mean to have knowledge of the motives of one’s

actions?26 As that question implies an understanding of the nature of thinking27 Steiner has arrived at the point from which he can embark upon his primary purpose, which is to show that thinking can be intuitive, and that intuitive thinking is the source of freedom. The methodology Steiner has employed in the construction of his enquiry is the methodology of conventional rational argument. Steiner also acknowledges that the way we are organised is fundamentally dualistic:28

26 Ph F Ch 1[9]; ITSP, p. 12.

Page 7 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt 27 Ph F Ch 1[17]; ITSP, p. 16: … what is the origin and significance of thinking? For without understanding the soul’s activity of thinking, no concept of knowledge of anything, including an action, is possible.

28 Ph F Ch 5 [26]; ITSP, p. 89: For us, the world-whole splits into above and below, before and after, cause and effect, object and mental picture, matter and force, object and subject, and so forth.

29 SK, p. 28; it is Berkeley, and not Kant, who argues that the world exists only so long as we keep our senses open

2. Steiner’s arguments against dualism

Steiner presents his argument against dualism most fully in Philosophy of Freedom, but there are attempts to counter dualism in some of the early Goethe studies and in Truth and Knowledge. In The Science of Knowing, for example, in a section entitled Correcting an Erroneous Conception of Experience as a Whole, Steiner makes a first reference to Kantian transcendental idealism by characterising it as a preconception. At this stage Steiner does not appear to have appreciated the difference between Kantian dualism and Berkeleian subjectivism, for he says:29

At this point we must indicate a preconception, existing since Kant, which has already taken root so strongly in certain circles that it is considered axiomatic. If anyone were to question it, he would be described as a dilettante, as one who has not risen above the most elementary concepts of modern science [Wissenschaft]. The preconception I mean is the view: It is already established from the very beginning that the whole world of perception, this endless manifoldness of colours and shapes, of sounds and warmth differentiations, etc, is nothing more than our subjective world of mental pictures [Vorstellungen], which exists only as long as we keep our senses open to what works in upon them from a world unknown to us. This view declares the entire world of phenomena to be a mental picture inside our individual

consciousness, and on the foundation of this presupposition one then erects further assertions about the nature of our activity of knowing.

Steiner juxtaposes this misrepresentation of Kantian dualism with a naive realist view of the world30 so as to demonstrate that dualism is both implausible and counterintuitive, but he does not develop the argument any further or make claims for any specific form of monism. What these and similar early allusions to dualism show, therefore, is that Steiner harbours an inherent aversion to dualism, but does not as yet appreciate the strength of the arguments of the critical philosophy which must lead to the positing of a dualistic world view .31

30 SK, p. 29. This simple reflection – that the naive person notices absolutely nothing about things that could bring him to this view – shows us that in the objects themselves there lies no compelling reason for this assumption. What is there about a tree or a table itself that could lead me to regard it as a mere configuration of mental pictures? At the very least this cannot therefore be presented as an obvious truth.

Page 8 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt 31 Steiner’s inherent aversion to dualism is evident in others of his early works. See, for example, Steiner, R. (1985) Friedrich Nietzsche: Fighter for Freedom, p. 55: Out of suffering and sick longing, the belief in the yonder world is born; out of the inability to penetrate the real world all acceptances of things in themselves have originated; RP p301: The dualistic mode of conception, which declares that the organic and the inorganic has to be explained according to two different principles, gives way to a monistic mode of conception, to a monism that has only one uniform mode of explanation for the whole of nature.

32 Loc Cit.

It is apparent that Steiner’s appreciation of the difficulties in countering dualism had grown by the time of Truth and Knowledge. In making his comment about the unhealthy faith in Kant Steiner means that the neo-Kantianism of his contemporaries is predicated upon, and hampered by, the dualism inherent in transcendental idealism. In his summary of the critical project Steiner then says of Kant:32

He showed that the foundation of things lying beyond the world of our senses and our reason, and which his predecessors sought to find by means of stereotyped concepts, is inaccessible to our faculty of knowledge. From this he concluded that our scientific efforts must be limited to what is within reach of experience, and that we cannot attain knowledge of the supersensible foundation, of the thing-in-itself. But suppose the thing-in-itself and a transcendental ultimate foundation of things are nothing but illusions!

Steiner recognises that he will need to counter the concept of a transcendental ultimate foundation of things, but in Truth and Knowledge he does not do this by way of developing

an argument. He moves, instead, to a consideration of the activity of thinking, which will lie at the core of all his epistemological work. In Truth and Knowledge Steiner claims that ... everything necessary to explain and account for the world is within the reach of our thinking33 and that the subjectivism and dualism of Kantian idealism can then be contextualised as ... a necessary transitional stage which is overcome in the very process of knowledge.34 For Steiner the very process of knowledge takes place within our thinking, and the act of knowing is a creative, rather than a replicative, engagement with the given world. His argument then is that the dualistic appearance of the world is an illusion, because in the very act of knowing we in fact overcome what otherwise appears to be a bifurcation between the objects of perception and our knowledge of them.35

33 TK, p. 10.

34 TK, p. 15.

35 TK, pp 11-12: … truth is not, as is usually assumed, an ideal reflection of something real, but is a product of the human spirit, created by an activity which is free; this product would exist nowhere if we did not create it ourselves. The object of knowledge is not to repeat in conceptual form something which already exists, but rather to create a completely new sphere, which when combined with the world given to our senses constitutes complete reality. Thus man’s highest activity, his spiritual creativeness, is an organic part of the universal

Page 9 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt world-process. The world-process should not be considered a complete, enclosed totality without this activity.

Man is not a passive onlooker in relation to evolution, merely repeating in mental pictures cosmic events taking place without his participation; he is the active co-creator of the world-process, and cognition is the most perfect link in the organism of the universe.

Steiner’s principal response to dualism is contained in Philosophy of Freedom. Steiner devotes the larger part of four of the fifteen chapters of Philosophy of Freedom to a discussion of dualism and monism, and criticizes dualism in several others. In Chapter 2 he describes how dualistic and monistic world views arise. In Chapter 7 he sets out to demonstrate that Kantian idealism and other dualistic epistemological positions, as well as three common forms of monism, are unsustainable. In Chapter 10 he argues that unsophisticated forms of ethics are fundamentally dualistic and that the exercise of moral freedom implies a monistic world view. The concluding chapter, Final Questions, is also given the heading The Consequences of Monism, and in it Steiner attempts to link the

argument of the previous chapters to his overriding purposes, namely to show that human beings are inwardly free and that they have a capacity to engage in intuitive thinking.

In Chapter 2 of Philosophy of Freedom Steiner introduces dualism and monism as the two natural attitudes, which arise from a search for the foundations of knowledge. He describes them as the two possible attitudes in the sense that the world will be understood either as one coherent knowable unity or it will not. His initial exposition argues both that dualism is fundamentally flawed, and that monism in its common forms is equally unsatisfactory. Steiner begins with an account of how both world views derive from the same act of awakened consciousness, and says of the process of cognition:36

36 Ph F Ch 2 [2]-[4]; ITSP, pp 19-21.

That which we seek in things [i.e. an explanation of the facts], over and above what is given to us immediately, splits our entire being into two parts. We become aware of standing in opposition to the world, as independent beings. The universe appears to us as two opposites: I and world.

We set up this barrier between ourselves and the world as soon as consciousness lights up within us. ... Only when we have made the world content into our thought content do we rediscover the connection from which we have sundered ourselves. ...

The whole relation between I and the world that I have portrayed here meets us on the stage of history in the contrast between a unitary worldview, or monism, and a two- world theory, or dualism. Dualism directs its gaze solely to the separation that human consciousness effects between the I and the world. Its whole effort is a futile struggle to reconcile these opposites, which it may call spirit and matter, subject and object, or thinking and phenomenon. ... Monism directs its gaze exclusively to unity, and seeks to deny or erase the opposites, present though they are. Neither monism nor dualism is satisfactory, for neither does justice to the facts. Dualism sees spirit (I) and matter (world) as two fundamentally different entities, and therefore it cannot

Page 10 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt understand how the two can affect one another. ... Yet, to the present day, things are hardly better with monism which, until now, has attempted three solutions: either it denies spirit and becomes materialism; or it denies matter, seeking salvation through spiritualism [Spiritualismus]; or else it claims that matter and spirit are inseparably united even in the simplest entity, so that it should come as no surprise if these two forms of existence, which after all are never apart, appear together in human beings.

This characterisation of the deficiencies in familiar world views then generates Steiner’s quest for a credible form of monism, that is, one which does not amount merely to a denial of matter or spirit or an unsubstantiated claim that they are inherently united.

The process Steiner adopts is to elaborate the weaknesses in the three variants of monism he has put forward before reconsidering and then rejecting dualism. It is then open to him to claim that the only way out of the dilemma is to return to what he variously describes as nature or the world or the facts as the starting-point for a more satisfactory form of monism. It is we, he reminds us, who separate ourselves from the native ground of nature and place ourselves as I in opposition to the world.37 Despite that separation Steiner postulates that there must be something of nature within us.38 This then leads him to embark upon an enquiry into nature outside us and nature within us, and to further postulate that there must be an inherent consistency between these two manifestations of nature.39 This postulation may seem a little surprising after Steiner has just rejected that form of monism, for which matter and spirit are inseparably united [and] appear together in human beings. The explanation is that Steiner is attempting to establish the groundwork for a critique of what he takes to be nature within us - the activity of thinking - as the starting point for his epistemological project.

37 Ibid [10]; ITSP, p. 25.

38Ibid [12]; ITSP, p. 25: To be sure, we have torn ourselves away from nature, but we must still have taken something with us into our own being. We must seek out this natural being within ourselves, and then we shall also rediscover the connection to her.

39 Ibid [12]; ITSP, p. 25: We can only find nature outside us if we first know her within us. What is akin to her within us will be our guide.

A particular concern for Steiner in what he perceives as the dualism of Kantian idealism is the ontological status of things-in-themselves. This is because Steiner is convinced that there are no limits to knowledge, and that, therefore, there can be no things-in-themselves separate from the observable phenomena of the given world. Kant, on the other hand,

makes it clear that we can say nothing of things-in-themselves, because our capacity for knowing is limited to representations constituted from our sense impressions. The fact that we can say nothing of things-in-themselves means that we cannot determine whether or not there are things-in-themselves, and if there are things-in-themselves whether they are different from or identical with the appearances, which make up the given world. Steiner does not consider whether, within the context of Kantian idealism, it may be that the

Page 11 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt appearances are the things-in-themselves. That is, he does not allow for the possibility that the dualistic methodology of the critical philosophy may nevertheless lead to a unitary world view.

In Chapter 4 of Philosophy of Freedom Steiner introduces Kant’s concept of representations [Vorstellungen] as the content of cognition. It is clear that the ontological status of representations must be different from that of things-in-themselves. Representations are, by definition, what is known of the sensory manifold and things-in-themselves are likewise, by definition, what remains unknown. Steiner contrasts representational theory with Berkeley’s esse est percipe, and then describes the Kantian distinction between representations and things-in-themselves in the following way:40

40 Ph F Ch 4 [23]; ITSP, pp 61-62; Steiner is citing from a contemporary neo-Kantian, Otto Liebmann.

Berkeley’s view stands in contrast to the currently prevailing Kantian view. This also limits our knowledge of the world to our mental pictures. But it does not do so because of the conviction that no things except these mental pictures exist. Rather, the Kantian view believes us to be so organised that we can learn only of modifications in our own self, not of the things-in-themselves that cause them. From the circumstance that I know only my mental pictures, the Kantian view draws the conclusion not that there is no existence independent of these mental pictures, but only that the subject cannot directly receive such an existence into itself. This view then concludes that only through the medium of its subjective thoughts can it imagine, fantasize, think, cognize, or even perhaps fail to cognize this existence. This (Kantian) view believes it is saying something absolutely certain, something that is immediately evident without any proof.

Steiner draws on Volkelt, von Hartmann and the physiologist, Mueller, to sketch what the proof might be before arguing that representational theory inevitably collapses into nothing.41

41Ph F Ch 4 [24-26]; ITSP, pp 62-66.

42Ph F Ch 4 [27]; ITSP, p. 68: From now on, I must treat the table itself – which I used to believe affected me, and produced a mental picture of itself within me – as a mental picture [Vorstellung]. But then to be consistent my sense organs and the processes in them must also be only subjective. I have no right to speak of a real eye, only of my mental picture of the eye. It is the same with nerve conduction and brain processes, and no less so with the process, in the soul itself, by which things are supposedly built up out of the chaos of the various sensations.

43 Ph F Ch 4 [28]; ITSP, p. 69.

Steiner argues that there are both a category flaw and a lacuna in the reduction in which the critical philosophy engages. The category flaw is that the critical philosophy places observation of external phenomena and observation of internal phenomena in different

Page 12 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt categories without providing any justification for reducing the given world to representations, but at the same time acknowledging the sense organs and other elements of the process of perception as objectively real.42 The lacuna arises between the forms of observation the critical philosophy engages in for the perception of external phenomena and for the comprehension of internal states. Steiner notes:43

Moreover, there is a gap in the whole train of argument. I am in a position to follow the processes within my organism, up to the processes in my brain, even though my assumptions become ever more hypothetical the closer I come to its central processes. The path of external observation ends with the processes in my brain; more precisely, it ends with what I would perceive if I could examine the brain with physical and chemical means and methods. The path of inner observation begins with sensation and goes as far as the construction of things from the material of sensation. At the point of transition from brain process to sensation, the path of observation is interrupted.

From these arguments Steiner believes he has shown that the critical philosophy is untenable.44 He does not consider the arguments, which might be made in response to his objections to critical idealism.

44 Ph F Ch 4 [29]; ITSP, p. 69-70: Critical idealism seeks to prove that percepts have the character of mental pictures, while naively accepting the percepts of one’s own organism as objectively valid facts. What is more, it fails to notice that it is throwing together two fields of observation between which it can find no connection.

45 Ph F Ch 4 [31]; ITSP, p. 70: Soviel ist hieraus gewiss: durch Untersuchungen innerhalb des Wahrnehmungsgebietes kann der kritische Idealismus nicht bewiesen, somit die Wahrnehmung ihres objektiven Charakters nicht entkleidet werden.

So far as the category flaw is concerned the critical idealist might argue in response that there is in fact a difference between representations of sense-perceptible phenomena of the given world and perception by the organs of sense. It is true that, observed externally, I do have no right to speak of my real eye, but only of my mental picture of the eye. From the point of view of the activity of the eye in seeing, however, there is a category difference, in that the activity of the eye is the very process, which generates the mental pictures of all other phenomena. Bearing in mind the emphasis Steiner places upon the activity of thinking in the act of knowing it is surprising that he seeks to make an argument of this kind against critical idealism. So far as the lacuna argument is concerned the critical philosopher might say in response that the gap in the chain between the path of external observation and the path of internal observation is the very problem, which led Kant to propose the critical method and to provide all observations with the same ontological status as representations.

Steiner concludes his initial arguments against critical idealism by asserting: This much, then, is certain: investigation in the perceptual realm can neither prove critical idealism, nor strip the percept of its objective character.45 The conclusion that perceptual investigation cannot prove critical idealism seems to indicate a fundamental misunderstanding of the critical philosophy, for which the issue is not whether its soundness may be proven or disproved, but whether it is successful as a method for determining which questions can be

Page 13 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt

asked, and which cannot. It is not a part of the critical philosophy to attempt to prove critical idealism by means of investigation in the perceptual realm at all. The critical philosophy is not a set of metaphysical propositions to be proven, but a method of enquiry. This aspect of Steiner’s attack on critical idealism does therefore appear to be misguided, and to arise from his aversion to ontological dualism, which he sees as one inevitable consequence of it.

The next chapters of Philosophy of Freedom are devoted to an account of thinking as the essential activity of nature within us. In these chapters Steiner argues that it is the activity of thinking, which is the source of human freedom.46 It is thinking, which generates concepts and which makes possible the cognitive act of reuniting percepts47 and concepts. These chapters are taken up with an explanation of the natures of and relationships between the cognitive elements of thinking, perceiving, ideas and concepts. In Chapter 7 of Philosophy of Freedom Steiner returns to his critique of dualism. He acknowledges that we are so organised that the full, total reality (including that of ourselves as subjects) initially appears to us as a duality.48 For the monist this appearance of duality is readily resolved into a unity by the process of cognition. For the dualist, however, the appearance of a duality signifies the reality of two worlds that are absolutely distinct from one another.49 Instead of recognising that the process of cognition overcomes the initial apparent duality, dualism

46 Ph F Ch 3 [18]; ITSP, p. 37: For in thinking we observe something of which we ourselves are the producers.

47The term percept is used in both ITSP and T Ph F as the translation for Wahrnehmung. What Steiner means by a percept is set out most clearly in a second edition addendum to Chapter 7: It should also be kept in mind that the idea of the percept, as developed in this text, must not be confused with that of external sense perception, which is only a special case of it. Readers will see from what has been said, but still more so from what will be said later, that everything both sensory and spiritual that meets a human being is here taken to be a percept until it is grasped by the actively elaborated concept. Senses of the kind normally meant by the word are not necessary to have percepts of soul or spirit [Wahrnehmungen seelischer oder geistiger Art]. ITSP, pp 124-125.

48 Ph F Ch 7 [1]; ITSP, p. 104.

49 Loc Cit.

separates the whole of existence into two regions, each of which has its own laws, and lets those regions confront each other outwardly.50 Dualism, Steiner concludes, arises from a false conception of cognition and has led to the unfortunate Kantian distinction between appearances and things-in-themselves.51 Steiner’s conception of cognition is that it consists in the thinking activity of assigning concepts to percepts. The fallacy in Kantian dualism is to imagine another world of percepts for which there are no available concepts.52 The

Page 14 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt consequence is that ... dualists, working with a completely contentless concept of the in- itself, cannot arrive at an explanation of the world.53

50 Ph F Ch 7 [2]; ITSP, p. 105.

51 Loc. Cit: The distinction between the perceived object and the thing-in-itself, which Kant introduced into science [Wissenschaft, knowledge] and which has not been overcome to this day, originates from this kind of dualism.

52 Loc. cit: But if we consider the sum of all percepts as one part of the world, and then oppose to these percepts a second part, the things-in-themselves, we are philosophizing into thin air. We are just playing a game with concepts. We construct an artificial contrast and then can find no content for its second term – since such content can be created for a separate, particular thing only out of perception.

53 Ph F Ch 7 [5]; ITSP, p. 107.

54 Loc. cit: It follows from the concept of cognizing, as we have defined it, that we cannot speak of limits to cognition.

55 Ph F Ch 7 [7]; ITSP, p. 108: The preconditions for cognizing exist through and for the I. The I itself poses the questions of cognition. In fact, it draws them from the element of thinking, which is completely clear and transparent within itself. If we ask ourselves questions that we cannot answer, their content cannot be clear and distinct in every aspect. It is not the world that poses questions to us; we pose them to ourselves.

56 Ph F Ch 7 [10]; ITSP, pp 108-109.

From Steiner’s point of view, then, the unifying activity of thinking in the process of cognition demonstrates both that any dualistic account of cognition will be inadequate, and that it is possible to arrive at an explanation of the world – that is, that there are no limits to knowledge. Indeed, Steiner believes he has shown there are no limits to knowledge by definition.54 This appears to be because the very act of asking questions of the world implies a capacity within the enquirer to find the answer.55 It is also because Steiner seems to believe that our capacities for perception and thinking are fundamentally unlimited, and he claims:56

Our cognition involves questions that emerge for us because a conceptual sphere, pointing to the totality of the world, confronts a perceptual sphere conditioned by place, time and subjective organisation. Our task is to balance these two spheres, both of which we know well. This has nothing to do with a limit to cognition. At a particular time, this or that might remain unexplained because the place of our vantage point in life prevents us from perceiving the things in question. But what is not found today may be found tomorrow. The limits determined in this way are only temporary, and they can be overcome by progress in perception and thinking.

Steiner also claims that the fallacy in dualism is a failure to recognise that the fundamental

Page 15 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt polarities in theory of knowledge between subject and object, and concept and percept, are merely devices for understanding cognition. Once thinking is applied to cognition, he believes, these distinctions disappear. The dualist, however, sees them as absolute. Steiner explains how this error arises in the following way:57

57 Ph F Ch 7 [11]; ITSP, p. 109.

58 Kant splits the cognitive process into five: 1) the object in itself, 2) the subject’s percept of the object, 3) intuitions, 4) understanding and 5) concepts; CPR A 19: Objects are given to us by means of sensibility, and it alone yields us intuitions; they are thought through the understanding, and from the understanding arise concepts

59 Ph F Ch 4 [16], ITSP, p. 55: From the na„ve standpoint, if we see the sun appear in the morning as a disc on the horizon and then follow the progress of this disc, we believe all of this exists and occurs just as we observe it. We cling fast to this belief until we meet other percepts that contradict the first.

Dualism mistakenly transfers the contrast between objects and subjects, which has meaning only within the perceptual realm, to purely imagined entities outside this realm. But things separated in the perceptual field are separate only as long as the perceiver refrains from thinking – for thinking suspends all separation and reveals it to be merely subjective. Therefore a dualist is really transferring – to entities behind the percepts – categories that have no absolute but only a relative validity, even for the percepts. A dualist splits percept and concept, the two factors involved in the cognitive process, into four: 1) the object in itself, 2) the subject’s percept of the object, 3) the subject, and 4) the concept that relates the percept to the object-in- itself.58

It should be noted that Steiner does much the same thing, in that he distinguishes between the object and the percept of the object - and criticizes the naive realist for not doing so59 – and distinguishes the cognizing subject from the concept. Indeed, Steiner’s picture of the process

of cognition also distinguishes concepts from ideas, which he defines as more generalized concepts.60

60From Steiner’s perspective it would be more correct to say that the critical idealist identifies six factors in the cognitive process, namely 1) the object in itself, 2) the subject’s percept of the object, 3) the subject’s mental picture of the percept of the object, 4) the subject, 5) the idea of the object and 6) the concept that relates the percept to the object-in-itself.

61 Ph F Ch 7 [11], ITSP, pp 109-110.

62 Ph F Ch 5 [22], ITSP, p. 85: The act of knowing (cognition) is the synthesis of percept and concept. Only percept and concept together make up the whole thing.

The dualist, Steiner claims, mistakenly attributes reality to distinctions, such as that between

Page 16 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt subject and object, which arise from – and are subsequently resolved by – the activity of thinking. Steiner argues that the dualist’s initial distinction between subject and object is compounded by a bifurcation in the act of knowing, which the dualist cannot resolve. Steiner depicts the idealist dualist argument as follows:61

For the dualist, the relationship between an object and a subject is a real one; the subject is really (dynamically) influenced by the object. This real process is said not to emerge into our consciousness [nicht in unser Bewusstsein fallen]. It is supposed to evoke a response in the subject to the stimulus proceeding from the object. The result of this response is supposed to be the percept, which alone emerges into consciousness. The object is supposed to have an objective reality (that is, a reality independent of the subject), while the percept is supposed to have a subjective reality. This subjective reality supposedly relates the subject to the object. That relationship is said to be ideal (conceptual). Thus, dualism splits the cognitive process into two parts. One of them, the creation of the perceptual object out of the thing-in-itself, is assigned a place outside consciousness, and the other, the connection of the percept to the concept and the relation of the concept to the object, is assigned a place within consciousness.

As with the elements of cognition, it is fair to say that Steiner engages in the same form of argument himself. He also divides the world into subject and object, and he also distinguishes between inner and outer elements in the process of cognition.62 Indeed, the essential difference between Steiner and the critical idealist would appear to be not so much a distinction between monistic and dualistic views of the world, but a distinction as to the point in the cognitive process where the divisions are to be drawn. For the dualist that point is

between the given world and representations in consciousness, while for Steiner it is within the activity of thinking itself.

A further argument Steiner employs against the critical idealist expression of dualism is that any variety of representational epistemology must be logically flawed, because it depends upon a naive realist view of the operations of the organs of perception while insisting that knowledge derived from those organs is merely representational. Steiner sets out the steps in the act of knowing from a naive realist point of view, and then retraces them from the perspective of representational epistemology. Having described the physiological processes from nerve endings to brain, Steiner draws the following epistemological conclusions:

... I must treat the table itself – which I used to believe affected me, and produced a mental picture of itself within me – as a mental picture. But then to be consistent my sense organs and the processes in them must also be only subjective. I have no right to speak of a real eye, only of my mental picture of the eye. It is the same with nerve conduction and brain processes, and no less so with the process, in the soul itself, by which things are supposedly built up out of the chaos of the various sensations. If I run through the elements of the act of cognition once again, assuming the correctness of that first [naive realist] circuit of thoughts, then the cognitive act reveals itself as a tissue of mental pictures that, as such, can have no effect on one another.63

63 Ph F Ch 4 [27]; ITSP, p. 68.

Page 17 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt 64 mental picture is the translation here of Vorstellung, which is also often rendered as representation and occasionally as idea.

Steiner is right, of course, to recognise that there is a logical non sequitur in any theory of knowledge, which consists only of a tissue of mental pictures64, and which yet claims to provide an account of the given world as the object of cognition. He would be wrong, however, were he to attribute such an error to Kant, and to interpret Kant as claiming that the table itself is as much a mental picture as the representation of it, which arises from the manifold of sense impressions.

Steiner argues that, in order to avoid this embarrassment, the critical idealist reverts to a naive realist conception of the organs of perception and accepts one’s own organism as something

that exists objectively.65 As a consequence the critical idealist then becomes inconsistent in the treatment of percepts, and ... makes the error of characterizing one percept in exactly the same way as the naive realism it had ostensibly refuted.66 Steiner summarises his argument against the apparent logical inconsistency in critical idealism by saying:

65 Ph F Ch 4 [30]; ITSP, p. 70.

66 Ph F Ch 4 [29]; ITSP, p. 69.

67 Ph F Ch 4 [29]; ITSP, pp 69-70.

68 CPR A xiii, p.10: In this enquiry I have made completeness my chief aim …

Critical idealism seeks to prove that percepts have the character of mental pictures, while naively accepting the percepts of one’s own organism as objectively valid facts. What is more, it fails to notice that it is throwing together two fields of observation between which it can find no connection.67

That is, to put it in terms of the framework of Steiner’s own enquiry, it fails to recognise the coherence between nature within us and nature outside of us.

The response which could be made to this attack upon critical idealist’s dualism is that it appears to assume the critical idealist is engaged in the same kind of project as Steiner himself has embarked upon – that is, in the demonstration of the coherence of a particular point of view. It is clear from the outset that Steiner’s investigation will lead in a predetermined direction, and that Steiner has something in mind he wishes to prove, namely that it is possible to arrive at a coherent and comprehensive, but monistic world view. Kant, on the other hand, claims to be engaging in a transparent and open-ended investigation into the elements of cognition, the preconditions for the act of knowing. From time to time in the course of that investigation he tells the reader of the First Critique he does not know where it will lead. His methodology takes the form of a systematic examination of every rational possibility.68 The outcome is not predetermined, but one consequence of what Kant takes to be the prolegomena for any future metaphysics is a world view, which in the event happens to be fundamentally dualistic. Because he takes it as a given that there is a correspondence between nature within us and nature outside of us, Steiner assumes there ought to be a similar

Page 18 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt correlation between the observation of mental pictures and of other percepts. Kant, however, is arguing that different factors come into play within each of these forms of observation, for he explains:69

69 CPR A 89, B 122; pp 123-124.

70 Ph F Ch 2 [4] – [9]; ITSP, pp 21-25.

The categories of the understanding, on the other hand, do not represent the conditions under which objects are given in intuition. Objects may, therefore, appear to us without their being under the necessity of being related to the functions of understanding; and understanding need not, therefore, contain their a priori conditions. Thus a difficulty such as we did not meet with in the field of sensibility is here presented, namely, how subjective conditions of thought can have objective validity, that is, can furnish conditions of the possibility of all knowledge of objects.

For the Kantian critical idealist there may be an a priori relationship between objects of observation and the functions of the understanding, but the methodology of critical idealism leaves open the possibility that there may not be such an association.

3. Steiner’s arguments for a monistic world view

Steiner’s presentation of monism in Chapter 2 of Philosophy of Freedom already assumes that there will be a form of monism which provides for a coherent and comprehensive account of perception, cognition and possible knowledge. Because he is arguing towards his own version of monism, he begins in Chapter 2 by discounting the three possible versions of monism which arise from an initial division of experience into matter and spirit. These three versions either deny spirit to become materialism, or deny matter to become something akin to Fichte’s subjective idealism, or deny that there really is a division between matter and spirit, because they are always found together.70 Steiner’s description of materialism as an inadequate account of the ground of cognition will not meet with any opposition from neo- Kantians. His explanation of the spiritualist view does however require further discussion, particularly as Steiner’s understanding of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre forms a central aspect of his own critique of critical idealism. It is examined in Part 2 Chapter 3 of this thesis. The

third form of monism has matter and spirit united in the simplest entity (the atom), and refers presumably to Leibnitz’s concept of the monad. The difficulty here, Steiner claims, is that the problem is merely displaced to a different arena, for if it is an indivisible unity, how does a unitary entity manage to express itself in a twofold way?71 Putting aside the weakness of Steiner’s argument for the moment,72 it could be said that both the second and third forms of monism he describes might otherwise be seen as varieties of mysticism. As Steiner is himself often characterised as a mystic, and as his attitude to mysticism throughout his works appears to be somewhat ambivalent,73 something needs to be said about Steiner’s view of mysticism as a form of epistemological monism.

71 Ph F Ch2 [9]; ITSP, pp 24-25.

72 The criticism Steiner is making of Leibnitzian monism applies equally to his own argument, namely that

Page 19 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt cognition is an indivisible unity, which expresses itself in the twofold forms of perception and thinking.

73 Despite his criticisms of mysticism as a source of knowledge in Philosophy of Freedom, and which are retained in the 1918 second edition, Steiner published Christianity as Mystical Fact shortly after the appearance of the first edition.

74NOS, p. 115.

75Loc. Cit: Schelling assumed that it is possible to experience a positive meaning of the world without ever being convinced that it exists. This and his conviction that we can know of existence only through higher experience seems inconceivable to self-reflective thinking; we are led to assume that in his later years Schelling could no longer understand his earlier views, which had such an impact on Goethe.

Mysticism is discounted by Steiner as a credible epistemological position in the 10th Introduction of Nature’s Open Secret. Having surveyed other epistemological positions Steiner says of mysticism:

We are left with a third possibility – the assumption that we are able to reach an unthinkable yet very real world by means other than thinking or perception. This assumption leads us directly to mysticism. We do not need to concern ourselves here with this, because we are interested only in the relationship between thinking and being, idea and reality. Let the mystic write the epistemology of mysticism.74

Steiner criticises Schelling’s later work for its mystical quality75, and can see no merit in mysticism, because it cannot offer any greater understanding of the nature of things than can accurate observation supplemented by the capacity to grasp ideas. Mysticism is revisited in

Chapter 8 of Philosophy of Freedom, where Steiner characterises mysticism as the philosophy of feeling, and says of it:76

76Ph F Ch 8 [3]; ITSP, p. 130.

77 Ph F Ch8 [7]; ITSP, p. 131.

78 Ph F Ch 4 [32]; ITSP, pp 70-71. Steiner responds to Schopenhauer’s the perceived world is my idea by arguing: This whole proposition collapses in the face of the fact, noted above, that the eye and hand are percepts no less than the sun and the earth. And thus, in Schopenhauer’s sense, and using his style of expression, we could answer: My eye, which sees the sun, and my hand, which feels the earth, are mental pictures in exactly the same way as the sun and the earth are. With this insight and without further ado, it is clear that I cancel out Schopenhauer’s proposition.

79 Ph F Ch8 [7]; ITSP, pp 131-132.

A mystical view based solely on feeling errs in wanting to experience what it ought to know; it wants to make something that is individual, feeling, into something universal.

It is open to question whether mysticism is necessarily the philosophy of feeling, but a

Page 20 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt characteristic of any claim to mystical knowledge does appear to be the reliance upon the immediacy of experience as against the reflective quality of thinking. Steiner is right to recognize that the universalisation of the experience of, or feeling for, mystical knowledge will also need to be expressed in thinking, and this leads to an epistemological position in which ... both kinds of cognition, thinking and perceiving, remain side by side without any higher mediation between them.77 There is, as Steiner shows, a logical inconsistency and an infinite regression in the cognitive implications both of mysticism and what Steiner calls the metaphysics of will, by which he means world views akin to that expressed by Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Idea.78 Steiner summarises the logical difficulties in mysticism and will-based philosophy as follows:79

Beside the conceptual principle attainable through knowledge, there is supposed to exist a real principle of the world that can be experienced, but not grasped by thinking. In other words, because they subscribe to the proposition that what is directly perceived is real, mysticism of feeling and the philosophy of will are both types of naive realism. Yet, compared to the original naive realism, they commit the further inconsistency of making a specific form of perceiving (feeling or willing) into the sole means of cognizing existence but they can do so only by subscribing to the general proposition that what has been perceived is real. On that basis, however, they would also have to ascribe an equivalent cognitive value to external perceiving.

Mysticism and metaphysics of the will, then, are both forms of naive realism and are essentially dualistic, despite their initial appearance as monistic world views. Steiner has earlier argued that naive realism cannot provide an adequate account of cognition,80 and he believes he has demonstrated the inadequacies in any form of dualism. From Steiner’s point of view mysticism may, therefore, be discounted as the basis for a coherent epistemology.

80 Steiner discusses naive realism and naive consciousness in Chapters 4 and 5 of Philosophy of Freedom as the bases to various forms of idealism. His opinion as to the adequacy of naive realism can be gleaned from the following: When someone builds a house and the ground floor collapses during construction of the second floor, then the second floor falls along with it. Naive realism is to critical idealism as this ground floor is to the second floor. Ph F Ch5 [2]; ITSP, p. 74; Kant offers his own more confident, and more eloquent, building analogy at the beginning of the Transcendental Doctrine of Method: If we look upon the sum of all knowledge of pure speculative reason as an edifice for which we have at least the idea within ourselves, it can be said that the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements we have made an estimate of the materials, and have determined for what sort of edifice and for what height and strength of building they suffice. We have found, indeed, that although we had contemplated building a tower which should reach to the heavens, the supply of materials suffices only for a dwelling-house, just sufficiently commodious for our business on the level of experience, and just sufficiently high to allow for our overlooking it. CPR, A 707, B 735, p. 573.

81 CPR, A 23, B 37; pp 67-68: By means of outer sense, a property of our mind, we represent to ourselves objects as outside us, and all without exception in space. ... and everything which belongs to inner determinations is ... represented in relations of time. Time cannot be outwardly intuited, any more than space

Page 21 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt can be intuited as something in us.

It is clear from the outset that Steiner is arguing for a particular form of monism, which will arise from a reinterpretation, or a displacement, of the point of departure in our coming to understand the cognitive process. It is as if an incision has to be made in the manifold of inner and outer experience to find entry into the act of knowing, and that Kant and other critical idealists choose to make that incision at the meeting point of cognizing subject and perceived object. In the First Critique Kant certainly takes it as given that there is such a fundamental split between subject and object.81 This assumption also forms the starting point of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre, for which the act of knowing commences with the positing by the self-posited I of a non-positing posited not-I or other. The Wissenschaftslehre is the other principal source of Steiner’s early philosophical work. Having rejected dualism and the three categories of monism he describes, Steiner believes he can ground a coherent monistic world view by choosing to effect an incision in the manifold

of experience at a different point from the disjuncture between subject and object, or positing I and non-positing posited other.

Despite the central role it plays in his argument, Steiner’s introduction to the concept of monism in Chapter 2 of Philosophy of Freedom is somewhat perplexing. We are introduced to monism as if it were the only alternative to dualism:82

82 Ph F Ch 2 [4]; ITSP, p. 20.

83 Loc Cit.

84 Ph F Ch 2 [4]; ITSP, p. 21.

85 Loc. cit; RSV p. 25: Der Monismus richtet den Blick alleiin auf die Einheit und sucht die einmal vorhandenen Gegensaetze zu leugnen oder zu verwischen.

86 Loc Cit.

87 Ph F Ch 2 [12]; ITSP, p. 26.

88 Loc Cit.

The whole relation between the I and the world that I have portrayed here meets us on the stage of history in the contrast between a unitary world view, or monism, and a two-world theory, or dualism.

In contrast with dualism, which directs its gaze solely to the separation that human consciousness effects between the I and the world83, the monism Steiner describes directs its gaze exclusively to unity, and seeks to deny or erase the opposites, present though these are.84 Steiner’s choice of language85 suggests that monism is no more adequate than dualism, and this impression is confirmed by his comment that (n)either monism nor dualism is satisfactory, for neither does justice to the facts.86 It soon becomes apparent, however, that Steiner is referring only to the existing versions of monism and that he purports to be setting out another form of monism, which will offer a credible and comprehensive

Page 22 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt account of cognition. That form of monism will be uncovered through a return to nature and a wish to descend into the depths of our own being.87 The investigation, Steiner claims, will come to a point where we can say to ourselves: Here I am no longer merely I. There is something here that is more than I.88 That point will be the point at which the key to the act of knowing will be revealed.

Steiner arrives at the crux of his epistemological argument in Chapter 3 of Philosophy of Freedom. So far as the argument for a satisfactory form of monism is concerned, Steiner indicates in this chapter that the starting point for his theory of knowledge – the point at which he makes his incision into the given world - will be the interplay of observation and thinking. Steiner contrasts this with the departure points of other monistic and dualistic forms of idealism, and says:89

89 Ph F Ch3 [4]; ITSP, p. 30.

90 The philosophers Steiner has in mind appear to be respectively Plato, Descartes, Kant, Fichte, Schopenhauer, Brentano, Haeckel and von Hartmann.

Insofar as we are conscious of it, observation and thinking are the two points of departure for all human spiritual striving [geistige Streben des Menschen]. The workings of both common human understanding and the most complicated scientific investigations rest on these two pillars of spirit. Philosophers have proceeded from various primal oppositions [Urgegensaetzen; RSP primary antitheses] such as idea and reality, subject and object, appearance and thing-in-itself, I and Not-I, idea and will, concept and matter, force and substance, conscious and unconscious – but it can easily be shown that the contrast between observation and thinking precedes all of these as the most important antithesis for human beings.

Like the philosophers to whom he appears to be alluding,90 Steiner will also need to reunite the bifurcations created by the acts of observation and thinking if his form of monism is to represent any advance on the reductionist and mystical forms he criticises. He will need to show that his critique of observation and thinking leads to a credible monistic view of the world, and that his methodology is something other than the dualistic methodology of Kantian idealism.

4. Steiner’s concept of thinking

For Steiner it is the activity of thinking which both creates the illusion that the world is a duality and which subsequently resolves that apparent dualism and unifies the observed object and the observer in the act of knowing. This leitmotif of Steiner’s world view first

appears in The Science of Knowing,91 recurs repeatedly throughout his other epistemological works, and is reformulated in a note to the new edition of The Science of Knowing published in 1924, in which Steiner says:92

91 SK, p. 35: With the rest of experience I must penetrate the shell in order to arrive at the kernel: with thinking,

Page 23 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt shell and kernel are one undivided unity.

92 SK, p. 124.

The sense world, in its manifestation to human contemplation, is not reality. It attains its reality when connected with what reveals itself about the sense world in man when he thinks. Thoughts belong to the reality of what the senses behold; but the thought-element within sense existence does not bring itself to manifestation outside in sense existence but rather inside of man. Yet thought and sense perception are one existence. Inasmuch as the human being enters the world and views it with his senses, he excludes thought from reality; but thought then just appears in another place: inside the soul. The separation of perception and thought is of absolutely no significance for the objective world; this separation occurs only because man places himself into the midst of existence. Through this there arises for him the illusion that thought and sense perception are a duality.

Steiner develops his characterisation of thinking in Philosophy of Freedom. Steiner’s depictions of thinking also form the basis for the further disjunctions between Steiner and Kant, which are taken up in the remaining chapters of this thesis. In claiming that there is a living quality to thinking Steiner compares thinking with the growth of a plant, and in this regard his argument arises from the incorporation of Goethe’s natural science into his epistemology (Chapter 2 following). Steiner’s discussion of the dynamic, dividing and reuniting, activity of thinking has its roots in his understanding of Fichte’s concept of intellectual intuition (Chapter 3). The depiction of thinking as a creative force, which brings about the totality of things in the world, allows Steiner to claim that thinking is the source of freedom (Chapter 4).

Steiner elaborates his concept of thinking in Chapter 5 of Philosophy of Freedom. He commences by comparing the relationship between thinking per se and perception with that

between waking and dreaming,93 and then argues that thinking is the unacknowledged element in all forms of representational epistemology. It is thinking, which links perceived phenomena to mental images:94

93 Ph F Ch 5 [8]; ITSP, p. 78: ... there is, in fact, something that relates to mere perception as experiences in the waking state relate to dreaming. That something is thinking.

94 Ph F Ch 5 [9]; ITSP, pp 78-79.

95 Ph F Ch 5 [10]; ITSP, pp 79-80.

Regardless of whether or not the percept, in the form given to me, persists before and after my mental picturing, it is only with the aid of thinking that I can say anything about it. If I say that the world is my mental picture, then I have spoken the result of a process of thinking, and if my thinking is not applicable to the world, then that result is an error. Between the percept and any kind of statement about it, thinking inserts itself.

Page 24 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt Thinking, therefore, is not merely an additional, further element in the process of cognition beyond the objective phenomenon: it is integral to the phenomenon itself. Steiner attempts to explain his concept of thinking by integrating it into the observation of a living plant. In response to the contrary position of a naive realist Steiner asks:95

By what right do you declare the world to be finished without thinking? Does not the world bring forth thinking in human heads with the same necessity as it brings forth blossoms on the plant? Plant a seed in the earth. It puts forth roots and stem. It unfolds into leaves and blossoms. Set the plant before you. It links itself to a specific concept in your soul. Why does this concept belong to the plant any less than leaves and blossoms do? You might reply that leaves and blossoms are present without a perceiving subject, while the concept appears only when a human being confronts the plant. Very well. But blossoms and leaves arise in the plant only when there is earth in which the seed can be laid and light and air in which leaves and blossoms can unfold. Just so, the concept of the plant arises when thinking consciousness approaches the plant.

A difficulty with this explanation is that it is no explanation at all in terms of the discursive thinking, which constitutes rational argument. Steiner moves from one analogy – does not the world bring forth thinking in human heads with the same necessity as it brings forth blossoms on the plant? – to another – But blossoms and leaves arise in the plant ... Just so, the concept of the plant arises when thinking consciousness approaches the plant as if to

prove that the necessity of cognitive engagement with the world implies that the concept of a plant is a part of the plant. Steiner’s explanation is only plausible if it is understood as an imaginative and pictorial account of the relationship between concepts and percepts. Seen in that light, it becomes apparent that Steiner’s explanation is not intended to be a discursive, rational argument but is in itself an exercise in the engagement of the intellectus archetypus. That is, Steiner is portraying images of nature in transformation so that the reader will also be engaged in thinking imaginatively and intuitively as he, Steiner, argues for the very possibility of intuitive thinking as a cognitive process.

Thinking, Steiner claims, is not an accidental incident to an object of perception, but is active in the same sense in which natural growth itself is active. Steiner next gives the example of observing a rose bud on consecutive occasions, and compares the resulting sequence of mental pictures with the transformations of the rosebud itself:96

96 Ph F Ch5 [11]; ITSP, p. 80.

97 Ph F Ch 5 [19]; ITSP, p. 84.

If I am given a rosebud today, then the picture that offers itself to my perception is limited to the present moment. But if I put the bud in water, then I will get a completely different picture of my object tomorrow. And if I keep my eyes turned toward the rosebud, then I shall see today’s state change continuously into tomorrow’s through countless intermediate stages. The picture offering itself to me in a specific moment is but an accidental cross-section of an object that is caught up in

Page 25 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt a continual process of becoming. ...

It is completely unrealistic to grasp at accidental elements and to declare, of the picture revealed at a particular time: that is the thing.

Thinking, then, has the capacity for being alive, and it is also universal. The concept I form for association with a percept or set of percepts will be the same as yours and that of all other thinkers. In returning to one of Kant’s geometric examples Steiner concludes:

The single, unitary concept of a triangle does not become many by being thought of by many thinkers. For the thinking of many thinkers is itself a unity.97

Thus, in thinking we are given the element that unites us with the whole of the cosmos.98

98 Ph F Ch 5 [20]; ITSP, p. 84.

99 Ph F Ch 5 [21] – [22]; ITSP, pp 84-85.

From the perspective of thinking, Steiner claims, the very act of knowing is a consequence of a need on the part of thinking itself to reconnect us with the universe. The outcome of any act of knowing, therefore, is also the reunification of percept and concept. From a cosmological point of view cognition is the process, which allows for the universe to become whole:99

The urge for knowledge arises in us because thinking in us reaches out beyond our separateness and relates itself to universal world existence. Beings without thinking do not have this urge. Other things remain external to such beings. For thinking beings, a concept arises from the encounter with an external thing. The concept is that part of a thing that we do not receive from without, but from within. Knowledge, cognition is meant to accomplish the balance or union of the two elements, inner and outer.

A percept, then, is not something finished or closed off. It is one side of the total reality. The other side is the concept. The act of knowing (cognition) is the synthesis of percept and concept. Only percept and concept together make up the whole thing.

In the act of knowing, according to Steiner, each human being is participating in the creation of the cosmos.

In the final chapter of Philosophy of Freedom, which he entitles Final Questions: The Consequences of Monism, Steiner recapitulates his argument for ontological monism and articulates the relationship between ontological monism and his form of methodological monism, which is achieved by engagement in what Steiner now calls intuitive thinking. The recapitulation focuses on the role of thinking and endeavours to demonstrate the ontological and cognitive unity of the world. At this point in his argument Steiner widens his perspective somewhat and claims that thinking forms the link between each individual

Page 26 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt and the cosmos. While individuals might live with different ideas, union arises in the world of ideas, for:100

100 Ph F Final Questions, hereinafter FQ, [2] ITSP, p. 236; Steiner does not develop his concept of God in Philosophy of Freedom beyond asserting that For us, neither a human, personal God, nor force, not matter, nor even the idealess will (Schopenhauer) can be considered the universal element of the world. Ph F Ch5 [23]; ITSP, p. 85.

101 Ph F FQ [1]; ITSP, p. 231.

102 Loc Cit.

103 Ph F FQ [1]; ITSP, p. 232.

Each person’s thinking embraces only a part of the total world of ideas and, to that extent, individuals also differ through the actual content of their thinking. But the contents exist within a self-enclosed whole that contains the thought contents of all human beings. The universal, primordial Being permeating all humanity thus takes hold of us through our thinking. Life within reality, filled with thought content, is at the same time life in God. The merely inferred, not-to-be-experienced transcendent realm is based on a misunderstanding by those who believe that what is manifest does not bear within itself the reason for its existence. They do not realise that, through thinking, they can find the explanation for perception that they seek.

In addition to this, what Steiner terms the experience of thinking observation101 is the means by which the urge for cognition is able to fulfil itself:102

Monism refuses to seek the ultimate causes of the world that appear to our perceiving and thinking by making abstract inferences about something outside that world. For monism, the unity brought to the manifold multiplicity of percepts through the experience of thinking observation is both what our human urge for cognition demands, and the means by which this urge for cognition seeks entry into the physical and spiritual regions of the universe.

At this point Steiner’s perspective appears to have left epistemology and moved to more metaphysical and cosmological considerations.

In Final Questions Steiner provides some additional formulations of the role thinking plays in overcoming the inadequacies in ontological and methodological dualism. Although thinking per se appears to be sufficient to demonstrate the benefits of a monistic world view, intuitive thinking is required to provide a sufficient account of knowing and being. Steiner introduces his central epistemological concept of intuitive thinking by claiming:103

Only through the experience of intuitive thinking [intuitives Denkerlebnis] can we find our total, self-contained existence within the universe. Thinking destroys the illusion of perceiving and integrates our individual existence into the life of the cosmos. The unity of the conceptual world, which contains objective percepts, also includes the content of our subjective personality. Thinking gives us the true form of

Page 27 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt reality, as a unity enclosed within itself, while the multiplicity of percepts is only an illusion conditioned by our organisation.

What Steiner means by intuitive thinking here appears to be some combination of observation and thinking. This has already been expressed in the form of the experience of thinking observation, which implies both the act of combining thinking and observation and a conscious awareness of the process. As will become apparent in the following chapters, the primary sources for Steiner’s concept of intuitive thinking would appear to be Goethe’s anschauende Urteilskraft [intuitive judgment]104 and Fichte’s depiction of self-consciousness as an activity in which an eye is inserted.105

104 GSW vol. 40, pp 30-31.

105 Cited in FOI

106 Ph F Ch 3 [4]; ITSP, p. 29: Insofar as we are conscious of it, observation and thinking are the two points of departure for all human spiritual striving.

107 Ph F FQ [1]; ITSP, p. 234.

The strategy Steiner adopts to claim intuitive thinking as his central epistemological concept appears to be to move away from his earlier depictions of observation and thinking as the two primary and separate sources of cognition,106 and to substitute in their places perceiving and intuition, for in Final Questions he says:107

Our mental organization tears reality into these two factors. One factor is apparent to perceiving; the other to intuition. Only the union of the two – the percept integrating itself lawfully into the universe – is full reality.

He then returns to thinking and observation, but now as the unified process of thinking observation [denkende Beobachtung], as the faculty which enables us to comprehend the

totality of the real.108 Finally thinking alone, in a form in which we observe with thinking [denkend beobachten], is adopted as the central process in the act of knowing:109

108Ph F FQ [1]; ITSP, p. 234: Reality lies in thinking observation that does not one-sidedly examine either concepts or percepts by themselves, but rather considers the union of both. Steiner has earlier described thinking observation as organizing [percepts] within the conceptual system of our concepts and ideas. Ph F Ch 5 [23] ; ITSP, p. 87.

109Ph F FQ [2]; ITSP, p. 234.

Monism ... shows that thinking is neither subjective nor objective, but a principle that spans both sides of reality. When we observe with thinking, we execute a process that itself belongs to the order of events. Through thinking, we overcome, in

Page 28 14 Part 2 Chapter 4 MONISM AND DUALISM.txt experience itself, the one-sidedness of mere perceiving.

It is clear that for Steiner monism and intuitive thinking are interdependent. It is the activity of thinking which provides for a unifying methodology and it is monism which shows that thinking is neither subjective nor objective. It is also clear that Steiner will need to show how it is possible to combine perceiving and intuition, or observation and thinking, to arrive at a credible claim for intuitive thinking as the means for access to essences. Steiner’s arguments for combining perceiving and intuition are considered in Chapter 5 following and his argument for combining observation and thinking in Chapters 6 and 7.

Page 29 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt PART 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE

The second disjunction between the epistemological consequences of critical idealism and Steiner’s concept of cognition arises from Steiner’s conviction that it is possible to perceive archetypes. It is as a result of this conviction that Steiner asserts that the distinction between phenomena and noumena may be dissolved and that there are no limits to the range of human knowledge. It will be remembered that Kant specifically excludes archetypal thinking from the range of human cognitive capacity by acknowledging the possibility of an intellectus archetypus as a divine cognitive capacity, yet distinguishing that capacity from the discursive form of human reason.1 Although Kant discusses intellectual intuition in the First Critique2 he does not allude to an intuitive understanding, or the intellectus archetypus, until the Dialectic of Teleological Judgment of the Third Critique, in which he compares the absence of a human capacity for intellectual intuition with the absence of intuitive understanding. It is the peculiarity of the human understanding to seek out purpose in nature, which leads Kant to draw this comparison:3

1 CJ s77 [405] – [410]; pp 289-294.

2 CPR B xl, fn p35: If, with the intellectual consciousness of my existence, in the representation I am, which accompanies all my judgments and acts of understanding, I could at the same time connect a determination of my existence through intellectual intuition, the consciousness of a relation to something outside me would not be required. But though that intellectual consciousness does indeed come first, the inner intuition, in which my existence can alone be determined, is sensible and is bound up with the condition of time. As only God is not bound up with the condition of time, only God can have access to intellectual intuition. CPR B72, p90: … such intellectual intuition seems to belong solely to the primordial being, and can never be ascribed to a dependent being, dependent in its existence as well as in its intuition, and which through that intuition determines its existence solely in relation to given objects.

3 CJ s77 [405]; p. 289.

Hence this distinguishing feature of the idea of a natural purpose concerns a peculiarity of our (human) understanding in relation to the power of judgment and its reflection on things of nature. But if that is so, then we must here be presupposing the idea of some possible understanding different from the human one (just as, in the Critique of Pure Reason, we had to have in mind a possible different intuition if we wanted to consider ours as a special kind, namely, as an intuition for which objects count only as appearances).

For Steiner the process of reasoning is just the reverse: out of the experience of form (archetypes) in nature he deduces that human understanding includes a capacity for intuitive judgment, and likewise for intellectual intuition, with the result that there is no longer any justification for thinking of the objects of the given world as counting for nothing more than

Page 1 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt appearances.

Steiner’s conviction that it is possible to perceive archetypes is evident in his earliest epistemological works, The Science of Knowing and the Introductions which comprise Nature’s Open Secret, and it remains a leitmotif of his epistemological position. The attachment to archetypes arises largely from Steiner’s study of the methodology of Goethe’s scientific works, although it also has its roots in Steiner’s familiarity with Kantian and post- Kantian idealism. There is, however, no mention of the perception of archetypes in Steiner’s next studies, his two most conventionally philosophical works, Truth and Knowledge and Philosophy of Freedom. In these works Steiner appears to be more concerned to argue for the intuitive nature of thinking than to characterise the objects of thought. Steiner has nevertheless not abandoned the concept of the archetype, for he returns to it, with particular reference to Platonic forms, in the last work of his early philosophical period, Goethe’s World View, published in 1897.

The argument of this chapter is divided into five sections. The first section examines what is to be understood by Kant’s concept of the intellectus archetypus in the Third Critique as a type of intuitive understanding. The context in which Kant introduces and discusses archetypal thinking, the cognition of organic nature, invites the suggestion taken up by Goethe and then by Steiner that some corrective may be required to the rejection in the First Critique of any form of intuitive understanding. The second section of this chapter presents Steiner’s argument in Goethe’s World View that the division between rationalism and

empiricism, which the critical philosophy seeks to resolve, arises in any case from a misunderstanding of the Platonic conception of forms and the style of observation intended by Aristotelian empiricism. If it is possible for human consciousness to engage an archetypal understanding it must also be possible to characterise and describe it. The third and fourth sections of this chapter deal with Steiner’s elaborations of Goethe’s concept of the archetype in The Science of Knowing and Nature’s Open Secret. If, as Steiner is arguing, archetypes may be perceived in the same way as Goethe claimed to see his ideas then he is making claims about the nature of thinking as an organ of perception. The fifth section sets out Steiner’s concept of the percept and the steps he is making towards the claim that thinking operates as an organ of perception.

1. Intuitive understanding and the intellectus archetypus

The second part of the Third Critique, which includes Kant’s discussion of the intellectus archetypus, concerns our understanding of nature. Kant appears to accept that mechanistic thinking may be inadequate to account for the seeming purposiveness of organic nature, and this suggests to him that another kind of causality might need to be contemplated. Kant therefore sets up an antinomy between mechanistic and teleological judging. He distinguishes between purposiveness as a form of thinking, and purpose in nature itself, and warns against the extension of purpose as reflective judgment to the idea that purposes are determinative of nature:

Yet we are right to bring teleological judging into our investigation of nature, at least problematically, but only if we do this so as to bring nature under principles of observation and investigation by analogy with the causality in terms of purposes, without presuming to explain it in terms of that causality. Hence teleological judging

Page 2 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt is reflective, not determinative. ... Suppose, alternatively, that we attributed to nature causes that act intentionally, and thereby based teleology not merely on a regulative principle for merely judging appearances, a principle to which we could think nature as being subject in its particular laws, but based teleology also on a constitutive principle [that would allow us] to derive nature’s products from their causes. On this alternative, the concept of a natural purpose would belong no longer to reflective but

to determinative judgment. But then it would not be judgment’s own concept (as is the concept of beauty, i.e. of formal subjective purposiveness); instead it would be a rational concept and hence would introduce a new causality into natural science, even though in fact we only borrow this causality from ourselves and attribute it to other beings without wishing to assume that they and we are of the same kind.4

4 CJ pp 236-237.

5 Ibid, p. 236.

6 Ibid, p. 250.

7 Ibid [399]; p. 282.

8 Loc. cit: For purposes in nature are not given to us by the object: we do not actually observe purposes in nature as intentional ones, but merely add this concept [to nature’s products] in our thought, as a guide for judgment in reflecting on these products.

9 Loc. cit: The purposiveness that we must presuppose even for cognizing the inner possibility of many natural things is quite unthinkable to us and is beyond our grasp unless we think of it, and of the world as such, as a product of an intelligent cause (a God).

Throughout the second part of the Third Critique Kant continues to argue in the same vein, suggesting that mechanical explanations may be inadequate to account for natural phenomena, from the structure of birds,5 to the growth of a tree,6 or even a mere blade of grass7, though he cautions, at the same time, against any extension of the recognition of purpose as an explanatory device into a belief that purposes are to be found as constitutive of nature itself.8

Kant’s claim that purposiveness can be seen as regulative, but not as constitutive, of nature arises from two features of the critical philosophy. One is that the limitations to our cognitive capacities preclude us from having noumenal knowledge of natural phenomena, and could never, therefore, demonstrate that nature is purposeful in itself. That capacity would only be available to an intelligent cause; indeed, although we are unable to form a judgment one way or the other, the appearance of nature as purposeful, is an argument for the existence of such an intelligent being.9 The other feature of the critical philosophy, which precludes us from perceiving purpose as constitutive of nature, is Kant’s conception of reason and understanding as interdependent and discursive operations of the mind. At this juncture in the Third Critique Kant reminds us that reason without understanding is merely

Page 3 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

regulative,10 and claims that understanding discovers and confirms that human cognitive capacity does not extend to archetypal thinking.11 Thus, although we can conceive of an intuitive understanding12 or an intellectus archetypus, we cannot claim to possess one. As a result:

10 Ibid [401]; p. 284: But without concepts of the understanding, to which objective reality must be given, reason cannot make objective (synthetic) judgments at all. As theoretical reason it has absolutely no constitutive principles of its own, but merely regulative ones.

11 Ibid [401]; p. 284: … understanding restricts the validity of these ideas [of reason] to this condition: that, given the nature of our (human) cognitive ability, or even given any concept we can form of the ability of a finite rational being as such, all thinking must be like this and cannot be otherwise – though we are not asserting that such a judgment has its basis in the object.

12 Ibid [406]; p. 290: … we can conceive of an intuitive understanding as well (negatively, merely as one that is not discursive), which, [unlike ours,] does not (by means of concepts) proceed from the universal to the particular and thus to the individual.

13 Ibid [410]; p. 294.

14 NOS, pp 45-46.

... for external objects as appearances we cannot possibly find an adequate basis that refers to purposes, but it seems instead that, even though this basis also lies in nature, we must still search for it only in nature’s supersensible substrate, even though all possible insight into that substrate is cut off from us: hence it seems that there is absolutely no possibility for us to obtain, from nature itself, bases with which to explain combinations in terms of purposes...13

The tension which is evident at this point in the critical philosophy is at the core of Steiner’s second disjunction from Kantian epistemology, for it is precisely the capacity to perceive archetypes, which Steiner claims Goethe demonstrated in his natural science. Steiner highlights the contrast between Goethe’s archetypal perception of organic morphology and the Kantian view in the Fourth Introduction of Nature’s Open Secret. Having argued that Goethe had taken the human capacity for knowledge into organic nature, Steiner explains his objection to the Kantian view as follows:14

We can comprehend the magnitude of Goethe’s achievement when we consider the fact that Kant, the great reformer of recent philosophy, not only shared that old erroneous concept [that only inorganic nature could be explained through itself] fully, but even sought for a scientific reason why the human mind would never be able to explain organic entities. He did, in fact, acknowledge the possibility of an intuitive intellect (intellectus archetypus) capable of grasping the connection between concept

Page 4 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt and sensory reality both in organic beings and in the inorganic realm. But he denied humankind the possibility of such an intellect. According to Kant, the human intellect can conceive of the unity, or concept, of a thing only as arising from the interaction of its parts, as an analytical generalization arrived at through abstract reasoning, but not in such a way that each part appears as the result of a definite, concrete (or synthetic) unity – that is, as the result of an intuitive concept. Consequently, he considered it impossible for the human intellect to explain organic nature, the activity of which must be viewed as emanating from the whole into the parts. Kant said:

Thus, our intellect has this peculiarity with regard to our power of judgment: namely that, in cognition by it, the particulars are not determined by the universal and cannot, therefore, be derived from it alone. (Critique of Judgment, paragraph 77)

According to this, when studying organic entities, we would have to give up the possibility of knowing the necessary relationship between the idea of the whole (which can only be thought) and what appears to our senses in space and time. According to Kant, we would have to be content with knowing that such a relationship exists; but we could not satisfy the demand of our logical thinking to know how the general thought, or idea, steps out of itself and manifests as sensory reality. We would have to assume, instead, that concept and sensory reality confront each other without mediation, having been brought about by an influence external to both, such as when a person assembles some composite object – say, a machine – according to an idea. Thus any possibility of explaining the organic world was denied – in fact, its impossibility seemed to be proven.

In the course of their discussions of the intellectus archetypus Kant and Steiner use a number of terms which appear to carry overlapping meanings and which require some explanation. Kant identifies the intellectus archetypus with intuitive understanding [intuitives Verstand]15, while Steiner refers to it also as intuitive intellect [intuitive Intellekt]16. If these terms are intended to designate the capacity to perceive archetypes they will also need to be distinguished from the intellectual intuition [intellektuelle Intuition], to which Kant refers in the First Critique.17 Intellectual intuition may be a related concept, but it refers to

15 CJ [406] – [408], pp 290-293: Hence we can conceive of an intuitive understanding [einen intuitiven Verstand] as well (negatively, merely one that is not discursive), which, [unlike ours,] does not (by means of concepts) proceed from the universal to the particular and thus to the individual … And [to make these points] we do not have to prove that such an intellectus archetypus is possible.

16 NOS, p. 45.

17 The first reference appears in a footnote to the Preface to the Second Edition: If, with the intellectual consciousness of my existence, in the representation I am’, which accompanies all my judgments and acts of

Page 5 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt understanding, I could at the same time connect a determination of my existence through intellectual intuition, the consciousness of a relation to something outside me would not be required.

18 Förster, E. (2009) The Significance of s76 and s77 of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of post- Kantian Philosophy (Part 1), Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal vol 30 no 2, p7 characterises the distinction in the following way: ... Kant brings not one, but two alternative cognitive capacities into play, which are by no means reducible to one another: a non-sensible, i.e., intellectual intuition, for which possibility (thought) and actuality (being) coincide; and an intuitive understanding, which proceeds from the intuition of the whole to the parts and hence knows of no contingency in the connection of the parts to the whole. The latter is discussed in s77 [of the Third Critique], the former in s76. Although both are always identified with one another in the literature, they are not the same: in the first case the alternative is between receptivity and spontaneity, in the second case the alternative is between a discursive and intuitive understanding.

19 CJ, p. 293fn. 27: [The archetypal understanding would present originals (things in themselves); our ectypal understanding, with the help of images (perceptions) gained from our intuition, presents derivatives

(things as appearances) of those originals.]

20 GWV, p. 5, Preface to the First Edition: I have therefore stated without reserve that in my view the Goethean way of thinking has its limit, that there are regions of knowledge which remain closed to it. an altogether different faculty.18 Intellectual intuition, it will be remembered, is the antithesis of sensory intuition and is, therefore, a purported capacity for the forming of judgments independently of sensory perception. Although intellectual intuition and the intellectus archetypus can be clearly distinguished, for Kant they share the attribute that each is the necessary logical corollary to an existent capacity (the capacities for sensory intuition and the intellectus ectypus respectively), neither of which is available to human cognition, but which is constitutive of a divine intellect. Because he does not acknowledge a human intellectus archetypus Kant does not develop the concept of an archetype, and commentators identify the Kantian concept of an archetype with the thing-in-itself.19 It is an essential element of Steiner’s argument for the perception of archetypes that Kant is recapitulating a fundamental misconception of Platonic forms, which from the earliest times has pervaded . Steiner elaborates this argument in Goethe’s World View.

2. Steiner’s claim that Platonic forms have been misunderstood

By the time Steiner published Goethe’s World View in 1897 he was able to contextualize Goethe as a thinker and to separate his own epistemological stance from Goethe’s.20 The first section of Goethe’s World View, Goethe’s Place in the Development of Western Thought, identifies Goethe as a Platonic thinker, but distinguishes Goethe’s thinking from

Page 6 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt what Steiner describes as the unhealthy element of one-sided Platonism21. The remainder of the work elaborates Goethe’s thinking as it applies to organic nature, colours, geology, palaeontology and atmospheric pressure, and as it is similar to, and might be distinguished from, idealism as conceived by Hegel. As this description of it suggests, Goethe’s World View is neither a tightly constructed nor a comprehensive presentation of Goethe’s understanding of life: in particular, it does not contain any detailed discussion of Goethe’s world view as it reveals itself in his literary works.22 Despite its loose construction Goethe’s World View does nevertheless contain a number of arguments, which demonstrate both the developing nature of Steiner’s own thought and his movement away from a purely Goethean conception of intuition and archetype.

21 Ibid, p. 19.

22 Ibid, pp 155-156: In the Epilogue to the New Edition of 1918 Steiner meets this criticism with the argument that, while Goethe’s world view could also be extracted from his literary works or his art history, it is most distinctive in his view of nature.

23 Ibid, p. 14.

24 Ibid, pp 14-15: What alone can be called truly existing, because they always are, but never become nor pass away, are the ideal archetypal images of those shadow images, are the eternal ideas, the archetypal forms of all things … Of them alone, therefore, is there actual knowledge, since only that can be the object of such knowledge which always and in every respect is, not that which is, but then again is not, depending on how one looks at it. Steiner does not say which Dialogue he is citing.

Steiner introduces his argument by locating Goethe’s approach to knowledge within the Platonic tradition, but not as that tradition is generally understood. He begins with a conventional description of Platonic epistemology:

The Platonic view tears the picture of the world-whole into two parts, into the mental picture of a seeming world and into a world of ideas to which alone true eternal reality is thought to correspond.23

Steiner then distances himself from the conventional representation of the idealist tradition, for which the world of ideas, forms or archetypes constitutes a reality separate from phenomena. Steiner cites Plato to show how it is that such an interpretation has arisen.24 This, Steiner then argues, is not a statement about the nature of knowledge – as ideal rather

than phenomenal – but about how knowledge is derived. Steiner returns to the conception of knowing he advances in Philosophy of Freedom, and says:

The separation of idea and perception is justified only when one speaks of how human knowledge comes about. The human being must allow things to speak to him in a twofold way. They tell him one part of their being of their own free will. He need only listen to them. This is the part of reality that is free of ideas. The other part,

Page 7 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt however, he must coax from them. He must bring his thinking into movement, and then his inner life fills with the ideas of things.25

25 Ibid, p. 15.

26 ibid, e.g. p. 16: … the question, What relationship exists outside of man between idea and sense world? is an unhealthy one; p. 17: In order to see the full extent of the deep significance of this direction of thought, which Goethe felt to be unhealthy …; p. 19: What lives in many of the thoughts that Goethe developed … was rejection of that stream of Platonism that he experienced as unhealthy.

27 ibid, e.g. p17: … this Platonism has grown stronger through a one-sided philosophical apprehension of Christian truth …; p. 18: The one-sided view of Platonism is extended over Christianity itself.

That is, the ideas of things are not ideas independent of the phenomena – they are a hidden part of the phenomenon perceptible only through the organ of thinking. Plato’s distinction between phenomenon and archetype is a device for apprehending the ideas within the perceptible world. It has been the failure to exercise thinking in such a way as to uncover the ideas within the phenomena which has led, according to Steiner, to what he repeatedly refers to as an unhealthy26 or one-sided27 version of Platonism.

Steiner offers an historical rationale for his argument by tracing the development of Platonism in Western thought. He identifies the way in which Platonism has been taken up by the Church as the primary reason for its having become unhealthy and one-sided. The Christian juxtaposition of the life of the senses and the life beyond this world has led, Steiner argues, to a juxtaposition of experiences against ideas, of phenomena against archetypes, and to the identification of Ideas with the divine. For the Christian thinker:

The world becomes the imperfect reflection of the perfect world of ideas resting in God. The archetypal images of all things begin to be thought of as contained within

the divine spirit. The human soul, then, as the result of a one-sided apprehension of Platonism, becomes separated from the relationship of idea and reality.28

28 Ibid, p. 18.

29 Loc. cit.

30 Redding, P. (2009) Continental Idealism, Routledge: London pp 67-69 refers to the misinterpretations of Plato.

31 GWV, p. 21.

32 Loc. cit.

In support of this conception of the Christian world view Steiner cites Augustine, for whom thinking cannot provide access to archetypal ideas, which must remain within the exclusive provenance of God:

Page 8 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

Without wavering we want to believe that the thinking soul is not of the same nature as God, for He allows no community, but that the soul can, however, become enlightened through taking part in the nature of God.29

The consequence of this view of the limits to the power of thinking, according to Steiner, has been that for over a millennium Plato has been misunderstood and the Western tradition has suffered from setting itself, and seeking to resolve, meaningless questions.30

Steiner argues that the Church’s misrepresentation of Platonic thinking has been carried over into a corresponding misrepresentation of Aristotelian epistemology. Steiner portrays Aristotle’s more empiricist way of thinking as if it were very much more akin to the way in which he characterises that of Plato and Goethe, and says of Aristotle:

He saw in nature a unified being, that contains ideas just as much as it does the things and phenomena perceptible to the senses.31

Steiner argues that Aristotle’s investigation of sense experience made Christian philosophers and theologians uncomfortable, for it places the highest active principle into the world of our experience.32 Thomas Aquinas, Steiner claims, resolved their discomfort by reinterpreting Aristotle, and arguing that the proper use of Aristotelian reasoning was not to acquire knowledge, but to confirm the divine revelation of it. The consequence of this, as with the one-sided taking up of Plato, was a further unhealthy skewing of Western thought in

an opposite and complimentary direction.33 The result, from within the perspective of the history of epistemology, has been the apparently irreconcilable conflict between empiricism and idealism.

33 Loc. cit.

34 Ibid, p. 22.

35 Ibid, p. 23.

36 Loc. cit.

It is in the context of this as the background that Steiner characterises subsequent theories of knowledge as ill-fated attempts to unscramble the Church’s distortions of Platonic idealism and Aristotelian empiricism. Steiner identifies Bacon and Descartes as the first to set about founding an epistemology on human powers, and both, as Steiner sees it, had also acquired, as heritage of a degenerate thought world, the pernicious way of looking at the relationship of experience and idea.34 Bacon has no sense of the idea within experience, but merely of the particulars of nature. He gathers a multiplicity of particulars, sorts them and measures them, and abstracts from their similarities and differences to arrive at ideas. Steiner describes Bacon’s thinking, therefore, as Platonism in reverse and says of it:

Plato sees reality only in the world of ideas, Bacon only in the world of perception without ideas. Within Bacon’s conception there lies the starting point for that attitude of thinkers by which natural scientists are governed right into the present-

Page 9 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt day.35

Descartes is likewise affected by one-sided Platonism, and is afflicted in addition with what Steiner calls the original sin of Western thought, namely mistrust toward the unbiased observation of nature.36 Descartes’ radical doubt, as much as Bacon’s quantitative empiricism, is the consequence of an artificial division between experience and idea. For Descartes neither experience nor idea can be a reliable source of knowledge, and the only sure ground lies in our consciousness of thinking itself.

Steiner then sketches what he sees as similar imbalances in the epistemological position of Spinoza and Hume, before arriving at Kant. The consequence of Descartes’ reliance upon thinking to produce conviction was that …it became the striving of Descartes’ successors to determine the whole compass of the truths that thinking can develop out of itself and prove. One wanted to find the sum total of all knowledge out of pure reason.37 Spinoza’s Ethics is, therefore, constructed on the model of Euclidean geometry, with no attention given to sense-perceptible reality. For Steiner Spinoza’s epistemology can be seen as the reductio ad absurdum of misconstrued Platonism:

37 Ibid, p. 24.

38 Ibid, p. 25.

39 Ibid, pp 25-26.

Spinoza regards only the knowledge arising through this activity, foreign to reality, as one that corresponds to the true being of the world, as one that provides adequate ideas. The ideas that spring from sense perception are for him inadequate, confused, and mutilated. It is easy to see that also in this world conception there persists the one-sided Platonic way of conceiving an antithesis between perceptions and ideas. The thoughts that are formed independently of perception are alone of value for knowledge.38

For Hume, by way of contrast, it is only the phenomena and the things of the world of which we can have knowledge. The ideas we attach to them, and the relationships between them (the appearances of cause and effect), are mere habits of thought. Hume’s analysis extends to the relationship between mind and body:

The human being is habituated further to seeing that a movement of his body follows upon a thought of his spirit. He explains this to himself by saying that his spirit has caused the movement of his body. Human ideas are habits of thought, nothing more. Only perceptions have reality.39

This might therefore be seen as the reductio ad absurdum of Bacon’s Platonism in reverse.

The end result, according to Steiner, is that the radical epistemological positions, which arise from unhealthy, one-sided Platonism and from a corresponding misunderstanding of Aristotelian

empiricism find their synthesis in Kant. Kant, Steiner says, brings to his critique three preconceptions, which constitute the roots of the Kantian thought structure:40

Page 10 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

40 Ibid, p. 26.

41 Loc. cit: this writer’s summary of Steiner’s argument

42 ibid, pp 27-28.

(1) there are necessary truths, which are produced by pure thinking free of any experience – the truths of mathematics and pure physics; (2) experience cannot provide necessary truths, and the world of perception is not to be trusted; and (3) as Hume has shown, the ideas into which thinking combines the individual perceptions do not stem from experience, but thinking adds them to experience.41

If the ideas of experience do not stem from experience they must be necessary truths of pure thinking, and our knowledge of experience can be nothing more than the contingent perceptions of appearances. We can therefore have no knowledge of things-in-themselves. In coming to these conclusions Kantian critical idealism, according to Steiner, represents the dead end of a continuum of progressive distortions of Plato’s account of the ground for knowledge. Steiner concludes:

One-sided Platonism brought forth in Kant a fruit that paralyses knowledge. Plato turned away from perception and directed his gaze upon the eternal ideas, because perception did not seem to him to express the being of things. Kant, however, renounces the notion that ideas open any real insight into the being of the world, just so they retain the quality of the eternal and necessary. Plato holds to the world of ideas, because he believes that the true being of the world must be eternal, indestructible, unchangeable, and he can ascribe these qualities only to ideas. Kant is content if only he can maintain these qualities for the ideas. Ideas then no longer need to express the being of the world at all.42

Although Steiner does not cite Kant in Goethe’s World View it may be that support can be found for Steiner’s position within other sections of the critical philosophy. Kant’s discussion of Plato in the introductory section to the Analytic of Teleological Judgment of the Third Critique suggests, however,

that Kant also acknowledges that Plato claimed an inherent connection existed between ideas and being:43

43 CJ, pp 240-241.

44 Kant also warns against the dangers in a misinterpretation of Plato. Referring to the apparent purposefulness in nature and the desire of the human intellect to find purpose, Kant says: Surely it is pardonable if, as the result of a misunderstanding, this admiration [of nature] gradually increased to the point of fanaticism [for pure intuition]. CJ, p. 241.

Plato, himself a master of [geometry], was overcome by enthusiasm [when he saw] that the

Page 11 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt original character of things is such that it can be discovered without any experience whatever, and that the mind is able to derive the harmony of beings from their supersensible principle; (to [these beings] we must add the properties of numbers, with which the mind plays in music). It was this enthusiasm that lifted Plato above empirical concepts to ideas that he thought could be explained only by an intellectual community [between ourselves and] the origin of all beings. No wonder he turned away from his school everyone who was ignorant of geometry; for what Anaxagoras inferred from objects of experience and their connection in terms of purposes, Plato meant to derive from the pure intuition residing within the human intellect [Geist].

Kant argues for a more fundamental distinction between ideas and sense perceptible experience than Plato (except for the synthetic a priori truths of geometry and arithmetic), but he does not appear to have misunderstood Plato in the manner Steiner suggests.44 Indeed, Kant appears to have understood Plato in the same way as Steiner does; the difference between them is that Kant is careful not to infer that purpose is constitutive of organic nature from the regulatory function of the pure intuition residing within the human intellect, while Steiner sees the capacity for pure intuition as confirmation that there must be forms (archetypes) within nature itself, and that these forms must be available to cognition.

3. Steiner’s adaptation of Goethe’s conception of archetypes

In Part 1 of this thesis an account was given of how Goethe conceived his way of seeing nature (Part 1 Chapter 2), and what might be understood by the concept of an archetype (Part 1 Chapter 3). Goethe’s use of the concept of the archetype arises in the context of his observations of natural phenomena, and is limited to his conception of the living quality of nature. Goethe did not claim to be putting forward a methodology for the perception of all phenomena, and nor did he claim to be offering a critique of Kantian idealism. Steiner is making both of these claims. He is also claiming that Goethe’s conception of archetypes may be adapted to resolve the

ontological split between noumena and phenomena inherent in transcendental idealism. The way in which Steiner understands archetypes, therefore, is as a ground for appearances within the phenomena, and as a perceptible form, which renders the concept of the thing-in-itself unwarranted and unnecessary.

As Steiner is endeavouring to incorporate archetypes into the idealist tradition, it is unsurprising that the first record of archetypes in his epistemology arises from before his work on the Introductions to Nature’s Open Secret and The Science of Knowing. In a letter to a friend of January 1881 Steiner reports having found confirmation for his own belief in essences in an observation made by Schelling:45

45 Steiner, R. (1987) Briefe, Vol. 1, p. 13, translated by Irene Czech and Regina Erich, cited in König, K. (2008) Karl König: My Task, Floris Books: Edinburgh

Dear trusted friend! It was on the night of January 10 to 11 when I did not sleep for one moment. I finally lay down on my bed after working until half past midnight on a number of philosophical problems. My intention, last year, had been to establish whether Schelling’s statement was true, when he says: We all have the secret and wonderful capacity to withdraw from transience and, above all, from everything that

Page 12 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt comes towards us from outside, into our innermost, unclothed selves and therein to behold eternity’s unchanging permanence in us.’ I believed then and still believe now that I then discovered in clarity that inner capacity – having already sensed it for a long time. The whole philosophy of idealism now stood before me in an essentially modified form. What is a sleepless night compared to such a discovery!

In contrast with Fichte, for whom the given world is posited by consciousness, Schelling conceives of nature as an independent ground of being, which generates a dialectic operation between the real and the ideal, and thereby produces the activity of consciousness. Schelling’s grounding of knowledge in nature, and in our capacity to behold eternity’s unchanging permanence in us reinforces Steiner’s conviction that it must be to possible to justify an epistemology that does not leave the world divided between appearances and essences.

Schelling’s Naturphilosophie is nevertheless the intellectual product of an aesthetic form of transcendental idealism. It is not at all a philosophy of nature in Goethe’s or in the modern sense of the term, in that it does not rely upon any close observation of nature. Like Goethe and Steiner Schelling claims that there is no unbridgeable split between phenomena and noumena, and that this is because the intellectual activity which generates knowledge is not reason, but intuition. For Fichte intuition describes the state of consciousness, which necessarily precedes reason. For Schelling intellectual intuition is not only a precondition of cognition: it generates an aesthetic intuition, and culminates in the capacity to create works of art. In the System of Transcendental Idealism Schelling asserts:

The whole of philosophy starts, and must start, from a principle which, as the absolute principle, is also at the same time the absolutely identical. An absolutely simple and identical cannot be grasped or communicated through description, nor through concepts at all. It can only be intuited. Such an intuition is the organ of all philosophy. – But this intuition, which is an intellectual rather than a sensory one, and has as its object neither the objective nor the subjective, but the absolutely identical, in itself neither subjective nor objective, is itself merely an internal one, which cannot in turn become objective for itself: it can become objective only through the second intuition. This second intuition is the aesthetic.46

46Schelling, F. (1978) System of Transcendental Idealism, cited in Schelling, F. (1989) The Philosophy of Art, translator’s introduction at xxxiii. Steiner is less enthusiastic about Schelling by the time of the publication, in 1890, of the second batch of Introductions to Nature’s Open Secret: NOS, p. 115: Schelling assumed that it is possible to experience a positive meaning of the world without ever being convinced that it exists. This and his conviction that we can know of existence only through higher experience seems inconceivable to self-reflective thinking: we are led to assume that in his later years Schelling could no longer understand his earlier views, which had such an impact on Goethe.

Steiner develops his adaptation of Goethe’s conception of archetypes in The Science of

Page 13 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt Knowing and in the Introductions, which comprise Nature’s Open Secret. The first five Introductions were published at about the same time as Nature’s Open Secret (1884), the second batch (Introductions 6 to 14) in 1887, Introductions 15 and 16 in 1890 and Introductions 17 and 18 in 1897, at around the same time as the publication of Goethe’s

World View. The Introductions which deal most with Steiner’s conception of archetypes are Introductions 4, 9, 10, 11 and 16.

3.1 Archetypes in The Science of Knowing

Steiner’s first presentation of archetypes occurs in a section of The Science of Knowing entitled The Activity of Knowing Nature.47 Steiner deals separately with the activities of knowing inorganic and organic natural phenomena. In his discussion of inorganic nature Steiner identifies what he calls the archetypal phenomenon with the laws of nature. He gives as an example the factors, which determine the path of a stone thrown horizontally, and establishes that these will include 1) the propelling force that I exert; 2) the force with which the earth draws the stone; 3) the force of air resistance.48 In this example ... the first two forces are the essential ones, which determine the particular nature of the path, whereas the third force is secondary49 and it is the essential forces that constitute the archetype:

47 SK, pp 75 – 100.

48 ibid, p. 78.

49 ibid, p. 79.

50ibid, p. 80; writer’s emphasis as to had to occur

Such a phenomenon, now, in which the character of the process follows directly and in a transparently clear way out of the nature of the pertinent factors, is called an archetypal phenomenon (Urphaenomen) or a basic fact (Grundtatsache).

This archetypal phenomenon is identical with objective natural law. For in it is expressed not only that a process has occurred under certain conditions, but also that it had to occur.50

Steiner does not say how it is he knows that the first two forces are the essential ones – that is, whether he is simply drawing upon his knowledge of Newtonian physics, or whether his characterisation of the laws of nature as archetypal phenomena implies the exercise of an enhanced form of thinking, or some form of intuition, for their apprehension. So far as inorganic nature is concerned, if the archetypal is nothing more than a description of

objective natural law, what had to occur, then there is nothing about it which would justify the postulation of any form of knowing nature other than the Newtonian physics accepted by Kant as a scientific method consistent with a critique of reason.51

51 CPR, B xiii-xiv, p. 20: Even physics, therefore, owes the beneficent revolution in its point of view entirely to

Page 14 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt the happy thought, that while reason must seek in nature, not fictitiously ascribe to it, whatever as not being knowable through reason’s own resources had to be learnt, if learnt at all, only from nature, it must adopt as its guide, in so seeking, that which it has itself put into nature.

52 SK, pp 84-100.

53 Ibid, p. 85: At the end of the eighteenth century the universally prevailing view was that there was no science to explain living phenomena in the sense in which physics, for example, is a science that explains things. Kant, in fact, tried to establish a philosophical basis for this view.

54 Loc. Cit.

Steiner’s argument is of greater interest when the enquiry moves onto organic nature.52 Steiner notes that, until the early 19th century, scientists did not attempt to account for the lawfulness of living organisms, because it was assumed that all life was created purposively by a being operating outside of nature.53 As a consequence of this, philosophers of science excluded organic nature from the field of scientific enquiry. Seen in this context Kant’s argument in the Critique of Judgment against the availability of the intellectus archetypus to human consciousness becomes the justification for not extending scientific enquiry further into the organic sciences. Instead, as Steiner points out, organic nature then becomes explicable only in terms of the regulative demands of consciousness:54

(Kant) considered our intellect to be such that it could go only from the particular to the general. The particular, the individual, things are given to him, and from them he abstracts his general laws. Kant calls this kind of thinking discursive, and considers it to be the only kind granted to the human being. Thus in his view there is a science only for the kinds of things where the particular, taken in and for itself, is entirely without concept and is only summed up under an abstract concept. In the case of organisms Kant did not find this condition fulfilled. Here the single phenomenon betrays a purposeful, i.e. a conceptual arrangement. The particular bears traces of the concept. But, according to the Koenigsberg philosopher, we lack any capacity to understand such beings [solche Wesen]. Understanding is possible for us only in the case where the concept and individual thing are separated, where the concept represents something general, and the individual thing represents something particular. Thus there is nothing left us but to base our observations about organisms

upon the idea of purposefulness: to treat living beings as though a system of intentions underlay their manifestation. Thus Kant has here established non-science scientifically, as it were.

Steiner records that in the later 19th century, as the notion of purposeful creation died away, organic nature did become the subject of scientific enquiry. The problem now, however, was that the methodology of inorganic nature was simply transferred to the study of living organisms, and as a result:

Page 15 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

One considered the method employed here to be altogether the only scientific one, and thought that for organics to be scientifically possible, it would have to be so in exactly the same sense in which physics is, for example. The possibility was forgotten, however, that perhaps the concept of what is scientific is much broader than the explanation of the world according to the laws of the physical world ...

... All this comes from the erroneous view that the method of a science is extraneous to its objects of study, that it is not determined by these objects but rather by our own nature. It is believed that one must think in a particular way about objects, that one must indeed think about all objects – throughout the entire universe – in the same way.55

55 Ibid, pp 86-88.

56 CJ, s77, pp 288-294 bears the heading: On the Peculiarity of the Human Understanding that makes the Concept of a Natural Purpose possible for us.

57 SK, pp 96-97: The kind of thinking in which the content appears in direct connection with the formal element has always been called intuitive.

In putting the case against the use of the same scientific method for organic nature as for inorganic nature in this way Steiner is exaggerating the distinction between his approach and Kant’s. It is true that Kant argues that the method of a science is determined by our own nature,56 but Steiner’s argument also includes a critique of the possible modes of cognition. Steiner has not yet fully developed his concept of intuitive thinking by the time of The Science of Knowing, but he refers to intuition for the first time, and argues for the availability of Goethe’s version of the intellectus archetypus, intuitive judgment [anschauende Urteilskraft], as the mode of cognition for the perception of archetypes.57

Intuition appears repeatedly as a scientific principle. The English philosopher Reid calls it an intuition if, out of our perception of outer phenomena (sense impressions), we were to acquire at the same time a conviction that they really exist. Jacobi thought that in our feeling of God we are given not only this feeling itself but at the same time the proof that God is. This judgment is also called intuitive. What is characteristic of intuition, as one can see, is always that more is given in the content than this content itself; one knows about a thought- characterization, without proof, merely through direct conviction. ...

... Our power of judgment must be a thinking beholding, and a beholding thinking. We have to do here, as was expounded by the first time by Goethe, with a power to judge in beholding (anschauende Urteilskraft). Goethe thereby revealed as a necessary form of apprehension in the human spirit that which Kant wanted to prove was something the human being, by his whole make-up, is not granted.

58 Ibid, p. 90: In inorganic nature we perceive a fact and see, in order to explain it, a second, a third fact and so on; and the result is that the first fact appears to us to be the necessary consequence of the other ones. In

Page 16 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt the organic world this is not so. There, in addition to the facts, we need yet another factor. ...

But what is that basic factor? It can, after all, be nothing other than what manifests in the particular in the form of the general. In the particular, however, a definite organism always manifests. That basic factor is therefore an organism in the form of the general: a general image of the organism, which comprises within itself all the particular forms of organisms.

59 CJ, [406]-[407]; p. 291.

The essence of the mode of cognition for the perception of archetypes, according to Steiner, is that the mind has the capacity to move from the general to the particular.58 In characterising the mode of consciousness for perceiving archetypes in this way Steiner is in agreement with Kant. Steiner believes, however, that the universality of nature confirms the availability of anschauende Urteilskraft or the intellectus archetypus. For Kant the universality and diversity of nature remain something of a quandary, for they require him to postulate the possibility of an intellectus archetypus, yet regard it as unavailable to human cognition:59

Therefore our understanding has this peculiarity as regards judgment: when cognition occurs through our understanding, the particular is not determined by the universal and therefore cannot be derived from it alone. And yet this particular in nature’s diversity must (through concepts and laws) harmonize with the universal in order that the particular can be subsumed under the universal. But, under these circumstances, this harmony must be very contingent, and must lack a determinate principle as far as the power of judgment is concerned.

How then can we at least conceive of the possibility of such a harmony – one that is presented as contingent and hence as possible only through a purpose that aims at it – between the things of nature and our judgment? To do this, we must at the same time conceive of a different understanding: without as yet attributing any [concept of a] purpose to this understanding, we can then present this harmony between the [particular] natural laws and our judgment as necessary relative to that understanding, [even though] our own understanding can conceive of this harmony only as mediated by purposes.

It is tempting to think that the as yet suggests Kant may also arrive at a point at which he, too, can allow for a human intellectus archetypus, but that is not what the original implies.60

60 KU, p. 360: Um nun gleichwohl die Möglichkeit einer solchen Zusammenstimmung der Dinge der Natur zur Urteilskraft (welche wir als zufällig, mithin nur durch einen darauf gerichteten Zweck als möglich vorstellen) wenigstens denken zu können, müssen wir uns zugleich einen anderen Verstand denken, in Beziehung auf welchen, und zwar vor allem ihm beigelegten Zweck, wir jene Zusammenstimmung der Naturgesetzte mit unserer Urteilskraft, die für unseren Verstand nur durch das Verbindungsmittel der Zwecke denkbar ist, als notwendig vorstellen können.

61 SK, p. 90.

Page 17 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

62 Ibid, pp 90-91.

63Ibid, p. 91: Just as natural law provides us with the possibility of recognizing each individual occurrence as a part of one great whole, so the typus puts us in a position to regard the individual organism as a particular form of the archetypal form.

Steiner then argues in The Science of Knowing that the starting point for knowledge of organic nature is ... a general image of the organism, which comprises within itself all the particular forms of organisms.61 He describes this general image, the typus, in the following way:62

This typus is not developed in all its completeness in any single organism. Only our thinking, in accordance with reason, is able to take possession of it, by drawing it forth, as a general image, from phenomena. The typus is therewith the idea of the organism: the animalness in the animal, the general plant in the specific one.

... The typus is something altogether fluid, from which all the particular species and genera, which one can regard as subtypes or specialized types, can be derived. The typus does not preclude the theory of evolution. It does not contradict the fact that organic forms evolve out of one another. It is only reason’s protest against the view that organic development consists purely in sequential, factual (sense-perceptible) forms. It is what underlies this whole development. It is what establishes the interconnection in all this endless manifoldness. It is the inner aspect of what we experience as the outer forms of living things. The Darwinian theory presupposes the typus.

Steiner concludes that The typus is the true archetypal organism ... [which] plays the same role in the organic world as natural law does in the inorganic.63 The way in which the typus and natural law are similar is that they are both said to underlie sense perceptible phenomena, but otherwise they are very different. Kant’s concept of a natural purpose is characterised

as identifiable with natural law, but Steiner conceives of the typus as perceptible to the senses.

Steiner also attempts to describe the mode of cognition required to perceive the typus in The Science of Knowing. His method is to contrast this mode of cognition with the reasoning applied to derive laws of nature in the inorganic sciences:

There it was a matter of showing that a particular sense-perceptible fact can occur in this and in no other way, because this or that natural law exists. The fact and the law confront each other as two separate factors, and absolutely no further spiritual work is necessary except, when we become aware of a fact, to remember the law that applies. This is different in the case of a living being and its manifestations. Here it is a matter of developing, out of the typus that we must have grasped, the individual form arising in our experience. We must carry out a spiritual process of an essentially different kind. We may not simply set up the typus, as something finished in the way

Page 18 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt the natural law is, over against the individual phenomenon.64

64 Ibid, pp 92-93.

65 Ibid, p. 93.

The essentially different process is first to grasp the typus and then to work from the general (the typus) to the particular and develop ... the individual form arising in our experience. To achieve this development we must also treat the relationship between typus and organism as more fluid than the relationship between law and phenomenon:

With the typus we must develop the particular case confronting us out of the archetypal form. We may not place the typus over against the individual form to see how it governs the latter; we must allow the individual form to go forth out of the typus. A law governs the phenomenon as something standing over it; the typus flows into the individual being; it identifies itself with it.65

Steiner is alive to the criticism that his account might appear to be unscientific in the conventional sense.66 He compares and contrasts organic science, therefore, with the paradigmatic inorganic sciences, mechanics and physics, and argues:

66 Ibid, p. 94: It is possible to make an objection here. If the typical form is altogether something fluid, how is it at all possible to set up a chain of sequential, particular types as the content of an organic science?

67 Ibid, pp 93-95.

If an organic science wants to be a science in the sense that mechanics or physics is, it must therefore know the typus to be the most general form and must then show it also in diverse, ideal, separate shapes. Mechanics is indeed also a compilation of diverse natural laws where the real determinants are altogether hypothetically assumed. It must be no different in organic science...

Just as in the inorganic we lead a phenomenon back to a law, so here we develop a specific form out of the archetypal form...

Just as mechanics is a system of natural laws, so organic science is meant to be a series of developmental forms of the typus...

An organic science is possible which, like mechanics, is science in altogether the strictest sense. It is just that the method is a different one. The method of mechanics is to prove things...

But we can do nothing with this proving method in organic science. The typus ... does not point, like a natural law, beyond itself. The particular organic forms can therefore be developed only out of the general typus form, and the organic beings [organischen Wesen] that arise in experience must coincide with one such derivative

Page 19 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt form of the typus. The developmental method must here take the place of the proving one.67

Steiner’s contrast between the proving method’ and the developmental method’ will need some unpacking. What he has told us so far about the developmental method is that it requires us to grasp the typus rather than to place the typus over against the individual form to see how it governs the latter. The typus which is grasped must coincide with the organic forms under observation. Steiner will need to say more about the sense in which the typus is grasped, and in what sense this amounts to a perception of the typus rather than the derivation of a concept in the same manner as a natural law is derived. He will also need to

explain the process, which allows for the typus to coincide with the organic phenomena under observation if the relationship is to be different from that between inorganic phenomena and the natural laws which govern them.

At the end of the section of The Science of Knowing devoted to the activity of knowing nature Steiner summarises the difference between observation of inorganic and organic nature as follows:68

68 Ibid, p. 100.

69 Loc. cit.

70 Ibid, p. 90: But what is that basic factor? It can, after all, be nothing other than what manifests in the particular in the form of the general.

The ideal of inorganic science is to grasp the totality of all phenomena as a unified system, so that we approach every phenomenon with the consciousness of recognising it as a part of the cosmos. In organic science, on the other hand, the ideal must be, in the typus and in its forms of manifestation, to have with the greatest possible perfection what we see develop in the sequence of single beings. Leading the typus through all the phenomena is what matters here. In inorganic science it is the system; in organic science it is comparison (of each individual form with the typus).

Steiner then refers to the developing method as the comparing method employed by Goethe.69 Both of these depictions of Steiner’s method – the developing method and the comparing method - are amplifications of his original description of the basic factor in the perception of archetypes as the purported capacity of the mind to move from the general to the particular.70 Beyond what has been said about the developing method earlier Steiner does not argue for these amplifications in The Science of Knowing. By the end of The Science of Knowing we are left with the impression that Steiner has taken Kant’s concept of the intellectus archetypus as the starting point for an elaboration of Goethe’s anschauende Urteilskraft and his scientific method, but that he has not been able to demonstrate the actuality of it.

4. Archetypes in Nature’s Open Secret

Page 20 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

In 1882 Steiner was invited to edit Goethe’s scientific writings for the publication of Kürschner’s National Literature71. Steiner began the work while he was still in Vienna, but did not complete it until he had been in Weimar for some years, and was about to leave for Berlin in 1897. In the course of that period Steiner also wrote his specifically epistemological works. Steiner’s commentaries consist of 18 Einleitungen [Introductions], which are now reprinted as Einleitungen zu Goethes Naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften72, and comprise the first of the 362 volumes of Steiner’s collected works. They are available in English as Goethe the Scientist73, Goethean Science74 and most recently as Nature’s Open Secret. The first five Introductions were published in 1884 along with The Science of Knowing. Introductions 6 to 14 appeared in 1887 and Introductions 15 and 16 in 1890, before Truth and Knowledge and Philosophy of Freedom. The final two Introductions, 17 and 18, did not appear until 1897, at around the time of the publication of Goethe’s World View. Most of the Introductions are directed to consideration of Goethe’s scientific discoveries in the specific domains referred to in Part 1 Chapter 2 of this thesis. Introductions 4, 9, 10, 11 and 16 contain extended accounts of the epistemological implications of Goethe’s scientific method, and in particular the concept of the archetype and of Goethe’s notion of anschauende Urteilskraft.

71 Goethes naturwissenschaftliche Schriften, edited by Rudolf Steiner, Union Deutsche Verlagsgeselleschaft,

Stuttgart-Berlin-Leipzig, 1884-97 (1921), four volumes

72 Steiner, R. (1999) Einleitungen zu Goethes Naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften, Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach , hereinafter GNS

73 Steiner, R. (1950) Goethe the Scientist, Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, NY

74 Steiner, R. (1988) Goethean Science, Mercury Press: Spring Valley, NY

4.2 Introduction 4

In the first group of Introductions Steiner presents the concept of the archetype and relates it to Kant’s discussions of intuitive understanding and the intellectus archetypus in s76 and s77 of the Third Critique. In Introduction 2 Steiner says of the archetype:75

75 NOS, pp 17-18.

76 Ibid, p. 45, cited at pp 5-6 above.

77 Ibid, p. 44.

Now, when we consider this archetypal plant itself, we can say:

Anything that is alive is a self-contained whole that brings forth its various states out

Page 21 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt of itself. Both in the spatial juxtaposition of its members and in the succession of its stages over time every living entity manifests interrelationships that do not appear to be determined by the sense perceptible characteristics of its members, nor by some kind of mechanical causality through which earlier stages determine later ones. These interrelationships are governed, rather, by a higher principle that stands above its members and stages. It is inherent in the nature of the whole that a specific stage arises as the first, another as the last; and the sequence of the intermediary stages is also determined within the idea of the whole; what comes before is dependent on what comes later, and vice versa. In short, in a living organism there is development of one thing out of another, transition from one stage into another - there is no finished, completed existence of any one particular, but rather continuous becoming.

Steiner elaborates the contrast he presents here between the higher principle within living entities and mechanical causality in a footnote to Introduction 4. The footnote appears shortly before the account given by Steiner76 of Kant’s rejection of the intellectus archetypus as a faculty of human cognition. In the footnote Steiner elevates the distinction between organic and inorganic nature to one of principle, and says of it:77

Herein lies the difference between organisms and machines. What is essential in the machine is only the interaction of its parts. The unifying principle that governs that interaction does not exist in the object itself but outside it as a plan in the head of its builder. Only the most extreme shortsightedness can deny that the difference between an organism and a mechanism is precisely the fact that in a machine the determining principle governing the interrelationship of its parts is external (and abstract), whereas in an organism it assumes a real existence in the object itself. Thus, the sense-perceptible conditions of an organism do not appear merely to follow one from another, but are governed by an inner principle that is imperceptible to the senses. In this sense this principle is no more perceptible to the senses than the plan in the builder’s head, which is also present only to the mind. Essentially, it is such a

plan, except that it has entered the organism’s inner being and affects it directly, not through a third party, the builder.

The archetype is not a mere intellectual construct for Steiner: it is external to the observer, and it inhabits the object.

The distinction Steiner is drawing here between an external principle and a principle which assumes a real existence in the object itself is what requires him to postulate both the archetype as such and a distinct human capacity to perceive the archetype. It also leads him to draw a distinction between ideas and concepts, which he derives from Goethe, and for which the idea appears to be the equivalent of the archetype, or the typus in the case of organic nature:

The idea is not a summary of experience; it produces experience. Goethe expresses this as follows: A concept is the sum of experience, an idea is its result; to understand a concept requires intellect, to comprehend an idea requires reason.

… The relationship between what we perceive – the material element in our knowledge given through the outer senses – and the concept – or formal means of

Page 22 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt recognizing the necessity of what we perceive – is their objective need for each other. But this relationship is such that the concept does not live in the particulars of an experienced event but in the interrelationship of those particulars.

… In organic nature the diverse particulars of an organism do not have such an external relationship to one another. The unity manifests in what is perceived; it comes into existence together with the diversity and is identical with it. … The concept does not merely play the role of a summarizing element with its object outside itself; it has united with its object completely. The object of our perception is no longer different from the concept through which we think it; we perceive that concept itself as idea.78

78 Ibid, pp. 52-53.

In distinguishing as he does between concepts of inorganic and organic nature Steiner is proposing something beyond Goethe’s distinction between the sum and the result of experience. For Steiner concepts of organic nature dissolve into, and are themselves perceived as, ideas.

It is interesting to compare Steiner’s characterisation of ideas and concepts with what Kant has to say about the matter. In Book 1 of the Transcendental Dialectic of the First Critique Kant is about to introduce transcendental ideas, and in doing so explains what he means by concepts and ideas. For Kant there are two kinds of concepts, namely concepts of reason and concepts of understanding, the distinction between them being that: Concepts of reason enable us to conceive, concepts of understanding to understand – ([as employed in reference to] perceptions).79 Steiner’s distinction is not this one, but can be seen as a further division of concepts of understanding into concepts of understanding inorganic and organic nature respectively. Kant begins his discussion of ideas by referring to Platonic ideas, which he describes as archetypes of the things themselves,80 and concludes it with a categorisation of the various forms of representations in an effort to ... preserve the expression idea’ in its original meaning, that it may not become one of those expressions which are commonly used to indicate any and every species of representation, in a happy-go-lucky confusion, to the consequent detriment of science.81 Kant then equates ideas with concepts of reason.82 One manifestation of this second disjunction between Steiner and Kant, then, is that Kant insists that ideas be identified with concepts of reason, while Steiner identifies ideas with the concepts of understanding of organic nature.

79 CPR, A311, B367, p. 308.

80 Ibid, A313, B370, p. 310: For Plato ideas are archetypes of the things themselves, and not, in the manner of the categories, merely keys to possible experiences. In his view they have issued from highest reason, and from that source have come to be shared in by human reason ...

81 Ibid, A319, B376, p. 314.

82Ibid, A320, B376, p. 314: The concept is either an empirical or a pure concept. The pure concept, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding alone (not in the pure image of sensibility), is called a notion. A

Page 23 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt concept formed from notions and transcending the possibility of experience is an idea or concept of reason.

These differing notions of the relationship between ideas and concepts also account for why it is that Kant can postulate an intellectus archetypus but deny that we have a capacity for it, while Goethe and Steiner insist that such a capacity must exist. Kant understands that Plato regarded ideas as archetypes of the things themselves, but it is clear he has rejected that

notion when he identifies ideas with concepts of reason. Goethe and Steiner, on the other hand, identify ideas respectively with the results of experience and with concepts of the understanding. They therefore need to argue for a mode of cognition, which extends beyond the discursive reasoning of Kant’s intellectus ectypus, because they are postulating ideas as perceptible phenomena and for ideas to be perceptible there must be a sense organ to perceive them. For Goethe the solution lies in the refinement of the faculty of judgment into intuitive or perceiving judgment [anschauende Urteilskraft], so that through the idea the observer becomes identified with the phenomenon. Steiner describes Goethe’s approach as follows:

(Goethe) maintained that, when dealing with objects of experience, the idea is an organ for apprehending the necessary interrelationships or phenomena that would otherwise be perceived blindly as random occurrences in space and time. Because the idea may not add anything new to the object, it follows that the object in its actual essence is of an ideal nature; in fact, all of empirical reality must have two sides – one through which it is of a particular, individual nature, and another through which it is of an ideal, universal nature.83

83 NOS, p. 67.

84 SK, pp 96-97: The kind of thinking in which the content appears in direct connection with the formal element has always been called intuitive.

Steiner’s own solution is to retain the separation between the idea as sense organ and as sense perceptible phenomenon (or archetype), and to elaborate Kant’s intellectus archetypus as the organ for the perception of archetypes in such a way that it takes on the characteristics of Goethe’s anschauende Urteilskraft.

It would seem to be for this reason that Steiner now introduces intuition, which, as we have seen, also enters into the argument of The Science of Knowing.84 Steiner refers to intuitive intellect, intuitive concept and intuitive knowledge as a way of describing the form of understanding necessary for the perception of archetypes. In Introduction 4, published around the same time as The Science of Knowing, Steiner writes:

We need a kind of thinking that can give a thought a substance not derived from outer sensory perception, a thinking that comprehends not only what is perceived externally by the senses, but also apprehends pure ideas apart from the sensory world. A concept that is not abstracted from the sensory world but whose content develops out of itself and only out of itself can be called an intuitive concept [intuitiven Begriff], and the comprehension of such a concept may be called intuitive knowledge. What follows from this is clear: A living organism can be comprehended only through an

Page 24 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt intuitive concept. Goethe actually demonstrated that it is in fact possible for us to know in this way.85

85 NOS, p. 50.

86GNS, p83: Man kann nun einen Begriff, der nicht durch Abstraktion aus der Sinnenwelt genommen ist, sondern der einen aus ihm und nur aus ihm fließenden Gehalt hat, einen intuitiven Begriff und die Erkenntnis desselben eine intuitive nennen.

87 SK, p. 96.

88 NOS, p78: Thinking relates to ideas as the eye relates to light and the ear to sound; it is an organ of perception. … What is given to the senses is only half of the given. The other half consists of ideas, which are also objects of experience – and accessible to the organ of thinking.

Intuition consists here in a thinking that ... apprehends pure ideas apart from the sensory world and out of which intuitive concepts may be generated. Steiner does not explain what he means by intuitive concepts, nor whether these would be concepts of reason or concepts of understanding. It may be that they are not concepts of understanding, for Steiner adopts the term intuitive’ rather than use anschauende’, which is also translated into English as intuitive’, and which would more readily refer back to Goethe’s purported faculty of anschauende Urteilskraft.86 It is evident from all of this that Steiner has not yet arrived at the notion of intuitive thinking as such, but his argument for an intuitive form of understanding has advanced from his introduction of intuition in The Science of Knowing, where he identifies it merely as those occasions when more is given in the content than this content itself.87

4.2 Introduction 9

Although there is some reference to his developing understanding of perception and thinking in Introduction 688, it is not until Introductions 9, 10 and 11 that Steiner makes further major statements about his epistemological position and, therefore, about the perception of

archetypes. In Introduction 9, as an entry into Goethe’s theory of knowledge, Steiner claims there has been a certain confusion … that has unfortunately persisted since Kant.89 The confusion is said to lie in the questions Kant sets himself in the Introduction to the First Critique as to the possibility of particular forms of knowledge.90 Steiner does not cite Kant, but summarises the critical project in the following way:91

89 NOS, p. 91.

90 CPR, B19-B23, pp 55-57: How are a priori synthetic judgments possible? How is pure mathematics possible? How is pure science of nature possible? How is metaphysics, as natural disposition, possible? How is metaphysics, as science, possible?

91 NOS, p. 91.

92CPR, A19, B33, p. 65: In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to its

Page 25 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed.

93NOS, pp 91-92: We cannot, however, determine the possibility of knowing before we have found out what knowing is. Thus the question, What is knowing? becomes the primary concern for any theory of knowledge.

94 NOS, p. 92: True knowing must acknowledge that the immediate form of the given sense-perceptible world is not yet in its essential form, which reveals itself to us only in the process of knowing. Knowing must provide us with what sense experience withholds, but which is nevertheless real.

Kant believed that philosophy before him had strayed by seeking to know the essential nature of things without first asking how such knowledge is possible in the first place. He saw the fundamental malady of all philosophizing that preceded him in the fact that thinkers thought about the nature of an object before examining our human cognitive capacities. He therefore proceeded to examine this fundamental philosophical problem, thereby inaugurating a new trend in thought. ... As a result, however, epistemology – which has become the central scientific question of the day – is assumed to be no more than a comprehensive answer to the question, How is knowledge possible?

Steiner is mistaken to think that Kant is enquiring into the possibility of all forms of knowledge. As is evident from the opening words of the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant assumes some knowledge is possible, and is enquiring into how we can arrive at judgments which are not determined by sense perceptions.92 The point Steiner wants to make is nevertheless an important one, and it is that any enquiry into the possibility of knowledge should be predicated upon an enquiry into the act of knowing.93 Steiner argues that knowledge is not of an object by a subject: it requires elements of both and arises as a product of the act of knowing.94 There is a more intimate relationship between the knower and the

known than is allowed for in the categories of reason of the First Critique, and one instance of that relationship occurs in the perception of archetypes.

In order to arrive at an epistemology which allows for the perception of archetypes Steiner believes he must show that our knowledge of the given world consists of more than representations [Vorstellungen] of it. Steiner therefore rejects the Kantian95 concept of the representation or mental picture as the content of our knowledge. Steiner’s rejection of the Kantian analysis appears, however, to arise from a misreading of the description of sense impressions as mental pictures. Steiner takes Kant to be assuming that sense impressions are nothing more than a multiplicity of mental pictures of various kinds, because our immediate experience of our sense impressions is constituted as mental images. What Kant says is actually quite different. In the opening, definitional section of the Transcendental Aesthetic Kant does not define representations, but describes them in relation to sensibility and sensation, and says of them:96

95 NOS, p93: Steiner cites the neo-Kantian, Johannes Volkelt, rather than Kant.

Page 26 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

96 CPR, A19, B33-34, p. 65.

97 CPR, A320, B376, p. 314: There is no lack of terms suitable for each kind of representation, that we should thus needlessly encroach upon the province of any one of them. Their serial arrangement is as follows. The genus is representation in general (repraesentatio). Subordinate to it stands representation with consciousness (perceptio). A perception which relates solely to the subject as the modification of its state is sensation (sensatio), an objective perception is knowledge (cognitio).

The capacity (receptivity) for receiving representations through the mode in which we are affected by objects, is entitled sensibility.

The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far as we are affected by it, is sensation.

That is, we receive representations as the effects of objects and we can identify our sensations with those effects. Later, in the introduction to the Transcendental Dialectic, Kant makes it clear that representation’ is a generic term for all forms of apperception.97 He does not

make the claim that we have access to nothing other than mental images, and were he to do so Steiner would be warranted to ask:98

98 NOS, p. 94.

99 NOS, p. 96: Thinking should therefore not be conceived of as adding something to the essence of reality. It is no more and no less an organ of perception than the eye or ear. Just as the eye perceives colours and the ear hears sounds, thus thinking perceives ideas. Idealism is therefore perfectly compatible with the principle of empirical research. Ideas are not the contents of subjective thinking but the results of research.

100 NOS, pp. 94-97: The three angles a, b and c maintain a constant relationship; together they make a straight angle or two right angles (180o). This is a mathematical statement. What is perceived is the angles a, b and c.

The above judgment is reached on the basis of thoughtful consideration. This judgment establishes a relationship between three perceptual images. There is no question of reflecting about any object behind the mental picture of the triangle.

101 NOS, p. 97; Kant makes a similar point in the A version of the Transcendental Deduction,: CPR A105 p135: Thus we think a triangle as an object, in that we are conscious of the combination of three straight lines according to a rule by which such an intuition can always be represented. This unity of rule determines all the manifold, and limits it to conditions which make unity of apperception possible. The concept of this unity is the representation of the object = x, which I think through the predicates, above mentioned, of a triangle.

Page 27 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt

If our perceptions are mental images, then all our knowledge is of mental images and the question arises: How is it possible for a mental image to coincide with the object it is supposed to represent?

Steiner’s rejection of mental images as the content of knowledge leads him to argue for the removal of mental images entirely from the phenomenology of cognition. He is in any case committed to the Goethean notion that the ideal is within the real, so that thinking might be understood as an organ for the perception of ideas rather than as the creator or receiver of mental images.99 Steiner now argues that mental images are nothing beyond concepts or what he describes as percepts’, the objects of perception. He criticises the neo-Kantian claim that for every individual percept there is a specific, irreducible idea and gives as an example the idea of the triangle.100 He contrasts Volkelt’s view with his position and says:

We now ask, Do the consequences of this widely held view correspond with the facts? Not at all. My single concept of the triangle encompasses all individual, perceived triangles; no matter how often I bring it to consciousness, it always remains the same. My various mental pictures of the triangle are all identical. I have only one concept of the triangle.101

Steiner is equating concepts with mental pictures, and appears to be missing the point that we may well have only one concept of a triangle, but have different mental pictures of the varieties of triangles. Indeed, referring now to what he calls percepts, Steiner himself makes a similar point:

The question now arises, What is the actual source of the identity of the concept? It certainly cannot be its manifestation as mental picture, for Berkeley was completely justified in maintaining that my present mental picture of a tree has nothing whatsoever to do with the mental picture I will have of it a minute later if I close my eyes in the meantime …102

102 Loc. cit.

103 It will be remembered that Kant accords mental pictures (representations) a central role as the genus of ideas. CPR, A320 B376, p. 314.

104 NOS, p. 97.

105 Ibid, pp 98.

106 Ibid, pp 98-99.

In arguing as he does Steiner has demonstrated that the notion of the mental picture may be used both as the equivalent of a concept and a percept, but he has not succeeded in showing that there is no place for mental pictures in a critique of cognition.103

Having rejected mental images Steiner is left with what appears to be an unsatisfactory

Page 28 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt account of the relationship between percept and concept. He begins by returning to the … fundamental insight that places the percept, in its particularity, over and against the concept in its universality.104 Because he characterises the relationship between percept and concept in this way and has rejected any role for mental images, Steiner know(s) of no intermediary between percept and concept105 and is led to conclude that (w)hat constitutes the particularity of an object cannot be grasped conceptually, but only perceived.106 As Steiner is also seeking the archetype within the phenomenon he then dissolves the percept into the concept, and says:

What actually distinguishes the percept from the concept is essentially just this element that cannot be conceptualized but must simply be experienced. Thus concept and percept stand juxtaposed as two different aspects of the world that are nevertheless identical in their essential nature. And because, as we have shown, the percept calls for the concept, it

follows that its essence lies not in its particularity, but in its conceptual universality. With regard to its appearance, however, this universality must first be found in the subject; for while it cannot be derived from the object, it can indeed be found by the subject as the latter investigates the object.107

107 Ibid, p. 99, writer’s emphasis

108 Loc. cit, this writer’s emphasis; our own spontaneous spiritual activity is an approximate translation of the original im Geiste durch dessen eigenes spontanes Verhalten, which does not introduce the notion of spiritual activity, but refers to the spontaneous acts of our mind: GNS, p.155.

109 Ibid, p. 94: There is no question of reflecting about any object behind the mental picture of the triangle.

Steiner does not explain what he means by the essential nature of the concept and the percept, except that it includes universality. His claim that this universality must first be found in the subject is his argument both for locating the archetype within the phenomenon and for establishing that the subject must be possessed of an organ for perceiving the archetype. Steiner has, in effect, divided mental images [Vorstellungen] into an intellectual part [concept] and a sensual part [percept], and is now required to reconsider other elements in the act of knowing.

One element to be reconsidered is perception. In a continuation of his critique of concept and percept Steiner reduces perception to a passive form of thinking and imbues concepts with the variety and complexity of the given world, for he says:

The concept is just as individual as the percept, its content just as rich. The only difference is that, to grasp the essence of the percept, nothing is required but the open senses, a purely passive relationship to the external world, whereas the ideal significance of the world must arise through our own spontaneous spiritual activity if it is to appear at all.108

This appears to fly in the face of his view that every variety of a triangle is sufficiently described by the one concept triangle.109 It is also contrary to our common experience that

Page 29 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt there is a certain amount of ordering, in even the simplest act of perception, and a great deal of ordering when we move, for example, from seeing to observing or hearing to listening. It is doubtful that sentient beings can ever be said to have a purely passive relationship to the

external world, or that there is such a thing as what Steiner terms pure sense perception.110 It seems Steiner is denying the inherent intermingling of perception and consciousness, so that he can distinguish percept and concept clearly, point to their complementarity, and then demonstrate their essential unity. An effect of his argument, however, is that perception seems to lose its identity as a cognitive function distinguishable from thinking, and perceiving archetypes comes to be identifiable with thinking about archetypes. Steiner’s way of expressing the relationship between thinking and perception also suggests that he is really talking about mental images:

110 Ibid, p. 102.

111 Loc. cit.

112 Steiner’s description appears to correspond with the empirical concept of Kant’s categorization of representations [Vorstellungen]; CPR, A320, B377, p. 314.

113 NOS, p. 120.

To explore a thing’s essential nature means to proceed from the centre of our thought- world and to work our way outward until there arises before our soul a thought- configuration that appears to be identical with our outer experience.111

A thought-configuration that appears to be identical with our outer experience would seem to be a fairly concise description of at least one form of mental image.112

4.3 Introduction 10

Introduction 10 is the longest of the Introductions and contains sections on methodology and epistemology. In the third section, The System of Science, Steiner returns to his consideration of Goethe and introduces Goethe’s distinction between three methods of scientific research – common empiricism, rationalism and rational empiricism.113 Common empiricism is the mere taking of an empirical inventory. Rationalism looks for the causes behind the phenomena, but is said to be in danger of establishing connections where none exist. For Goethe, rational empiricism is the highest scientific method, and Steiner claims

it … deals with pure phenomena that are identical with objective, natural laws.114 That is, like Steiner’s idealism that is at the same time realism,115 Goethe’s rational empiricism is a synthesis of the subjective and the objective, which is achieved by objectifying the subjective. Just as Steiner claims that ideas and the activity of thinking form part of the given, objectively identifiable phenomena, so Goethe’s rational empiricism has it that the connecting power of the spirit unites with natural objects. That is, there is a symbiosis between the observed phenomena, including archetype and typus, and the organ which is to perceive them:

Page 30 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt 114 Ibid, p. 121.

115 Ibid, p. 116.

116 Loc. cit.

117 Ibid, p. 124.

Because natural objects manifest as separate, we need the synthesizing power of the spirit to show us their inner unity. And because the unity of reason is itself empty, it needs natural objects to fill it. Thus, in the third stage [rational empiricism], phenomena and spiritual capacities meet and become one. Only now is the spirit fully satisfied.116

The impression Steiner gives of the cognitive process is that thinking, as an organ of perception, is in need of objectified ideas (archetypes) for it to perceive.

Having provided an outline of methodology Steiner revisits the Kantian concept of limits to knowledge. In a section entitled On the Limits of Knowledge and the Formation of Hypotheses Steiner puts an argument against there being any limits to knowledge and says:

If we consider the fact that the object to be explained is a given, it should become clear that the given itself cannot limit us in any way. Before it can demand explanation or understanding, it must present itself to us within the world of given reality. Whatever remains outside the realm of the given does not need explaining. Any limit would arise only when, confronted by a given reality, we lacked the means to examine it.117

Steiner takes it to be a part of the given that there is complementary relationship between sense-perceptible phenomena and the concepts and ideas, which arise within us. This, Steiner claims, is because the very act of thinking in the process of cognition is what divides reality into the objective given and the subjective concept of it. If this is so, he is claiming, then it must be possible to know any given, and the very notion of a limiting boundary to knowledge is therefore inconceivable. Steiner expresses the relationship between object and cognising subject in terms of explanation, and says:

Our need to explain arises precisely because the way we wish to define the given – the explanation we wish to give to it – appears on the horizon of what our thinking presents to us. It is not that the explanation – the essence of the thing to be explained – is unknown to us; far from it – it is its emergence in our mind that requires the explanation. The thing that demands the explanation and our means to explain it are both available to us. We only need to establish the connection between the two. The explanation is not a quest for an unknown but a clarification of the interrelationship between two knowns. It should never occur to us to explain a given in terms of something that we do not already know. In principle, this means that there can be no limits to explanation.118

118Loc. cit.

Page 31 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt 119Loc. cit: It may happen that we have an inkling that some external reality exists, but that it is removed from our field of perception. We perceive its traces, its effects, and we presume that it exists.

120 Ibid, p.125: Hypotheses about central scientific principles have no value. When a thing cannot be explained through a known, concrete principle, it is not explicable, not does it call for an explanation.

If there are no limits to explanation, as Steiner claims, there will be no limits to knowledge. The only limit to knowledge Steiner will allow occurs when we are prevented from perceiving something, which we know’ must exist.119 When this occurs, however, we are able to construct a hypothesis to accord with what we cannot yet perceive. This, according to Steiner, is the proper function of hypotheses, which should not be seen as a substitute for scientific principles.120

4.4 Introduction 11

Introduction 11 contains a comparison of Goethe’s way of thinking with Kant’s and that of prominent post-Kantians. In the course of summarising the critical project Steiner identifies two presuppositions of Kant’s, which determine how the project is undertaken and why it is that there is no place in it for the perception of archetypes. Steiner’s claim is this:121

121 Ibid, p. 141.

122 CPR, A19, B33, p. 65: In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed. But intuition takes place only in so far as the object is given to us: writer’s emphasis.

123Loc. cit: Objects are given to us by means of sensibility, and it alone yields us intuitions; they are thought through the understanding, and from understanding arise concepts. But all thought must, directly or indirectly, by way of certain characters, relate ultimately to intuitions, and therefore, with us, to sensibility, because in no other way can an object be given to us.

124 NOS, p. 141.

According to Kant, we determine given reality; it is the way it is because we conceive it that way. Kant actually skips over the real epistemological question. At the beginning of his Critique of Pure Reason, he takes two steps that he doesn’t justify, and his whole philosophical edifice suffers as a result. He simply distinguishes between subject and object without investigating the significance of the fact that our intellect makes such a distinction between two forms of reality – in this case, the knowing subject and the object to be known. He then attempts to formulate conceptually the mutual relationship between these two domains, again without inquiring into the meaning of such a formulation.

Page 32 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt The two presuppositions are the division between subject and object and the subsequent conceptual formulation of the relationship between them. It is true that Kant appears to assume the distinction between object and cognising subject from the outset in the First Critique.122 He does not enquire into the origin of that division. It is also apparent that Kant’s assumptions about the process of cognition do imply that there can be no immediate relationship between subject and object.123 The conclusion Steiner draws from this is that there remains an underlying unity between all the elements of cognition:124

If Kant hadn’t viewed this central epistemological question from a skewed perspective, he would have noticed that the distinction between subject and object is only an intermediate step in the process of cognition, that underlying them both is a

unity perceptible by reason, and that the qualities we ascribe to a thing are not merely subjective. A thing is a unity constituted by reason, and it is the intellect that distinguishes between the thing in itself and the thing according to us. It is simply inadmissible to say that what we attribute to the thing in one case can be denied it in another. Whether I see the same thing from one point of view or from another, it nevertheless remains a unified whole.

Steiner appears to be assuming that there is a unity perceptible by reason. For Steiner this unity extends to include the existence of archetypes as perceptible objects and thinking as the organ for their perception. The very point of the critical project, as Kant explains in the Preface to the Second Edition of the First Critique, is to put aside any presuppositions and to enquire into the possibilities of knowledge without assumptions about the capacities of reason.125 Steiner is well aware of this. It may be, therefore, that his unity perceptible by reason is a derivation from Kant’s transcendental unity of apperception,126 though the implications of it are very different.127

125 CPR, B xvi, p. 22: Hitherto it has been assumed that all our knowledge must conform to objects. But all attempts to extend our knowledge of objects by establishing something in regard to them a priori, by means of concepts, have, on this assumption, ended in failure. We must therefore make trial whether we may not have more success in the tasks of metaphysics, if we suppose that objects must conform to our knowledge.

126 CPR, A 108, p. 136.

127 Loc. cit; Kant is referring to the mind’s capacity to integrate discrete sense perceptions from the manifold of experience into one body: This transcendental unity of apperception forms out of all possible appearances, which can stand alongside one another in one experience, a connection of all these representations according to laws.

4.5 Introduction 16

Introductions 15 and 16 were published in 1890, at around the time Steiner was working on his doctoral thesis, Truth and Knowledge. Introduction 16, Goethe as Thinker and Researcher, is an account of Goethe’s approach to natural science as an alternative to Newtonian physics and mechanics. It contains some of Steiner’s arguments for the

Page 33 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt perception of archetypes. In the second section Steiner turns to the archetypal phenomenon. He begins by investigating the connection between the experience of a sensation – he uses the

example of seeing the colour red – and the cause of that sensation.128 Steiner’s argument is that, viewed phenomenologically, it is the sensation, which is the cause, in that the sensation of seeing red passes through the vibratory medium of the air to effect the perception of an object:

128 NOS, pp 171; in choosing perception of red Steiner may be referring to Kant’s warning at the conclusion of his categoristion of representations: CPR A320, B377, p. 314: Anyone who has familiarised himself with these distinctions must find it intolerable to hear the representation of the colour, red, called an idea. It ought not even be called a concept of understanding, a notion.

129 Ibid, p. 172.

130 Ibid, p. 173.

This reveals a truth well suited to illuminate the whole theoretical foundation of physics and physiology. What do I learn by investigating something involved in a process that enters my consciousness as a sensation? All I really learn is how that particular thing responds to the action that proceeds from the sensation. In other words, the way a sensation expresses itself in a particular object of the world of space and time. Far from being the cause that initiates the sensation within me, the spatial- temporal process is the effect of the sensation in a thing that exists in space and time. I could include any number of things along the path from the stimulus to the organ of perception; each will respond in a way that is both determined and limited by its own nature. It is thus the sensation itself that expresses itself in each of the processes.129

Whatever is transmitted in the path from the stimulus to the sense organ will be experienced as further perceived sensations. Steiner concludes that (t)he perceived world is nothing other than an aggregate of metamorphosed perceptions.130 Archetypes and archetypal phenomena, then, are also nothing other than metamorphosed perceptions. If this is so, however, it is difficult to see that there is any distinction between the perception of archetypes and the perception of any other phenomena, or why there is a need to argue for thinking as an organ of perception.

In the third section of Introduction 16, The System of Natural Science, Steiner sets out to present what he calls the inner architecture of Goethe’s way of thinking. At the core of this inner architecture is the interaction between sensory perception and concepts through the mediation of thinking. Steiner’s introduction to the section indicates that he has not yet

separated thinking from concepts and ideas, as he does in his later epistemological work, and nor has he yet identified the intuitive nature of thinking.131 Steiner describes the goal of thinking as the relating of concepts to percepts and of percepts to each other. He establishes the non-conceptual nature of perception by pointing out, that … there is no way for me to communicate the colour red to a colour-blind person, no matter how I describe it

Page 34 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt conceptually132 and concludes that:

131Ibid, p. 179: It might seem as though, by limiting the task of thinking to the ordering of perceptions, our investigations are now calling into question the very autonomy of concepts and ideas which we advocated so strongly to begin with. Further reflection will show that this is not the case; after all, what is the goal of thinking when it establishes connections between perceptions?

132 Loc. cit.

133 Loc. cit.

134 Ibid, p. 180.

135 Ibid, p. 181.

There is an aspect of the sensory perception that never enters into the concept – something that must be experienced before it can become an object of cognition at all.133

Steiner explains that what can never enter the concept is how something appears, for concepts are limited to what something is. That what will differ according to whether we are investigating inorganic or organic nature. The observation of inorganic nature, as he argued in The Science of Knowing, leads to the uncovering of laws of nature, and these are laws which arise from perception of the archetypal phenomenon and … lie outside the perceived multiplicity.134 The type (typus), which is the conceptual part of organic nature, … appears as a principle within the sensory multiplicity instead of existing outside of it as a law.135

At this point in the development of his epistemology Steiner is not yet clear about the way he wishes to see the relationship between different manifestations of what he calls the idea, nor how he is to characterise the relationship between percept, concept and thinking. He

identifies natural law, type and concept all with the idea136 and reiterates, but without arguing for it, the notion that concepts and ideas are objects of perception.137 In the concluding section of Introduction 16, Goethe, Newton and the Physicists, Steiner returns to Goethe’s discovery of the Urpflanze, and to the generalisation from that observation to the notion that there are perceptible archetypes of all natural phenomena. Steiner characterises Goethe’s way of seeing as empirical idealism138, which he describes in the following way:

136 Loc. cit: Natural law, type and concept are the three forms of the idea.

137 Loc. cit: The concept is present in a form that can be perceived. In human consciousness, the concept itself is perceptible. Observation and idea coincide; we actually perceive the idea.

138 Ibid, p. 188.

139 Loc. cit.

… when observing the multiplicity of things that arise for the senses, to the extent that

Page 35 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt those things are similar, we can find a spiritual unity [geistige Einheit] at their foundation, which is the source of all their similarities.139

The spiritual unity is, presumably, another way of referring to the idea or the archetype. The implication of it, however, is that there will be an inherent unity between the perceptible archetype itself and an organ, which is designed to perceive it.

5. Thinking as an organ of perception

Steiner’s characterisation of archetypes as perceptible phenomena leads him to argue that there must be an organ with which to perceive them. In The Science of Knowing and the first batch of Introductions Steiner equates archetypes of inorganic nature with laws of nature, which are conceived of as ideas outside of the phenomena, and which therefore require nothing other than the exercise of pure reason. With organic nature, however, Steiner claims that the typus is to be found within the phenomenon, but has not yet established how these archetypes are to be perceived. In a section of The Science of Knowing concerning Thinking

and Perception Steiner hints at thinking as an organ of perception, though at the same time he regards thinking as the non-sensory half of cognition and experience:140

140 SK, pp 53-54.

141NOS, p. 105.

We would have to renounce our thinking entirely if we wanted to keep to pure experience. One disparages thinking if one takes away from it the possibility of perceiving in itself entities inaccessible to the senses. In addition to sense qualities there must be yet another factor within reality that is grasped by thinking. Thinking is an organ of the human being that is called upon to observe something higher than what the senses offer. The side of reality accessible to thinking is one about which a mere sense being would never experience anything. Thinking is not there to rehash the sense-perceptible but rather to penetrate what is hidden to the senses. Sense perception provides only one side of reality. The other side is a thinking apprehension of the world.

By the time of the second batch of Introductions to Nature’s Open Secret Steiner argues that thinking must be the organ for perceiving archetypes. Steiner introduces the notion of thinking as a sense organ in Introduction 9. In the course of a discussion about the nature of ideas (archetypes) Steiner claims that the nature of thinking is not to create ideas but to perceive them, and says:

The idea-content of the world is based on its own foundations, it is complete and perfect within itself. We do not create it; we only seek to comprehend it. Our thinking does not create it; it perceives it. Thinking is not a producer but an organ of apprehension.141

Thinking, therefore, gives us entry into the world of ideas. Steiner takes a literal view of the

Page 36 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt notion of a world of ideas and depicts the relationship between thinking and ideas as indivisible in space and time:

My consciousness that I am standing inside a thing is only the result of its objective nature, of the fact that it contains its own principle. By taking possession of the idea, we gain entry into the centre of the world. What we grasp here is the source from

which everything springs. We become one with this principle; therefore the idea – what is most objective – appears to us, at the same time, as most subjective.142

142 Loc. cit.

143 Goethe. J. Propitious Encounter cited in GOS, p. 96: I gave a spirited explanation of my theory of the metamorphosis of plants with graphic pen sketches of a symbolic plant. He listened and looked with great interest, with unerring comprehension, but when I had ended, he shook his head, saying: That is not an empiric experience, it is an idea.’ I was taken aback and somewhat irritated … Controlling myself, I replied, how splendid that I have ideas without knowing it, and can see them before my very eyes.’

144 NOS, p. 96: Thinking should therefore not be conceived of as adding something to the essence of reality. It is no more and no less an organ of perception than the eye or ear. Just as the eye perceives colours and the ear hears sounds, thus thinking perceives ideas.

145Loc. cit: Sense-perceptible reality is, in fact, such a riddle to us for the very reason that we do not find its centre within it. It ceases to be so enigmatic when we realize that it has the same centre as the thought-world, which comes to manifestation within us.

146 The Science of Knowing contains a large section on thinking and thought, in which Steiner objectifies thought and emphasizes the interconnecting activity of thinking: SK, pp 43-44: With regard to objectivity, the work of the thinker can very well be compared with that of the mechanic. Just as the mechanic brings the forces of nature into mutual interplay and thereby effects a purposeful activity and release of power, so the thinker lets the thought-masses enter into lively interaction, and they develop into the thought-systems that comprise our sciences.

147 NOS, p. 78: Whoever attributes to thinking a perceptive capacity that goes beyond that of the senses, must also acknowledge that this capacity directs itself toward objects that lie beyond sense-perceptible reality. The objects of thinking, however, are ideas. When our thinking comprehends an idea, it unites with the foundations of universal existence.

Steiner also appears to have taken a literal view of Goethe’s riposte to Schiller that he could see his ideas.143 For Steiner thinking is to ideas exactly as the eye is to the visual world and as the ear is to sound.144 Indeed, in Nature’s Open Secret Steiner regards the relationship between the idea (archetype) as percept and thinking as the organ of perception as more immediate than that between sense-perceptible phenomena and other organs of

Page 37 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt perception.145

Steiner’s characterisation of thinking as a sense organ creates some difficulties for him, and raises questions about how the other functions of thinking are now to be regarded. Thinking is generally related to concepts rather than to percepts, and the primary function of thinking is usually understood to be the organising activity of relating concepts to sense perceptions or to each other. Steiner himself expresses views about thinking to this effect in The Science of Knowing146 and Nature’s Open Secret.147 When Steiner speaks of thinking as an organ of perception he does not say whether he means by this that thinking retains its organising,

correlating and other functions, or whether he is putting forward a conception of thinking as nothing other than an organ of perception. It is no doubt for good reason that Kant’s discussion of thinking in the First Critique is undertaken in the form of I think’, which Kant identifies as the vehicle of all concepts.148 Because Kant recognises the centrality of I think’ in every judgment149 it may be that the relationship between thinking and concepts might be seen as analogous to the relationship between sense organs and percepts, but not that thinking is itself an organ of perception.

148 Kant addresses thinking in the Paralogisms of Pure Reason, pp 327-383: CPR, A341, B399 p. 329: We now come to a concept which was not included in the general list of transcendental concepts but which must yet be counted as belonging to that list, without, however, in the least altering it or declaring it defective. This is the concept or, if the term be preferred, the judgment, I think’. As is easily seen, this is the vehicle of all concepts…

149 CPR, B406, p. 368: Since the proposition I think’ (taken problematically) contains the form of each and every judgment of understanding and accompanies all categories as their vehicle …

Even the notion that the relationship between thinking and concepts might be analogous to the relationship between seeing and objects, or between hearing and sounds, creates difficulties for Steiner. Consider the difference between active and passive engagements of these sense organs. We can draw a distinction between using the organ of sight simply to see something, and the active, conscious mode of observing it. Similarly we can distinguish between hearing a sound and actively listening to a piece of music. The difference is that observing and listening are forms of perceiving which already contain an element of thinking within them. How, then, would it operate with ideas as the sense perceptible objects of thinking? Thinking about an idea will always involve an element of thinking. It does not make sense to speak of a passive form of perceiving with thinking as the sense organ, because thinking of itself is the very activity. Thinking, then, is not analogous to seeing and hearing and it is not a sense organ.

Steiner will need to seek out another approach to the apperception of archetypes. One other approach would be not to regard archetypes as sense perceptible phenomena, but as

phenomena which are accessible to thinking by some other means. Thinking would then also no longer be regarded as an organ of perception. If archetypes are not sense perceptible then they might be seen as ideas, which are not perceived by thinking, but are accessible to

Page 38 15 Part 2 Chapter 5 PERCEIVING THE ARCHETYPE.txt a mode of thinking operating differently from the discursive thinking of pure reason. There is an opening to this suggestion in the non-discursive mode of thinking outlined by Kant in the Third Critique, the thinking of the intellectus archetypus. Steiner takes up this opening, and in Truth and Knowledge and Philosophy of Freedom adopts Fichte’s notion of intellectual intuition and develops it into intuitive thinking.

Page 39 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt PART 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION

The third and fourth disjunctions between Steiner’s early work and Kantian epistemology have to do with the role of intuition in cognition. In Part 1 Chapter 1 an account was given of the concept of intuition in philosophical discourse and of Kant’s rather idiosyncratic use of the term. It will be remembered that, early in the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant determines that the only intuitions are the sensory intuitions of space and time.1 Kant specifically excludes intellectual intuition as a faculty of human cognition, though – as with the intellectus archetypus – he allows that there may be such a thing as a divine intellectual intuition.2 Kant’s rejection of intellectual intuition as a faculty of human cognition was immediately challenged by the post-Kantians. Schelling saw intellectual intuition as the faculty through which the human ego identifies itself with the world of nature.3 For Fichte the process of coming to consciousness, which for him precedes knowledge of any particular things, commences with a spontaneous intellectual intuition.4 Steiner also argues for the actuality of intellectual intuition. For Steiner intellectual intuition is a means by which he seeks to extend possible knowledge beyond the limits imposed by Kant and, as became clear at the end of the previous chapter, Steiner remains in need of some means to characterize the apperception of archetypes. The means he ultimately chooses is the intuitive thinking outlined at the end of Part 2 Chapter 7. To arrive at intuitive thinking Steiner proceeds by way of two steps. The first is to demonstrate the actuality of intellectual intuition, and the second is to argue from intellectual intuition to intuitive thinking. In Truth and Knowledge

1 CPR, A19, B33, p. 65: Objects are given to us by means of sensibility and it alone yields us intuitions ...

2 CPR, B72, p, 90: … intellectual intuition seems to belong solely to the primordial being, and can never be ascribed to a dependent being …

3 Schelling, F. (1989) The Philosophy of Art, op cit, translator’s introduction at xxxiii: The whole of philosophy starts, and must start, from a principle which, as the absolute principle, is also at the same time the absolutely identical. An absolutely simple and identical cannot be grasped or communicated through description, nor through concepts at all. It can only be intuited. Such an intuition is the organ of all philosophy. – But this intuition, which is an intellectual rather than a sensory one …

4 IWL, p. 46: Intellectual intuition is the name I give to the act required of the philosopher: an act of intuiting himself while simultaneously performing the act by means of which the I originates for him.

Steiner restates and adopts Fichte’s arguments for the availability of intellectual intuition in human cognition, and in Philosophy of Freedom he attempts to develop intellectual intuition into intuitive thinking. This chapter addresses Steiner’s adaptation of Fichte’s concept of intellectual intuition and the following chapter deals with Steiner’s arguments for intuitive thinking.

The argument of this chapter is divided into five sections. The first section explains what

Page 1 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt Kant means by intellectual intuition in the First Critique and sets out the reasons for his rejection of intellectual intuition as a faculty of human cognition. In asserting the actuality of intellectual intuition Steiner is relying heavily upon the arguments developed by Fichte. The second section outlines Fichte’s arguments for intellectual intuition in the several versions of the Wissenschaftslehre. Fichte’s argument is complex and the structure of it has been examined closely by Dieter Henrich in an article on Fichte’s Original Insight. Because Steiner’s concept of intuitive thinking is so dependent upon the viability of Fichte’s argument for intellectual intuition the third section of this chapter is given over to an examination of Henrich’s discussion of Fichte’s original insight. The fourth section presents Steiner’s derivation of intellectual intuition in Truth and Knowledge. The final section of this chapter sets out the steps Steiner takes in Truth and Knowledge towards a derivation of intuitive thinking from intellectual intuition.

1. Kant’s rejection of intellectual intuition

Kant makes occasional reference to intellectual intuition in the First Critique, and explains at several points in the Transcendental Dialectic why it is that intellectual intuition must be discounted as a faculty of human cognition. Intellectual intuition is introduced in a footnote

to the Preface to the second edition of the First Critique, in which Kant describes intellectual intuition and our relationship to it as follows:5

5CPR, B xl, fn. p35.

If, with the intellectual consciousness of my existence, in the representation I am, which accompanies all my judgments and acts of understanding, I could at the same time connect a determination of my existence through intellectual intuition, the consciousness of a relation to something outside me would not be required. But though that intellectual consciousness does indeed come first, the inner intuition, in which my existence can alone be determined, is sensible and is bound up with the condition of time.

Kant does not define what he means by intellectual intuition, intellectual consciousness and inner intuition either here or elsewhere, except as they relate to each other. Here Kant appears to be saying that intellectual consciousness is a way of describing consciousness of the self in the process of cognition devoid of any positive judgments about one’s existence, and that this is to be distinguished from inner intuition, which is the consequence of observing the self as an object and then forming a judgment about the actuality of one’s own existence from within the manifold of sensible intuitions. The distinction Kant is drawing between consciousness of self and observation of self demonstrates that, for him, cognition must be passive and objective. It follows that, as we cannot establish the actuality of our existence except as an object of the manifold of sensible intuitions, we cannot speak of ourselves as being capable of intellectual intuition.

Kant’s subsequent discussions of intellectual intuition in the Transcendental Aesthetic of the First Critique, like this first one, tend to build up a fairly comprehensive account of what intellectual intuition is not, and why it is not available to human consciousness as a mode of

Page 2 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt cognition. Indeed, he argues, it must be unavailable to human cognition, because it must lie outside of the determinations of space and time (or else it would merely constitute a form of sensible intuition), and as only God is not constrained within the pure intuition of time, only a

divine or primordial being can have access to intellectual intuition.6 In his study of the First Critique Heinrich Cassirer explains that a primary reason for Kant’s rejection of intellectual intuition is that Kant sees cognition as essentially passive, while intellectual intuition would of necessity be active.7 Thus, were we to have access to intellectual intuition as a faculty of cognition:

6 CPR, B72, p. 90: … such intellectual intuition seems to belong solely to the primordial being, and can never be ascribed to a dependent being, dependent in its existence as well as in its intuition, and which through that intuition determines its existence solely in relation to given objects.

7 Cassirer, H. (1954) Kant’s First Critique, George Allen and Unwin: London pp 12-13: (Kant) holds it to be characteristic of all human knowledge, inasmuch as it is direct or immediate, that it is essentially passive; and he holds likewise that there is something profoundly significant about the fact that the factor in knowledge which he calls intuition should be found to exhibit the property of sheer passivity. In this way he is led to make a distinction between what he terms sensible intuition, on the one hand, and on the other, intellectual operations which he considers never to be wholly passive. Moreover, he contrasts the type of intuition with which we are familiar with a faculty of intuition which would involve an element of activity, and which would by itself give rise to knowledge. To indicate its nature, he speaks of intellectual intuition’ or intuitive understanding’, while emphasizing at the same time that he does not mean to assert the actual existence or even the possibility of such a form of knowledge which could be met with only in a consciousness wholly different from ours.

8 Ibid, p. 46.

9 Loc. cit.

10Ibid, p. 47: What is to be signified by things-in-themselves’ are realities such as would concern only a mind fundamentally different from our own, that is to say, one which was endowed with a faculty of intellectual intuition.

(1) Whenever the idea of an object was entertained, this alone would be sufficient to guarantee its reality; and (2) The mere conceiving of an object by the mind would be enough to provide knowledge of that object.8

These two elements, according to Cassirer, are inseparably linked, for it is because the entertaining of the idea of an object would suffice to assure the mind of its reality, that the

Page 3 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt object would at once become known in the very act of being conceived of.9 And, in addition, a quality of such a mind is that it would be capable of knowing the things-in- themselves. Indeed, Cassirer concludes, the very nature of a thing-in-itself would be that it is that part of the object of cognition which is accessible to intellectual intuition.10

In the ensuing Transcendental Analytic of the First Critique Kant sets out how he understands the relationships to be between the intuitions [Anschauungen] he has identified in

the Transcendental Aesthetic, the representations or mental images [Vorstellungen], which comprise our perception of phenomena and the process of thinking [Das ich denke]. To establish these relationships Kant also introduces the concepts of self-consciousness [Selbstbewusstsein] and apperception [Apperzeption]. Kant’s description of these elements of the process of cognition commences with the actuality of mental images and concludes with the claim that he has established the original synthetic unity of apperception.11 Although there is reference to intuitions there is no specific reference to intellectual intuition. It will be noticed that the overlap between Anschauung as sense-perceptible observation and Anschauung as intellectual intuition allows Kant to claim that the limits of perception are contained within the mental images of appearances, and do not extend to the things-in- themselves. As for thinking, Kant’s approach is to place it in the nominative form of I think (das: Ich denke) as a construct of self-consciousness, rather than to examine the act of thinking itself. As a consequence, Kant does not undertake an analysis of the process of thinking, the activity of pure reason, either here or elsewhere in the First Critique. As with

11 CPR, B132, p. 153: It must be possible for the I think’ to accompany all my representations; for otherwise something would be represented in me which could not be thought at all, and that is equivalent to saying that the representation would be impossible, or at least would be nothing to me. That representation which can be given prior to all thought is entitled intuition. All the manifold of intuition has, therefore, a necessary relation to the I think in the same subject in which this manifold is found. But this representation is an act of spontaneity, that is, ii cannot be regarded as belonging to sensibility. I call it pure apperception, to distinguish it from empirical apperception, or, again, original apperception, because it is that self-consciousness which, while generating the representation I think’ (a representation which must be capable of accompanying all other representations, and which in all consciousnesses is one and the same), cannot itself be accompanied by any further representation. The unity of this apperception I likewise entitle the transcendental unity of self- consciousness, in order to indicate the possibility of a priori knowledge arising from it. Here is seems necessary to cite the original, because of the denseness of Kant’s arguments:

KRV, p. 136: Das: Ich denke, muß alle meine Vorstellungen begleiten können denn sonst würde etwas in mir vorgestellt werden, was gar nicht gedacht werden könnte, welches eben so viel heißt, als die Vorstellung würde entweder unmöglich, oder wenigstens für mich nichts sein. Diejenige Vorstellung, die vor allem Denken gegeben sein kann, heißt Anschauung. Also hat alles Mannigfaltige der Anschauung eine notwendige Beziehung auf das: Ich denke, in demselben Subjekt, darin dieses Mannigfaltige angetroffen wird. Diese Vorstellung aber ist ein Actus der Spontaneität, d. i. sie kann nicht als zur Sinnlichkeit gehörig angesehen werden. Ich nenne sie die reine Apperzeption, um sie von der empirischen zu unterscheiden, oder auch die

Page 4 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt ursprüngliche Apperzeption, weil sie dasjenige Selbstbewußtsein ist, was, indem es die Vorstellung Ich denke hervorbringt, die all andere muß begleiten können, und in allem Bewußtsein ein und dasselbe ist, von keiner weiter begleitet werden kann. Ich nenne auch die Einheit derselben die transzendentale Einheit des Selbstbewußtseins, um die Möglichkeit der Erkenntnis a priori aus ihr zu bezeichnen.

intuition Kant portrays thinking as receptive and content-less: these are the limiting constructs of the mind.

As he does with the intellectus archetypus Kant establishes the possibility of intellectual intuition only to claim that there can be no such actual source of knowledge for human consciousness. Some Kant scholars have nevertheless attempted to flesh out what Kant’s apparent acknowledgement of the possibility of intellectual, or spontaneous, intuition might imply. Paton, for example, reminds us that Kant’s characterization of intellectual intuition is intertwined with a distinction Kant wants to sustain between the mind of man and the mind of God. In Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience Paton explains:

Kant’s arguments apply only to human experience, and he regards as conceivable a knowledge which depends, not on sensuous, but on intellectual, intuition.

Intellectual intuition would not, like sensuous intuition, depend on objects given to it from without: its objects would be given, or produced, by the very act of intuition itself. Of such an intellectual intuition space and time would not be forms. They are forms of sensuous intuition alone. Hence if we conceive the divine mind as possessing intellectual intuition, the divine experience, if it can be called experience, would not be spatial or temporal.12

12 Paton, H.(1970) Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience, George Allen and Unwin Ltd: London , p. 178.

What Paton’s observation reminds us is that Kant’s rejection of intellectual intuition as a human capacity arises from the unspoken metaphysics lurking in the background of the critical philosophy. Kant has to allow for differences of kind between the mind of man and the mind of God, and one difference will be that the divine mind is productive of the objects of its consciousness while the human mind is not. Kant does not, however, demonstrate that the human mind is incapable of producing any of the objects of its consciousness (as an acceptance of the actuality of intellectual intuition would require), and nor does he explain how the human mind arrives at thoughts, ideas and concepts if it does not itself produce them.

Kant returns to a discussion of intellectual intuition, it will be remembered, in s.76 of the Third Critique, when he is dealing with our understanding of organic nature. Here he also appears to associate intellectual intuition, or intuitive understanding, with the intellectus archetypus in s77 of the Third Critique. Kant argues that our reliance upon concepts to cognize sensory phenomena means that any intuitive capacity we have must be of a receptive, rather than a spontaneous, nature. What Kant now refers to as a power of complete spontaneity of intuition or an intuitive understanding, like the intellectual intuition he alludes to in the First Critique, is a notional possibility, but is again not available to human cognition. Kant draws on the characteristics of both intellectual intuition and the intellectus archetypus when he says:

Page 5 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

Now [all] cognition requires [not only understanding] but also intuition; and a power of complete spontaneity [as opposed to receptivity] of intuition would be a cognitive power different from, and wholly independent of, sensibility: thus a power of complete spontaneity of intuition would be an understanding in the most general sense of the term. Hence we can conceive of an intuitive understanding as well (negatively, merely one that is not discursive), which, [unlike ours,] does not (by means of concepts) proceed from the universal to the particular and thus to the individual. For such understanding there would not be that contingency in the way nature’s products harmonize with the understanding in terms of particular laws. It is this contingency that makes it so difficult for our understanding to unify the manifold in nature so as to [give rise to] cognition. This task, which an intuitive understanding does not need to perform, can be accomplished by our understanding only through a harmony between natural characteristics and our power of concepts; and this harmony is very contingent. 13

13 CJ, pp 290-291.

From the Preface to the First Critique to the second part of the Third Critique Kant retains his position that the only possible intuition is sensory intuition and that what he describes variously as intellectual intuition, intuitive understanding and the intellectus archetypus can never be anything more than a notional possibility. For Fichte, in contrast, intellectual intuition is the starting point of all philosophy.

2. Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre

Fichte’s derivation of intellectual intuition is a central plank of his epistemology and his whole philosophical system, which, despite the possible ambiguities, is probably best described simply as the Wissenschaftslehre [theory of knowledge]14. Steiner’s philosophical work owes a considerable indebtedness to Fichte, which rivals his indebtedness to Goethe. That indebtedness is most evident in Steiner’s dissertation, Truth and Knowledge, in which Steiner argues that Fichte was on the right track, but stopped short of arriving at the logical conclusion of his own investigations, namely that thinking is the activity at the core of intellectual intuition. In the conclusion to the Preliminary Remarks of Truth and Knowledge Steiner demonstrates his indebtedness to Fichte by saying of his doctoral project:15

14 IWL, Editor’s Introduction, ix: Over the course of his career Fichte produced no fewer than sixteen different expositions of the first principles of his system, many of which differ utterly in format, structure and vocabulary from all of those that preceded and followed. One must therefore exercise caution when referring to Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre. For the term Wissenschaftslehre does not refer to any particular stage or presentation of Fichte’s philosophy, and still less to any particular book; it refers instead to Fichte’s overall system, to the general orientation of his thinking in the broadest and most encompassing sense.

15 TK, pp 28-29; Wissenschaft would be better translated here as knowledge.

16 RP, pp 122-131and The Spirit of Fichte Present in our Midst, lecture, Berlin, 16 December 1915 contain

Page 6 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt extended discussions of Fichte’s role in post-Kantian thinking.

17CML, pp 40-41: I had reached a point in my study of Kant where I could formulate an idea (though immature) of how Fichte wanted to take a step beyond Kant. But that was not the main reason for my interest in Fichte. It was most important that I find ways to express, in clearly defined thoughts, the living activity of the human soul. My efforts concerning natural scientific concepts had finally brought me to see that the activity of the human I is the only possible starting point for true knowledge. I told myself that something spiritual is immediately present in one’s consciousness when the I actively observes this activity itself. I felt it was necessary to express such observations as clear, surveyable concepts. To this end, I stuck to Fichte’s Science of Knowledge. But I also had my own ideas. Page by page, I rewrote the Science of Knowledge. The

The discussion which follows aims so to formulate the problem of cognition that in this very formulation it will do full justice to the essential feature of epistemology, namely, the fact that it is a science which must contain no presuppositions. A further aim is to use this philosophical basis for science [Wissenschaft] to throw light on Jacob Gottlieb Fichte’s philosophy of science [Wissenschaftslehre].

Steiner often refers to Fichte in his later works,16 and in his autobiographic Course of my Life he gives an amusing account of his youthful efforts to improve upon the argument of the Wissenschaftslehre.17 The most comprehensive attempt to date to offer a critique of

result was a long manuscript. Previously, I had agonized over finding concepts that apply to natural phenomena, from which one could then derive a concept of the I. Now my goal was just the opposite; beginning with I-being, I wanted to penetrate the creative processes in nature. Spirit and nature manifested before my soul in full contrast.

18 Veiga Greuel, M. (1990) Wirklichkeit und Freiheit, Gideon Spicker Verlag: Dornach

19 IWL, p. 7: I still owe the reader the following remarks: I have always said, and here I repeat, that my system is none other than the Kantian system. i.e., it contains the same view of the subject, though it proceeds in a manner that is entirely of Kant’s presentation.

20 Ibid, p. 52: … the author of the Wissenschaftslehre has prefaced his presentation with the claim that this philosophy is in complete accord with Kant’s and is nothing other than the Kantian philosophy properly understood.

21 CPR, B1, p. 41: There can be no doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience. Kant does not mean to imply that the only source of knowledge is sense experience, for he adds: But though all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all arises out of experience. For it may well be that even our empirical knowledge is made up of what we receive through impressions and of what our own faculty of knowledge (sensible impressions serving merely as the occasion) supplies from itself.

Steiner’s early work from within the academy happens to be a comparison between the use of certain central epistemological concepts by Fichte and by Steiner.18 The argument of Fichte’s Wisssenschaftslehre will therefore be an essential element to be considered in any critical examination of Steiner’s epistemology.

Page 7 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

Fichte presented the Wissenschaftslehre in several forms, including the serialised First and Second Introductions of 1797/1798 to the Public Announcement of a New Presentation of 1800. In the Preface to the First Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre Fichte claims that he will be doing nothing more than making Kant intelligible and responding to misunderstandings, which had developed around the critical philosophy.19 He repeats this claim somewhat further into his argument in the Second Introduction.20 It is very apparent, however, that Fichte’s whole orientation is entirely different from the position adopted by Kant in the First Critique. If the starting point of epistemology for Kant is that knowledge commences ineluctably from experience,21 Fichte has it that all knowledge arises from an originating activity, namely the positing activity of the self-conscious I or ego. The ego (consciousness) becomes aware of itself (I) as distinct from what lies outside of itself (not-

I), which the ego posits, therefore, as the non-positing non-ego of the given world.22 It is then not much further into the Wissenschaftslehre before Fichte reveals that his desire is to accomplish a complete revolution in the way we think, and that he is operating well outside of the Kantian position.23

22 IWL, p. 42: Let us begin by looking at the I that is being observed. What is this self-reverting act of the I? Among which class of modifications of consciousness should it be posited? It is not an act of comprehending anything by means of concepts. It first becomes an act of comprehension only when it is opposed to a Not-I and only insofar as the I itself is determined within this opposition.

23Ibid, pp4-5: My writings are not meant to explain Kant’s, nor are they intended to be explained by his writings. They must stand on their own without any reference whatsoever to Kant. To state my own position as plainly as possible: I am not concerned to rectify nor to bring to completion any set of philosophical concepts that may already be in circulation – be they anti-Kantian or Kantian.

24 Ibid, p. 46: Intellectual intuition is the name I give to the act required of the philosopher: an act of intuiting himself while simultaneously performing the act by means of which the I originates for him. Intellectual intuition is the immediate consciousness that I act and of what I do when I act.

25 Ibid, p. 186.

26 Ibid, p. 189.

A central feature of this independence from Kant is Fichte’s reinstatement of intellectual intuition as an element in cognition. Fichte’s presentation of intellectual intuition commences with a definition of it in the Second Introduction as a moment in cognition.24 By the time of the Public Announcement of a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre it has broadened into the methodology of … a thoroughly new discovery, the very idea of which did not exist previously and can be obtained only from the Wissenschaftslehre itself.25 Fichte expresses his new discovery in the following way:

Right up to the time of Kant, philosophy has been considered to be a form of rational cognition based on concepts, and for this reason it is contrasted with mathematics, which is considered to be a form of rational cognition based on intuitions. …

Page 8 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

Such a view of the nature of philosophy fails to take into account several things. First of all, since there is certainly supposed to be a kind of rational cognition based on intuitions (for this is what one claims mathematics is), then – so long as all cognizing and thinking is not supposed to come to an end with this sort of cognition, and indeed, so long as it is supposed to be possible for us even to assert that there is such cognition – there must, in addition, be some cognition of this cognition. And since an intuition, as such, can only be intuited, this latter sort of cognition must itself be based on intuition.26

The consequence of this new discovery, Fichte asserts, is that any critique of reason must ultimately be based upon a ground of unmediated intuition. Fichte then expresses this seemingly paradoxical deduction as follows:

A critique of reason involves a cognition of reason, which is here the object of cognition; and thus reason has been assigned the task, prior to anything else, of cognizing itself. Only after it has done this can it then go on to examine how it may be able to cognize anything beyond itself. Consequently, from the moment that a critique of reason became a topic of discussion, it should have been obvious that reason does not grasp itself and cannot apprehend itself by means of anything (such as a concept) that has to be derived from something else and that does not possess its foundation or ground within itself; instead, reason can grasp and apprehend itself only immediately – and there is nothing immediate but intuition. Hence, if philosophy is from now on to be synonymous with reason’s own self-produced cognition of itself, then philosophy can by no means be considered to be cognition based upon concepts, but must instead be cognition based upon intuition.27

27 Ibid, p. 191.

28 Ibid, p. 20.

29 ibid, both in the sense of being contradictory, and in the sense of denying the self: e.g. p.18: The dogmatist’s principle is belief in things for the sake of himself. Thus he possesses only an indirect or mediated belief in his own dispersed self, which is conveyed to him only by objects.

Fichte’s various presentations of the Wisssenschaftslehre vary in their emphases and in their detail but, for the sake of brevity, it might be said that the central argument is essentially along the following lines:

1. Only two kinds of epistemological (and philosophical) positions are possible – those which take their starting point from the observed things of the world, and those which start from the observer. These positions might be described as dogmatism and idealism. Although Fichte said famously: The kind of philosophy one chooses … depends upon the kind of person one is28, it is not a case of one choice being of no greater value than the other: dogmatism, Fichte claims, is self-negating29, and it is

Page 9 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt only idealism, which warrants any further consideration.

2. There are also two forms of idealism. One form might be called transcendental, or critical, idealism, and this is what other interpreters have made of Kant’s critical philosophy. The problem with transcendental idealism is that it assumes there is a discontinuity between the observer and the observed – hence the need for transcendence - and it thereby generates the unknowable things-in-themselves. The other kind of idealism is what the Wissenschaftslehre seeks to demonstrate as the true and only foundation of knowledge – an idealism, which takes as its starting point not merely the observer, but the activity of consciousness turned upon itself: the observer self-observing. This, says Fichte, is also the correct understanding of the critical philosophy, though the world and Kant himself might disagree.30 Fichte does not give a name to this form of idealism, and sometimes also refers to it as transcendental idealism’: to distinguish it for its emphasis upon activity and immediacy we might call it immanent idealism. 3. The fundamental issue for epistemology is not Kant’s question How are synthetic truths a priori possible? which arises from, and assumes the existence of, separate categories of knowledge, and separated forms of experience. Epistemological enquiry should, instead, commence by taking account of the varieties of mental images (representations) we have before us, when we turn our consciousness upon ourselves. We find there are mental images, which arise from our own thoughts,

30 Ibid, pp 52-53: ... the author of the Wissenschaftslehre has prefaced his presentation with the claim that this philosophy is in complete accord with Kant’s and is nothing other than this philosophy properly understood. ...

Yet all of the recognized experts on Kant’s philosophy who have expressed an opinion on this topic – be they friends or foes of the Wissenschaftslehre – have unanimously affirmed just the opposite; and, at their suggestion, this has even been asserted by Kant himself, who must surely understand his own philosophy better than anyone else. The author of the Wissenschaftslehre would be happy to share this opinion – if only he could. Kant made his views very clear in his Open letter on Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre of August 7, 1799: … I hereby declare that I regard Fichte’s Theory of Science [Wissenschaftslehre] as a totally indefensible system. … I am so opposed to metaphysics, as defined according to Fichtean principles, that I have advised him, in a letter, to turn his fine literary gifts to the problem of applying the Critique of Pure Reason rather than squander them in cultivating fruitless sophistries. See Zweig, A. (ed) (1955) Kant: Philosophical Correspondence 1759-99, pp 253-254.

desires and imaginations. There are also mental images, which are not created by us, but appear before us as our representations of, and experiences of, the given world. The question, therefore, should rather be formulated as: What is the origin of the system of representations accompanied by a feeling of necessity?31 4. In endeavouring to answer this question we begin by recognizing that our consciousness operates out of two series of mental activities. One series is generated by our consciousness of selfhood – of I. On this level we act spontaneously in the world. The other series is generated by speculation upon life –

Page 10 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt this is the standpoint of the philosopher. The method of the Wissenschaftslehre will consist in observing the interplay of these two series of activities.32 5. Because it is activity we are observing, we realize there is no need – and no place - for us to assume the being of any object, including consciousness. The standpoint of the I is spontaneous activity, and the standpoint of the philosopher is the observation of the conscious subject. From this standpoint the philosopher discovers that the ground of all being is the act of the I turning back upon itself.33 6. The I the philosopher observes in the act of turning back upon itself is, of course, the philosopher’s own I. In becoming aware of this, the philosopher realizes that the ground of all being is, in fact, a free act, and an intuition. This is not an intuition of the sensory world: it is what Fichte describes as an intellectual intuition.

31 Ibid, p. 39.

32 Ibid, p. 38 fn: The philosopher occupies the standpoint of pure speculation, whereas the I itself occupies the standpoint of life and science … The standpoint of life is comprehensible only from the standpoint of speculation. … The standpoint of speculation exists only to make the standpoint of life and science comprehensible.

33 Ibid, p. 40: The sole thing to which the person who undertakes this act of abstraction continues to cling and proposes to employ as the basis for explaining everything that has to be explained is the conscious subject. Consequently, he must grasp this subject entirely apart from any representation of being, for only in this way will he then be able to show that this subject contains within itself the ground of all being being for this subject, as goes without saying. But if we abstract from all being of and for this conscious subject, then nothing pertains to it but acting. More specifically, in relation to being, the subject in question is the acting subject. The philosopher therefore has to apprehend this subject while it is engaged in acting. This is the point at which the previously mentioned double series first arises.

By the time Fichte has developed his argument to this point the distance from the position adopted by Kant could not be greater. While Kant clams that intellectual intuition lies outside of the range of human cognition, for Fichte intellectual intuition is at the very core of all cognitive activity.

2.1 Fichte’s concept of intellectual intuition

Fichte’s new discovery that intuition is at the core of all cognition leads him on to elaborate a critique of intellectual intuition. Intellectual intuition emerges gradually in the course of Fichte’s various restatements of the Wissenschaftslehre. It does not appear in the Grundlage, but by the time of the Second Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre it is identified by Fichte as the generative source of all cognition. In the Second Introduction Fichte defines what he means by intellectual intuition as follows:

Intellectual intuition is the name I give to the act required of the philosopher: an act of intuiting himself while simultaneously performing the act by means of which the I originates for him. Intellectual intuition is the immediate consciousness that I act and

Page 11 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt of what I do when I act. It is because of this that it is possible for me to know something because I do it. That we possess such a power of intellectual intuition is not something that can be demonstrated by means of concepts, nor can an understanding of what intellectual intuition is be produced from concepts. …

To be sure, anyone can be shown, within his own acknowledged experience, that this intellectual intuition is present in every moment of his consciousness. I cannot take a single step, I cannot move my hand or foot, without the intellectual intuition of my self-consciousness in these actions. It is only through such an intuition that I know that I do this. Only in this way am I able to distinguish my own acting (and, within this acting, my own self) from the encountered object of this acting. Every person who ascribes an activity to himself appeals to this intuition. It contains within itself the source of life, and apart from it there is nothing but death.34

34 Ibid, pp 46-47.

In the first paragraph of the definition intellectual intuition is identified as, and is recognizable as, a self-conscious action. In the second paragraph, however, Fichte appears to be moving to a description of what others, including Kant before him and Steiner after

him, identify as the unconscious action of the will. It will be necessary, therefore, to examine both how Fichte elaborates his concept of intellectual intuition, and whether, in the end, what he is describing is the form of intellectual intuition Kant asserts is unavailable to human cognition, or whether Fichte is describing some other function of the mind.

Fichte compares intellectual intuition with sensory intuition. According to Fichte both must be grasped conceptually, and intellectual intuition is always conjoined with sensory intuition.35 Like sensory intuition, intellectual intuition leads to the construction of a mental image36, though it is an image of a series of actions, rather than of a thing.37 From these comparisons Fichte argues that there is a reciprocal dependency between intellectual intuition and sensory intuition, as both of them arise from self-consciousness.38 Intellectual intuition, then, is as intrinsic to the structure of consciousness and the operation of reason as is sensory intuition. This, as Fichte acknowledges, is in direct conflict with Kant’s assertion that intellectual intuition is outside the range of human capacities.39 Fichte nevertheless remains committed to the view that he is the true interpreter of Kant, and that the Wissenschaftslehre is nothing other than the First Critique from another perspective. He must, therefore, find some way of distinguishing what Kant has to say about intellectual intuition from the central role he wishes to ascribe to it. Fichte does this by proposing that he and Kant are actually using the same words to express two very different concepts:

35 Ibid, p. 47: I cannot discover myself to be acting without also discovering some object upon with I act; and I discover this object by means of sensory intuition, which I grasp by means of a concept.

36 Loc. cit: Vorstellung, translated by Breazeale, in this instance, as an image or a picture rather than as representation.

37 Loc. cit: How could I possibly know (what it is I want to produce) unless I had immediately observed myself

Page 12 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt engaged in the act of constructing a concept of a goal, that is, in a type of acting?

38 Loc. cit: … for sensory intuition is possible only in conjunction with intellectual intuition, since everything that is supposed to be my representation must be referred to me; but consciousness of the I comes only from intellectual intuition

39 Ibid, p. 55: … there is nothing against which Kant has declared himself more decisively and, one might say, disparagingly than against the claim that we possess a power of intellectual intuition.

In Kant’s terminology every intuition is directed at some being (a posited being, something fixed and enduring). Accordingly, intellectual intuition would, in this case, have to be a consciousness of a non-sensible being, an immediate consciousness of the thing in itself, and indeed, a consciousness made possible by thought alone; i.e. it would amount to a creation of the thing in itself simply from the concept of the same … The intellectual intuition of which the Wissenschaftslehre speaks is not directed toward any sort of being whatsoever; instead, it is directed at an acting – and this is something that Kant does not even mention (except, perhaps, under the name pure apperception).40

40 Ibid, pp 55-56.

41 Ibid, pp 73-74: … the object, considered as something given, is also something merely thought of; and therefore the passage plucked from the Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason [the object is given to us, Critique of Pure Reason, A19, B33] merely characterizes the system of necessary thinking in terms borrowed from the empirical viewpoint, a viewpoint that can be explained and derived only by means of the Critique that follows.

… All of our cognition does indeed begin with an affection, but not with an affection by an object. This is Kant’s view of the matter, and it is also the position of the Wissenschaftslehre.

The difference might be expressed as a difference of emphasis. Kant is speaking of an intellectual intuition (as opposed to a sensory intuition), while what Fichte has in mind is the activity of intellectual intuition.

Fichte is, nevertheless, not consistent either in developing or even in maintaining this distinction. Not very much further into the Second Introduction, Fichte argues that for Kant, as much as for Fichte himself, the non-sensible being and the thing in itself are not objects. They are not any kinds of things, and do not, therefore, have to be characterised with the quality of being. They are, rather, nothing other than affections brought about by the activity of thinking.41 Kant’s intellectual intuition, therefore, is not directed toward any sort of being any more so than is Fichte’s activity of intellectual intuition. There are two points to be made about Fichte’s apparent inability to follow through with the distinction he draws between his and Kant’s conceptions of intellectual intuition. One is that his argument for abandoning the distinction between intellectual intuition and intellectual intuition depends upon an idiosyncratic interpretation of Kant’s use of the expression object of sense

Page 13 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt experience in the First Critique42 The other is that it is something of a lost opportunity for, as Förster shows, there is some merit in maintaining the distinction between intellectual intuition and intellectual intuition, as both of the senses in which Fichte uses the term are in any case to be found in the differing ways in which Kant expresses himself in the First and Third Critiques.43

42 CPR, B1, p. 41: There can be no doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience. For how should our faculty of knowledge be awakened into action did not objects affecting our senses partly of themselves produce representations, partly arouse the activity of our understanding to compare these representations, and, by combining or separating them, work up the raw material of the sensible impressions into that knowledge of objects which is entitled experience? [writer’s emphasis]

43 Förster, (2009) Part 1, p. 8: However, the intellectual intuition that is brought into play here [in s77 of the Third Critique] is not identical to the productive intuition referred to in the deduction, so that we have to distinguish more precisely between two meanings of the concept of intellectual intuition – one, immediate and direct because it is a productive intuition, and the other, immediate and direct because it is a non-sensible intuition.

44 IWL, p. 48.

45 Loc. Cit.

Fichte describes intellectual intuition as something which is directed at an acting. Intellectual intuition is known to us, Fichte tells us, as an inference from the obvious facts of consciousness44. He explains these obvious facts in the following manner:

First I resolve to think of some determinate thing, and then the desired thought ensues; I resolve to do some determinate thing, and the representation of its occurrence then ensues. This is a fact of consciousness.45

If this fact is accounted for purely in terms of sensory intuition, however, I can do no more than observe that the thought follows in time from the resolution to think; the representation follows in time from the resolution to act: I cannot, from the considerations available to sensory intuition, conclude that the one is the cause of the other. I must assume, therefore, that my activity, my resolution is the source of the thoughts and the representations. Fichte describes intellectual intuition in the following fashion:

Why do I make this assumption? No basis for it can be found among the sensory ingredients we examined above. Accordingly, it must have its basis in a special type of consciousness, indeed, in an immediate consciousness, and hence, in an intuition.

The intuition in question certainly cannot be a sensory intuition directed at some materially subsisting thing; instead, it must be an intuition of a sheer activity – not an activity that has been brought to a halt, but one that continues; not a being, but something living.46

Page 14 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

46 Loc. Cit.

47Ibid, p. 50: Intellectual intuition provides the only firm standpoint for any philosophy. Everything that occurs within consciousness can be explained upon the basis of intellectual intuition – and only upon this basis. Without self-consciousness there is no consciousness whatsoever, but self-consciousness is possible only in the way we have indicated: I am only active. I cannot be driven from this position. This is the point where my philosophy becomes entirely independent of all arbitrary choice and becomes a product of iron necessity …

48 Ibid, p. 49: Fichte, like Kant, nevertheless identifies freedom and compliance with the moral law. He, too, therefore emphasizes the claims of duty: p. 50: With this, transcendental idealism simultaneously reveals itself to be the only type of philosophical thinking that accords with duty. It is the mode of thinking in which speculation and the ethical law are most intimately united.

49 Loc. Cit; TK, p. 77, Steiner citing Harms (1876) Die Philosophie seit Kant : His [Fichte’s] world-view is predominantly and exclusively ethical, and his theory of knowledge has no other feature.

This intuition, for Fichte, forms the ground for all philosophy.47

Fichte also argues that the actuality of intellectual intuition is most evident in the practical sphere of the ethical law within us. The ethical law for Fichte appears to be nothing other than the Kantian categorical imperative48, and this, as for Kant, is also the domain of human freedom. Fichte links consciousness and freedom in this way:

Our intuition of self-activity and freedom has its foundation in our consciousness of this law, which is unquestionably not a type of consciousness derived from anything else, but is instead an immediate consciousness. Here I am given to myself, by myself, as something that is obliged to be active in a certain way. … It is only through the medium of the ethical law that I catch a glimpse of myself; and insofar as a I view myself through this medium, I necessarily view myself as self-active. In this way an entirely alien ingredient, viz., my consciousness of my own real efficacy, arises for me within a consciousness that otherwise would be nothing but a consciousness of a particular sequence of my representations.49

Fichte differs from Kant, however, in having the one activity – intellectual intuition – as the ground for what Kant describes separately, and distinctly, as pure and as practical reason. This both simplifies, and complicates, Fichte’s position. George Seidel, in his critique of the ways in which the concepts of activity and ground are developed by the post- Kantians, explains that it leads Fichte to a grounding of all reason upon intellectual intuition:

Fichte’s philosophical position is complicated by the fact that he insists upon joining the theoretical self of Kant’s first critique with the practical self of the Critique of Practical Reason, in order to explain both the activity which is knowing and the ethical action which requires knowledge. On the score of the activity which is knowing, he says that the act of self-positing self-consciousness is the concept of the self; and the concept of the self is the concept of this act: It is thus because I make it

Page 15 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt thus. Thus, the intellectual intuition becomes the underpinning for the concept. He speaks of the intellectual intuition as a fact (Thatsache) of consciousness for the philosopher, but a Thathandlung [act] for the original self. The intellectual intuition is, then, the one and only firm standpoint for all philosophy. It couples two worlds, the world of theoretical knowledge and the world of moral action, in a single glance. It is, says Fichte, through the medium of the moral law that I behold myself. Fichte departs from Kant at this point, insisting, as he does, that since it is the self which performs the ethical act, the self must be able to be aware that it is the self that performs it. There must be speculative knowledge of the practical act such that it may be recognized as the self’s own. As he says, intellectual intuition is the immediate intuition of the self’s own activity. This activity, which is identified with freedom, is the bridge between the sensible and intelligible world.50

50 Seidel, G.(1976) Activity and Ground: Fichte, Schelling and Hegel, Georg Olms Verlag: Hildesheim/New York, p. 75.

51 ISTP, pp. 159-160: Kant says, Duty! You exalted, mighty name, you who contain nothing lovable, nothing ingratiatingly agreeable [was Einschmeichelung bei sich führt] , but who demand submission, (you who) establish a law … before which all inclinations fall dumb, though in secret they might work against it! To this,

It might be said at this point that there are some interesting comparisons and differences between the respective positions adopted by Fichte and by Steiner. Fichte identifies the activity of intellectual intuition as the source of freedom; Steiner ascribes freedom to the activity of thinking: for Fichte intellectual intuition is the bridge between the sensible and intelligible worlds; for Steiner that role is undertaken by a specific form of intellectual intuition, namely what he calls intuitive thinking. Steiner’s work, in this regard, is clearly a development of Fichte’s. The same cannot be said of Fichte’s apparent acceptance of the Kantian moral law within. In contrast, Steiner’s concept of freedom, and what Steiner terms ethical individualism, are very much at odds with the notion of a categorical imperative and the Kantian concept of duty.51

a human being, out of the consciousness of the free spirit, replies: Freedom! You friendly, human name, you who contain everything morally beloved, everything that most dignifies my humanity, and who make me into no one’s servant, you who do not merely establish a law, because it feels unfree in the face of every merely imposed law!

52 Important texts for understanding the development of Fichte’s thought have only become available in the 20th century. There are two manuscripts of the lectures Fichte gave between 1796 and 1799 on the Wissenschaftslehre in the novo methodo, the Hallesche Nachschrift and the Nachschrift Krause. The former was not published until 1937, and the latter was only discovered in 1980. See Zöller, G. (1996) Thinking and Willing in Fichte’s Theory of Subjectivity in D. Breazeale & T. Rockmore (eds) New Perspectives on Fichte, Humanities Press: New Jersey p. 14fn.

Page 16 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

53 TK, pp 79-83: Let us now survey Fichte’s line of thought once more. On close inspection one sees that there is a break in its sequence: a break, indeed, of a kind that casts doubt upon the correctness of his view of the original deed of the I. ... Had Fichte attempted to discover how the I determines its own activity, he should have arrived at the concept of knowledge which is to be produced by the I.

3. Fichte’s original insight

Fichte’s derivation of intellectual intuition as the starting point of consciousness arises from his analysis of the process of self-consciousness. That analysis moves through various modifications from the earlier versions of the Wissenschaftslehre to the later, as Fichte seeks to overcome the objections he envisages to his formulations. The motivating factor in these modifications is Fichte’s awareness that there are inherent defects in the reflection theory of self-consciousness, the notion that self-consciousness merely consists in treating the conscious subject as an object. Fichte recognises that there is something more to the activity involved in self-consciousness than the mere fact of reflection. The consequence is that he develops an increasingly sophisticated construction of how it is that that activity operates.52 A comprehensive examination of the phases in Fichte’s conception of self-consciousness is to be found in Dieter Henrich’s essay Fichte’s Original Insight. Henrich sets out the contradictions in the reflection theory and Fichte’s three successive formulations for self- consciousness. In Truth and Knowledge Steiner relies upon Fichte’s arguments for intellectual intuition, but then claims that Fichte falls short in his failure to identify the activity of the I within cognition.53 In Philosophy of Freedom Steiner argues that it is the

activity of thinking, through which self-consciousness is related to cognition.54 The following presentation of Henrich’s critique of Fichte’s formulation of self-consciousness has been undertaken to better evaluate Steiner’s epistemological claims, namely that there is a lacuna in Fichte’s line of thought, and that Fichte’s critique of self-consciousness would otherwise have lead to the identification of intuitive thinking as the source of knowledge of essences.

54 ISTP, p. 33: This is the characteristic of thinking. The thinker forgets thinking while doing it. What concerns the thinker is not thinking, but the observed object of thinking.

55 FOI, p. 19: Self-consciousness is unique inasmuch as there is no distinction, here, between the one who thinks and the object of his thought, between the one who possesses something and what he possesses. Where the Self is, both the subject and this subject as its own object, are present. Also, we can never grasp the Self as subject in isolation in the way we can any other thing, whatever it might be. When we are thinking of it we have already presupposed the consciousness of it in our own thought and thus have turned the subject-self of which we are thinking into an object. Thus we only revolve around it in a perpetual circle. This means that self-consciousness, considered on its own, does not amplify or extend our knowledge of reality. The knower already contains what he grasps when he turns back into himself.

56 Loc. cit.

Page 17 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt Henrich gives an historical overview of the theory of self-consciousness. Although self- consciousness has been a feature of epistemology from Plato, and a basic principle of philosophy from Descartes onwards, philosophers, up to and including Kant, considered self- consciousness as a consequential element of other elements of their theories of knowledge. They did not examine the concept of self-consciousness itself, because self-consciousness does not appear to provide us with any knowledge of the world. It appears, rather, to be merely reflective, and consideration of it seems to lead to circularity.55 Fichte’s original insight was to find a way of avoiding this apparent circularity by distinguishing between consciousness of the self and the positing of self-consciousness. Henrich expresses this distinction by claiming it is not the Self but the theory of the Self as reflection that continually turns in a circle.56 According to Henrich the contradictions within the reflection

theory of self-consciousness can be demonstrated by posing a set of simple questions, the first of which was one raised by Fichte. Henrich expresses the first question as follows:

The theory that the Self is reflection talks about a Subject-Self that knows itself by entering into relation to itself, that is, by turning back into itself. How can this subject be conceived? If we assume that it is really the Self when it functions as the subject, then it is obvious that we are turning in a circle and are presupposing what we want to explain. For we can only speak of an I where a subject has apprehended itself, where an ego says I to itself. Self-consciousness is distinguished from all other forms of knowledge precisely by the fact that one and the same item presents itself in self-consciousness in a double guise. Whatever act might bring this consciousness about, only the total result, in which the I gains possession and knowledge of itself, can be called I. However, this act can by no means be described as reflection. For reflection can only mean that an item of knowledge which is already at hand is properly apprehended and thereby made explicit!57

57 Ibid, p. 20.

58 Loc. cit.

That is, the reflection theory must be circular, because anyone who sets reflection into motion must himself already be both the knower and the known.58 If this circularity is to be avoided then self-consciousness must take place immediately and spontaneously. In other words, the very act of positing self-consciousness demonstrates features which, according to Kant, are unavailable to human cognition and which are characteristic of, and demonstrative of, intellectual intuition.

Henrich outlines a second question for self-reflection theory, which follows from the first. Not only must the subject be both the knower and the known, self-reflection theory is in danger of generating a third element of consciousness, which accounts for the capacity of the knower to identify the correct object as the reflection of itself. The only way for self- reflection theory to avoid this complication is for it to acknowledge that the subject has immediate (intuitive) consciousness of the object as itself. Henrich shows that the second

question is also circular and demonstrates that, once again, self-consciousness presupposes intellectual intuition. He sets out the argument as follows:

Page 18 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

Now, if we are to explain consciousness of the identity I=I, it is not enough that any subject whatsoever gain an explicit consciousness of any object whatsoever. This subject must also know that its object is identical with itself. … But how can self- consciousness know that it has grasped itself, if an Object-Self has come about only via the Self’s act of reflection? Obviously it can know this only if it already knew itself before. For only on the basis of previous knowledge is it possible for self- consciousness to say: What I am grasping is I myself. But, if it already knows itself, then it already knows that I=I. And thus the theory of reflection begs the question once again. It presupposes that the problem which it has been faced with has been completely solved at the start.59

59 Ibid, p. 21.

60 Loc. cit.

61 Ibid, p. 24.

62 Loc. cit.

63 TK, p. 79: The I is not postulated by presupposing another I; it presupposes itself. This means: the I simply is, absolutely and unconditionally. The hypothetical form of a judgment, which is the form of all judgments, when an absolute I is not presupposed, here is transformed into a principle of absolute existence: I simply am. Fichte also expresses this as follows: The I originally and absolutely postulates its own being. This whole

Fichte, according to Henrich, was the first philosopher to recognize this circle and to draw consequences from it.60 Recognizing the circularity was Fichte’s original insight; the consequence for Fichte was that he then found himself engaged in repeated attempts to describe unambiguously the process of self-consciousness.

Henrich’s presentation of Fichte’s first two formulations of the dynamic of self- consciousness affords us a further opportunity for understanding what it is that Steiner will characterise as Fichte’s fundamental mistake. The first formulation, from the Grundlage of 1794, is expressed in these terms: the Self posits itself absolutely and unconditionally.61 It is not difficult, from this formulation, to see why it is that Fichte is often accused of absolute solipsism. Henrich describes the formulation as allowing for extreme expression to the pathos of freedom.62 Steiner appears to be referring to this formulation in Truth and Knowledge when he is reciting Fichte’s ontological deduction.63 The difficulty with this first

deduction of Fichte’s is clearly nothing but a kind of pedagogical discussion, the aim of which is to guide his reader to the point where knowledge of the unconditional activity of the I dawns in him. His aim is to bring the activity of the I emphatically home to the reader, for without this activity there is no I.

64 FOI, pp 29-30: … the Self has no knowledge of itself unless the intuition and the concept of the Self are inextricably bound together with one another. They are equiprimordial

65 CPR, A51, B75, p. 93.

Page 19 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

66 FOI, p. 30. formulation is the lack of any dynamic to lead to self-knowledge. The second formulation, from the 1797 Introductions, acknowledges this deficit, and Fichte reformulates his derivation of self-consciousness to read: The Self posits itself absolutely as positing itself. The beauty of this formulation is that it oversteps the question of whether the Self has intuitive or conceptual knowledge of itself by allowing for it to have both at the same time.64 It is also a further step away from the Kantian picture of consciousness and cognition, and it adds an ironic twist to Kant’s pithy Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind65. The irony is that Kant can only have had sensory intuitions in mind, while Fichte has managed to extend Kant’s dictum to include intellectual intuition.

Fichte’s third formulation of reflective self-consciousness is significantly different from the other two. It arises from a recognition that the second formulation also depends upon a hidden assumption, namely that the active Self, in positing itself as positing, depends upon a pre-existing active ground, in which there is balance and unity between intuition and concept. Fichte overcomes this difficulty now by describing self-consciousness as an activity in which an eye is inserted [eine Taetigkeit, der eine Auge eingesetzt ist].66 Henrich explains how Fichte arrives at this image:

It is only by thinking of the activity of the eye in this way that we can acquire an idea of the Self and its being for itself. It then becomes clear that the eye which catches sight of the activity must at the same time see itself. For the activity is essentially an activity of the eye; thus, the activity can only be seen at the same time as the eye is seen. … In other words, the relationship the Self has to itself amounts to knowledge existing for itself and manifest to itself; at the same time, however, this knowledge remains a matter of fact which can be used to explain everything else except its own existence ...

Accordingly, the eye inserted in the activity includes intuition and concept at the same time. Only then can it be wholly inward to the act and, at the same time, to its cognitive relation to itself; only then can it be understood as self-consciousness.67

67 Ibid, p. 33.

68 Förster develops this argument in Die 25 Jahre der Philosophie and in his paper Goethe and the Auge des Geistes (2001) Deutsche Vierteljahrschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte, pp 87-101at p. 99: The similarities between Goethe’s approach and that of Fichte are indeed striking. Both proceed from an intuitive whole or ideal unity from which the empirical distinctions evolve.

69 The Preface is dated December 1891. Wahrheit und Wissenschaft was first published by Hermann Weissbach in Weimar in 1892.

Fichte’s adoption of such a decidedly visual formulation to account for the activities of cognition and self-consciousness is of particular interest for two reasons. One is that it is remarkably reminiscent of Goethe’s descriptions of the interactions between subject and

Page 20 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt object in the practice of intuitive judgment [anschauende Urteilskraft], and suggests that there may be a more immediate connection between Fichte’s representation of consciousness and Goethe’s perception of the archetype than is usually assumed.68 The other is that Fichte has shifted in his representation of self-consciousness from a mathematical postulation of the necessity of being to a metaphor derived from the senses and the activity of a sense organ. From this characterisation of intellectual intuition it will not be such a large step for Steiner to take in arguing that cognition is grounded in the activity of thinking.

4. Steiner’s derivation of intellectual intuition in Truth and Knowledge

In 1890 Steiner moved to Weimar. He enrolled in the University of Rostock to undertake his doctoral work, and in 1891 completed his dissertation, which he published in the following year as Wahrheit und Wissenschaft [Truth and Knowledge]69. The subtitle of the original edition, Introduction to Philosophy of Freedom, indicates that Truth and Knowledge prepares the ground for Philosophy of Freedom, and that Steiner already had the argument of Philosophy of Freedom in mind. Truth and Knowledge is clearly grounded very much within the neo-Kantian academic tradition. Steiner indicates that his intention is to overcome the

unhealthy faith in Kant70 of his contemporary neo-Kantians, and that: Unlike Kant ... the purpose here is not to show what our faculty of knowledge cannot do, but rather to show what it is really able to achieve.71 Steiner claims to have outgrown his dependence upon Goethe72, and developed the principal concepts of his own epistemology. He is attempting to demonstrate that his epistemology is a whole that rests upon its own foundation.73

70 TK, p. 9.

71 Ibid, p. 11.

72 Ibid, p. 13: Until now, I have always presented my philosophical views in connection with Goethe’s world- view … In this work, however, I hope to have shown that the edifice of my thought is a whole that rests upon its own foundation, and need not be derived from Goethe’s world-view.

73 Ibid, p. 13.

74 Ibid, p. 10.

75 Ibid, p. 11.

First amongst the pillars of that foundation is Steiner’s idiosyncratic conception of thinking. The thesis of his dissertation is ... to show that everything necessary to explain and account for the world is within the reach of our thinking.74 According to Steiner knowledge is produced through the activity of thinking. That is, knowledge should not be seen as an object to be acquired, but as something which arises in the course of thinking, and:

… truth is not, as is usually assumed, an ideal reflection of something real, but is a product of the human spirit, created by an activity which is free; this product would exist nowhere if we did not create it ourselves. The object of knowledge is not to repeat in conceptual form something which already exists, but rather to create a

Page 21 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt completely new sphere, which when combined with the world given to our senses constitutes complete reality. Thus man’s highest activity, his spiritual creativeness, is an organic part of the universal world-process.75

To arrive at his revitalised understanding of thinking Steiner reworks the concept of intuition. He retraces the steps Fichte has taken away from Kant, and then endeavours to take them further. In his Preliminary Remarks, the first chapter of Truth and Knowledge, Steiner indicates he has two interrelated aims, namely:

… so to formulate the problem of cognition that in this very formulation it will do full justice to the essential feature of epistemology, namely, the fact that it is a science

which must contain no presuppositions. A further aim is to use this philosophical basis for science to throw light on Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s philosophy of science.76

76 Ibid, pp 28-29.

77 KRV, B19-20, pp 58 -59:Die eigentliche Aufgabe der reinen Vernunft ist nun in der Frage enthalten: Wie sind synthetische Urteile a priori möglich?, B73, p. 96:Hier haben wir nun eines von den erforderlichen

To rid epistemology of presuppositions Steiner devotes two chapters to demonstrating the deficits in Kant’s formulation of the problem of knowledge and the methodology of the First Critique. Steiner’s response to Kant is considered in section 4.1 following. In Chapters 4 and 5 of Truth and Knowledge Steiner presents his own formulation of the constituents of knowledge, and it is here that Steiner emphasizes the activity of thinking at the centre of cognition. Steiner’s arguments for intellectual intuition are presented in section 4.2. In Chapter 6 of Truth and Knowledge Steiner turns to Fichte’s claim that it is the activity of the I and consciousness, rather than thinking, that leads to knowledge. The final two chapters of Truth and Knowledge are a short epistemological conclusion and a practical conclusion. It can be seen that, although Steiner is continually attempting to distance himself from Kant and his contemporary neo-Kantians, he is also seeking to respond to the epistemological and practical consequences of the First and Second Critiques. Steiner’s moves away from Fichte and towards his own conception of thinking, as the activity at the heart of intellectual intuition, are discussed in section 5 following.

4.1 Steiner’s response to Kant

Steiner’s response to the critical philosophy, like Fichte’s, begins with the claim that Kant has formulated the problem of knowledge incorrectly, by asking himself the wrong question. It is familiar territory that, in the Introduction at the end of the Transcendental Aesthetic of the First Critique, Kant formulates the problem of knowledge as: How are synthetical judgments a priori possible?77 For Steiner, however, this cannot be the starting point of an

Stücken zur Auflösung der allgemeinen Aufgabe der Transzendentalphilosophie: wie sind synthetische Sätze a priori möglich?

78 TK, p. 33.

Page 22 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

79 CPR, B20, p. 59.

80 TK, p. 34. Steiner is, of course, not alone in pointing to the foundational difficulties in the critical philosophy. See, for example, Williams, R. (1992) Recognition; State University of New York Press: Albany, p. 29: The Kantian transcendental is theoretically problematic in that Kant’s account of the conditions of possibility of knowledge does not reveal how such a transcendental account itself is possible. And, in regard to the antinomies: p. 31: Is not the critique of knowledge itself knowledge? It does not appear to be knowledge in the restricted and qualified sense that it purports to establish. But if critique is not knowledge, how can Kant pretend to adjudicate opposing cognitive and metaphysical claims? epistemology, because it assumes that there can be knowledge that is independent of experience. There may be some such knowledge, Steiner allows, but for him:

A theory of knowledge must leave open, to begin with, the question of whether we can arrive at a judgment solely by means of experience, or by some other means as well. Indeed, to an unprejudiced mind it must seem that for something to be independent of experience in this way is impossible. For whatever object we are concerned to know, we must become aware of it directly and individually, that is, it must become experience. We acquire mathematical judgment too, only through direct experience of particular single examples.78

Kant takes it as given that there will be mathematical and scientific knowledge independent of experience. In the Introduction to the First Critique Kant also asks: How is pure mathematics possible? How is pure natural science possible?79 Steiner’s response to these questions is to point to Kant’s presuppositions, for as Steiner says:

The Critique of Pure Reason does not at all prove that mathematics and pure science are a priori sciences, but only establishes their sphere of validity, pre-supposing that their truths are acquired independently of experience. Kant, in fact, avoids discussing the question of proof of the a priori sciences, in that he simply excludes that section of mathematics … where even in his own opinion the a priori nature is open to doubt; and he limits himself to that section where he believes proof can be inferred from the concepts alone.80

Any knowledge which arises independently of experience, Steiner argues, would have to be unmediated knowledge of one or other of the faculties of our consciousness. Even so, for it to become knowledge, Steiner claims, it would have to form part of our experience.

A second objection Steiner has to Kant’s starting point is the corollary of the first. Not only does Kant assume the existence of knowledge independent of experience, he also suggests that what appears to be arise from experience may not be comprised merely of experience.81 Just as Kant draws our attention to synthetic judgments a priori, Steiner raises the possibility of purely experiential knowledge, and claims:

81 CPR, B1, p. 41: But though all knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all arises out of experience. For it may well be that even our empirical knowledge is made up of what we receive through

Page 23 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt impressions and of what our own faculty of knowledge (sensible impressions serving merely as the occasion) supplies from itself.

82 TK, p. 34.

… at the beginning of a theoretical investigation of knowledge, one ought not to maintain that no valid and absolute knowledge can be obtained by means of experience. For it is quite conceivable that experience itself could contain some characteristic feature which would guarantee the validity of insight gained by means of it.82

It should be mentioned that the kind of experience being referred to by Steiner appears to include both of the forms of experience expressed in the well-known German distinction bewteen Erfahrung and Erlebnis. These are, broadly, inner and outer experiences – what one goes through, and what one lives through. Steiner’s position, in contrast with Kant’s, seems to be that all our knowledge arises out of some form of experience.

A further objection of Steiner’s to Kant is the notion that all empirical knowledge is limited to, and consists only of, representations (Vorstellungen). Steiner observes that, from Kant’s time to his, almost all philosophical views assume this to be so, whether or not their proponents are Kantians. Even Eduard von Hartmann, to whom Steiner has dedicated his thesis, regards this notion as irrefutable:

… in his (Hartmann’s) book, Kritische Grundlegung des transzendentalen Realismus (Critical Basis of Transcendental Realism) he assumes that his readers, by critical reflection, have overcome the na„ve identification of the perceptual picture with the thing-in-itself, that they have convinced themselves of the absolute diversity of the subjective-ideal content of consciousness – given as perceptual object through the act

of representing – and the thing existing by itself, independent both of the act of representing and of the form of consciousness; in other words, readers who have entirely convinced themselves that the totality of what is given us directly consists of our representations.83

83 TK, pp 39-40.

84 Ibid, p. 41; this objection might be extended to the circularity inherent in any critique of reason or thinking, for which see Breazeale, D. Circles and Grounds in the Jena Wissenschaftslehre in Breazeale, D. & Rockmore, T. (eds) (1994) Fichte: Historical Contexts/Contemporary Controversies, Humanities Press: New Jersey, pp 43- 70

85 Ibid, p. 41: citing Part 1 of von Hartmann’s Das Grundproblem der Erkenntinistheorie [The Fundamental Problem of Epistemology].

86 Ibid, pp 42-43.

Steiner makes the same observation about this assumption as Fichte makes about Kant’s

Page 24 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt notion that the starting-point of knowledge is reason:

To say that my knowledge extends to begin with only as far as my representations, is to express a quite definite judgment about cognition. In this sentence I add a predicate to the world given to me, namely, its existence in the form of representation. But how do I know, prior to all knowledge, that the things given to me are representations?84

The limiting of empirical knowledge to representations has, Steiner says, become an intrinsic part of modern scientific consciousness. Steiner cites von Hartmann’s observation85, that there are three separate arguments for this, which nevertheless lead into each other. These arguments are from physical, psycho-physiological and philosophical perspectives. Physical science reduces sense-perceptible phenomena to vibrations and systems of minute particles separated by empty space, so that:

(t)he physicist believes he is justified in assuming that a material body does not affect our senses of touch and warmth by direct contact, because there must be a certain distance, even if very small, between the body and the place where it touches the skin. From this he concludes further that what we sense as the hardness or warmth of a body, for example, is only the reaction of the peripheral nerves of our senses of touch and warmth to the molecular forces of bodies which act upon them across empty space.86

This view of the relationship between phenomena and sense perception is confirmed by the psycho-physicist87, who reports that:

87 Ibid, fn 32, pp 101-102. Steiner is alluding to the work of Johannes Peter Müller, professor of anatomy and physiology at Berlin University in the earlier 19th century. Müller, in his Handbuch der Physiologie des Menschen developed the principle of the law of specific energy of sense substances: The kind of sensation following stimulation of a sensory nerve does not depend on the mode of stimulation, but upon the nature of the sense organ. Thus, light, pressure, or mechanical stimulation acting on the retina and optic nerve invariably produces luminous impressions.

88 Ibid, p. 43.

89 Ibid, p. 44.

90 Ibid, p. 45, citing Hartmann’s Grundproblem, p. 37.

… there is only one kind of phenomenon in the external world, namely motion, and that the many aspects of the world which we perceive derive essentially from the reaction of our senses to this phenomenon.88

As a consequence, there can be no similarity between what first affected the sense organs,

Page 25 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt and the sensations that finally arise in consciousness.89 The philosophical argument for reducing empirical knowledge to representations is derived from the other two. The physical and the psycho-physiological arguments show that there is not even any immediate connection between our receiving a sense impression and becoming conscious of a sensation, much less between our sensations and the phenomena of the given world. The philosopher must therefore conclude that our na„ve consciousness is illusory, and agree with von Hartmann that … all that the subject perceives are modifications of its own soul-condition and nothing else.90

Steiner outlines three arguments to refute scientific reductionism. The first is that the reduction is itself self-cancelling. We are assuming both, in a na„ve realist way, that an external world exists, and at the same time, as a transcendental idealist, that our organism is so constituted, that we can only ever perceive the external world as representations. We can only have one or the other. The second argument is that this form of reasoning cannot prove anything at all. It starts from na„ve realism so as to demonstrate that our world-picture is nothing other than the subjective content of representations. Even if the conclusion is

correct, it cannot be proven from a contrary premise. The final point, summarizing the others, is that: Transcendental idealism demonstrates its truth by using the same premises as the na„ve realism which it aims to refute.91 The conclusion Steiner draws, therefore, is that there is no alternative but to abandon this path. If there is to be a credible foundation for an epistemology it must lie outside the well-trodden paths of uncritical na„ve realism and neo- Kantian transcendental idealism.

91 Ibid, p. 46.

92 Ibid, p. 47.

93 Ibid, p. 48, this writer’s italics

4.2 Steiner’s argument for intellectual intuition

The positive epistemological argument of Truth and Knowledge commences at the end of chapter 3, and is developed in chapters 4 and 5. At the conclusion of his response to Kant, Steiner observes that the use of thinking is the unspoken element upon which the subjectivist transcendental arguments rely. Subjectivism presupposes that, starting from certain facts, logical thinking will lead to correct conclusions. As Steiner observes, … the justification for using thinking in this way is not examined by this philosophical approach.92 The difference between the na„ve realist view of the world and the critical, according to Steiner, is the element of thinking. When this analysis is applied to self observation, one recognizes that … (a) critical attitude is one that comes to grips with the laws of its own activity in order to discover their reliability and limits.93 The epistemologist, therefore, will need to attend to the laws inherent in cognition through the engagement of thinking.

In Chapters 4 and 5 Steiner endeavours, like many before him, to set out what the foundation must be for any epistemology. Steiner has the benefit of having learnt from the mistakes and pitfalls of Kant, Fichte, Hegel and other foundational thinkers. He is wary of any preconceptions. The starting point of any epistemology, Steiner observes, must nevertheless

Page 26 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt be the state of things … immediately prior to cognition, so that the very next step man takes beyond it is the activity of cognition.94 For this, Steiner introduces the concept of the directly given.95 The directly given comprises a world content, which includes concepts and ideas mediated to us by intellectual intuition.96 Through intellectual intuition we come to realise that it is the activity of thinking, which is the origin of cognition. In chapter 4 Steiner describes the directly given and postulates intellectual intuition. In chapter 5 he identifies cognition with the activity of thinking.

94 ibid, p. 51.

95 WW, p. 27:das unmittelbar gegebene Weltbild

96 Ibid, p. 34: Nur die Begriffe und Ideen sind uns in der Form gegeben, die man die intellektuelle Anschauung genannt hat. The rendering of intellektuelle Anschauung in the Stebbing translation as intellectual seeing avoids the difficulties inherent in intuition, but it also misses the point of Steiner’s using Kant’s language.

97 Ibid, pp 51-52: it is correct to describe this buzzin’, bloomin’ confusion as disconnected and undifferentiated, precisely because it is the activity of thinking, which connects and differentiates our sense- impressions.

98 ibid, p. 52.

99 KRV, A21, B36, p. 70: Diese gehören zur reinen Anschauung, die a priori, auch ohne einen wirklichen Gegenstand der Sinne oder Empfindung, als eine bloße Form der Sinnlichkeit im Gemüte stattfindet.

The state of things immediately prior to cognition is what Steiner calls our directly given world picture:

… that picture of the world which presents itself to man before he has subjected it to the processes of knowledge in any way, before he has asserted or decided anything at all about it by means of thinking. This directly given is what flits past us, disconnected, but still undifferentiated.97

Steiner says of the world picture before conceptual activity that it … contains neither substance, quality nor cause and effect; distinctions between matter and spirit, body and soul, do not yet exist.98 It is interesting to compare this with Kant’s deconstruction of sense experience in the Transcendental Aesthetic. There Kant, it will be remembered, removes the qualities of substance, power, hardness and colour to be left with space and time as pure intuitions, as preconditions of sensibility, and, therefore, of cognition.99 Steiner’s is a more

radical surgery, which also removes the concepts upon which the Kantian critique comes to rely. Steiner notes:

Furthermore, any other predicate must also be excluded from the world-picture at this stage. The picture can be considered neither as reality nor as appearance, neither subjective nor objective, neither as chance nor as necessity; whether it is thing-in- itself, or mere representation, cannot be decided at this stage.100

Page 27 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

100 TK, p. 52.

101 If it were to, it would be as a consequence of cognition, and could not, therefore, constitute a starting- point.

Steiner is aware that his concept of the directly given world picture does not, and indeed, cannot, correspond with any known form, or stage, of consciousness.101 He is also aware that the division between the given and the known is, despite his best efforts, drawn artificially. He is determining what is removed from the given world picture, so as to leave merely the directly given, and he is using conceptual definitions to do it. He comments that the process of successive extraction does not determine the starting-point of epistemology, but points in the direction of it:

… what we have extracted by means of thought does not characterize the directly given world-picture, nor define nor express anything about it; what it does is to guide our attention to the dividing line, where the starting point for cognition is to be found. … To remove from this all that has been contributed by cognition, and to establish a pre-cognitive starting point, can only be done conceptually. But such concepts are not of value as knowledge; they have the purely negative function of removing from sight all that belongs to knowledge, and of leading us to the point where knowledge begins.

The point prior to cognition is the conceptual separation between the directly given and cognition, but there is no distinction of content to distinguish the given from the known. As a result, the directly given world content must include:

… everything that enters our experience in the widest sense: sensations, perceptions, opinions, feelings, deeds, pictures of dreams and imaginations, representations, concepts and ideas.

Illusions and hallucinations too, at this stage, are equal to the rest of the world- content. For their relation to other perceptions can be revealed only through observation based on cognition.102

102 TK, p. 56.

103 Descartes, R. (1960) Meditations, Penguin Books: London pp 111-112, writer’s italics; qu’est-ce que je suis? Un chose pendant …

104 Ibid, p. 110: I am, I exist: that is certain. But for how long? For as long as I think.

It is interesting to compare this depiction of the content of the directly given, as the starting point for all knowledge, with Descartes’ depiction of the content of thinking:

Page 28 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt And so, once again, what am I? A thinking thing – a thing, that is to say, which doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wills, and does not will, and which also affirms and feels. … And it is I who imagine, for though chance may have it, as I have already supposed, that everything I imagine is false, the power of imagining still belongs truly to me and to my thought. Finally, it is I who sense or perceive physical things through my senses, I who see the light, hear a noise, and feel heat. … And to feel, in this precise sense, is nothing other than to think.103

Although Descartes describes his victory over existential doubt with the active cogito, ergo sum104, his argument is based upon the concept of himself as a thinking thing. He argues from the content of thinking, in its broadest sense, to establish the existence of the I. Steiner argues from a similar content, as the content of the directly given, to deny that either the existence of consciousness or of the I has been established, and to assert that what has been established, rather, is the primacy of the activity of thinking:

When epistemology starts from the assumption that all the elements just mentioned constitute the content of our consciousness, the following question immediately arises: How is it possible for us to go beyond our consciousness and recognize actual existence; where can the leap be made from our subjective experiences to what lies beyond them? When such an assumption is not made, the situation is different. Both consciousness and the representation of the I are, to begin with, only parts of the directly-given and the relationship of the latter to the two former must be discovered by the means of cognition. Cognition is not to be defined in terms of consciousness,

but vice versa: both consciousness and the relation between subject and object in terms of cognition.105

105 TK, p. 57.

106 IWL, p. 73: When you posit an object that is accompanied by the thought that it has exercised an effect upon you, then you also think of yourself as affected in this case. And when you think that this is what occurs in the case of every object you perceive, then you think of yourself as generally affectable. In other words, it is by means of this act of your own thinking that you ascribe receptivity or sensibility to yourself. Thus the object, considered as something given, is also something merely thought of …

107 TK, p. 57: Since the given is left without predicate, to begin with, the question arises as to how it is defined at all; how can any start be made with cognition? How does one part of the world-picture come to be designated as perception and the other as concept, one thing as existence, another as appearance, this as cause and that as effect; how is it that we can separate ourselves from what is objective and regard ourselves as I in contrast to the not-I?

108 Loc. cit.

109 TK, p. 58.

Page 29 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt Steiner casts doubt over a wider canvas than does Descartes: for Steiner (as for Fichte106) there is doubt about the objectivity of the object, the givenness of the given.107

Steiner’s strategy now is to find the bridge from the world-picture as given, to that other world-picture which we build up by means of cognition.108 Steiner does not argue for the existence of such a bridge, but appears to take it as a given. This is concerning, and surprising, as he has been so careful to locate a starting point for epistemology without any presuppositions. His rationale for assuming the existence of such a bridge is that, otherwise, our relationship with the directly given world picture could be nothing more than descriptive:

Somewhere in the given we must find a place where we can set to work, where something exists which is akin to cognition. If everything were really only given, we could do no more than merely stare into the external world and stare indifferently into the inner world of our individuality. We would at most be able to describe things as something external to us; we should never be able to understand them. Our concepts would have a purely external relation to that to which they referred; they would not be inwardly related to it. For real cognition depends on finding a sphere somewhere in the given where our cognizing activity does not merely presuppose something given, but finds itself active in the very essence of the given.109

It seems that Steiner has become hostage to the very begging-of-the-question he had set out to avoid. The purpose of his argument was to discover whether and how our concepts have a relationship with the given, not to assume it. We are now told that real cognition occurs when our cognizing activity finds itself active in the very essence of the given. The concepts real cognition, cognizing activity and the essence of the given are not defined or explained, and the use of them can only have the effect of diminishing the effect of the argument Steiner has so far maintained.

The bridge Steiner discovers between cognition and the given arises, he claims, from closer examination of the nature of the given. Within the given there is also the not-given.110 Steiner does not say what he means by formally part of the given, but it will, presumably, not amount to a formal constituent of perception, such as Kant’s intuitions of space, time and causation. He seems to be saying that what, at the commencement of the enquiry, appears to be all of the one nature is on closer observation, or further reflection, in fact differentiated into the given and the not-given. There would be nothing remarkable in that, except that observation and reflection are the very activities, which would seem to be most associated with the engagement of a consciousness and an ego. If this is so, then Steiner has separated out the not-given from the given through assuming the initiating activity of the very elements he has argued are to be defined in terms of cognition, for:

110Loc. cit: … precisely through strict adherence to the given as merely given, it must become apparent that not everything is given. Insistence on the given alone must lead to the discovery of something which goes beyond the given. … the given also includes what according to its very nature is not given. The latter would appear, to

Page 30 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt begin with, as formally part of the given, but on closer scrutiny, would reveal its true nature of its own accord.

Both consciousness and the representation of the I are, to begin with, only parts of the directly-given and the relationship of the latter to the two former must be discovered by means of cognition. Cognition is not to be defined in terms of

consciousness, but vice versa: both consciousness and the relation between subject and object in terms of cognition.111

111 TK, p. 57.

112 Ibid, p. 58.

113Loc. cit; this is an exact translation: WW. p. 32: Dies ist der zweite Punkt unserer Erkenntnistheorie. Er besteht in den Postulat: es muß im Gebiete des Gegebenen etwas liegen, wo unserer Tätigkeit nicht im Leeren schwebt, wo der Inhalt der Welt selbst in dieser Tätigkeit eingeht.

114 TK, p. 59: It is essential to remember that it is we ourselves who postulate what characteristic feature that part of the world-content must possess with which our activity of cognition can make a start.

Steiner has one further argument for concluding that there must be something in the given, which is both not-given, and immediately connected to cognition. It is this:

The whole difficulty in understanding cognition comes from the fact that we ourselves do not create the content of the world. If we did this, cognition would not exist at all. I can only ask questions about something which is given to me. Something which I create myself, I also determine myself, so that I do not need to ask for an explanation of it.112

This argument, again, assumes the existence of a consciousness, and an I, prior to cognition. I can only ask questions implies a consciousness separate from the given, and something, which is given to me implies a separation between the given and the not-given me. Steiner’s final claim – that I do not need to ask for an explanation for what I create myself – is also not any form of proof of a bridge between what he has defined as the given, and the process of cognition. As a result Steiner is left to summarise his argument as a postulate:

This is the second step in our theory of knowledge. It consists in the postulate: In the sphere of the given there must be something in relation to which our activity does not hover in emptiness, but where the content of the world itself enters this activity.113

Steiner acknowledges that his argument for a bridge between the directly given world-picture

Page 31 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt and cognition is insufficient to qualify as proof, and can amount to nothing more than a postulate.114

Steiner now seeks to identify which part of the given world is, in fact, not-given, and which forms a bridge with the process of cognition, by engaging with our activity. It will be that part, which of its nature is connected with, or forms part of, the process of cognition. It is concepts and ideas which, in fact, arise in the act of cognition, and only then can they form part of the given.115 Steiner has arrived at his bridge between the directly given world- content and cognition. The bricks and mortar of the bridge, it might be said, are concepts and ideas, while the framework itself is intellectual intuition. Intellectual intuition has such a central role, for Concepts and ideas alone are given us in a form that could be called intellectual intuition.116

115Ibid, p. 60: It is a characteristic feature of all the rest of our world-picture that it must be given if we are to experience it; the only case in which the opposite occurs is that of concepts and ideas: these we must produce if we are to experience them.

116 See fn 97.

117TK, pp 60-61.

In describing the form in which we receive concepts and ideas as intellectual intuition Steiner is alluding, specifically, to Kant’s notion of intellectual intuition. Contrary to the Kantian view, he argues that concepts are not empty, because we do possess the capacity for intellectual intuition.

Kant and the later philosophers who follow in his steps, completely deny this ability to man, because it is said that all thinking refers only to objects and does not itself produce anything. In intellectual seeing [Anschauung] the content must be contained within the thought-form itself. But is this not precisely the case with pure concepts and ideas? … If one clings to the Kantian assertion that of themselves concepts are empty, it would be impossible to determine anything about the given world. Suppose two elements of the world-content were given: a and b. If I am to find a relation between them, I must do so with the help of a principle which has a definite content; I can only produce this principle myself in the act of cognition; I cannot derive it from the objects, for the definition of the objects is only to be obtained by means of the principle. Thus a principle by means of which we define objects belongs entirely to the conceptual sphere alone.117

If Steiner has demonstrated the existence of intellectual intuition, in the form denied by Kant, he will have gone a long way towards establishing that dualism can be overcome in the process of cognition. But is that what Steiner has established? He has postulated that there must be some not-given in the directly given, which connects with our efforts at cognition; he

Page 32 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt has identified this not-given with concepts and ideas, and he has claimed that concepts and ideas present themselves to us in the very form of intellectual intuition Kant describes as unavailable to the human intellect. His argument for this latter claim is that our use of concepts to associate elements of the world-content requires that those concepts contain principles, which we produce in the act of cognition. They cannot, Steiner claims, have arisen from the directly-given world-content, for the definition of the objects is only to be obtained by means of the principle. It was, however, Steiner’s own postulate that the given world- content contains an element, which is not-given, and that this element consists in concepts and ideas. He does not explain how it is that these very directly-given concepts and ideas do not contain the principles of association between other elements of the given, and why it is that, from these postulates, we need to postulate the existence of intellectual intuition.118

118This is surprising, because Steiner does attempt to respond to the objection, that he has been operating covertly with a concept [Vorstellung] of the I. He claims (TK, p. 61.) that his uses of the expressions we produce concepts and we insist on this or that are merely turns of phrase, and do not commit him to the position that consciousness precedes cognition. These very turns of phrase, however, imply the preceding existence, not only of a conscious I, but of a whole community of similar consciousnesses.

5. Intellectual intuition and the activity of thinking

The third element Steiner introduces into his theory of knowledge is the activity of thinking. Steiner’s analysis of the process of cognition seems to be this: (1) At the moment preceding cognition the world-picture is directly given; (2) from the world-picture concepts and ideas have been separated out, and (3) knowledge arises from the activity of thinking in reuniting

concepts and ideas with the given. Steiner describes the last stage as the act of restoration, and says:

The act of restoration consists in thinking about the world as given. Our thinking consideration of the world brings about the actual union of the two parts of the world- content: the part we survey as given on the horizon of our experience, and the part which has to be produced in the act of cognition before that can be given also. The act of cognition is the synthesis of these two elements. Indeed, in every single act of cognition, one part appears as something produced within that act itself, and through that act, as added to the merely given.119

119 Ibid, pp 63-64.

120 Ibid, p. 64: To permeate the world, as given, with concepts and ideas, is a thinking consideration of things. Therefore, thinking is the act which mediates knowledge. It is only when thinking arranges the world-picture by means of its own activity that knowledge can come about. Thinking itself is an activity which, in the moment of cognition, produces a content of its own. Therefore, insofar as the content that is cognized issues from thinking, it contains no problem for cognition. We have only to observe it; the very nature of what we observe is given us directly. A description of thinking is also at the same time the science of thinking.

121 Ibid, p. 65.

Page 33 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

It is the activity of thinking, therefore, which lies at the very core of all cognition, and it is the recognition that there is content to the activity of thinking, which distinguishes Steiner’s epistemology from the Kantian.120 Steiner is now able to provide a description of the kind of activity in which thinking engages when it restores the world-picture, and says:

… thinking approaches the given world-content as an organizing principle. The process takes place as follows: Thinking first lifts out certain entities from the totality of the world-whole. In the given nothing is really separate; everything is a connected continuum. Then thinking relates these separate entities to each other in accordance with the thought-forms it produces, and also determines the outcome of this relationship. When thinking restores a relationship between two separate sections of the world-content, it does not do so arbitrarily. Thinking waits for what comes to light of its own accord as the result of restoring the relationship. And it is this result alone which is knowledge of that particular section of the world content.121

Steiner now compares his analysis of the role of thinking with Kant’s. Kant regards the truths of mathematics and the Newtonian laws of nature as given, and as accessible a priori to cognition. For Steiner, by contrast, there are no such a priori truths, and they can be obtained

as truths only through the activity of thinking. In an allusion to the argument of the Transcendental Deduction122 Steiner argues for the primacy of thinking in cognition and says:

122 CPR, B131, p. 152: It must be possible for the I think’ to accompany all my representations ... All the manifold of intuition has, therefore, a necessary relation to the I think’ in the same subject in which this manifold is found.

123 TK, p. 66.

124 Loc. cit.

125 Ibid, pp 66-67.

126 CPR, B4-B5, p. 44: Now it is easy to show that there actually are in human knowledge judgments which are necessary and in the strictest sense universal, and which are therefore pure a priori judgments. If an example from the sciences be desired, we have only to look to any of the propositions of mathematics; if we seek an example from the understanding in its quite ordinary employment, the proposition, every alteration must have a cause’, will serve our purpose. In the latter case, indeed, the very concept of a cause so manifestly contains the concept of a necessity of connection with an effect and of the strict universality of a rule, that the concept would be altogether lost if we attempted to derive it, as Hume has done, from a repeated association of that which happens ...

Page 34 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt When Kant speaks of the synthetic unity of apperception it is evident that he had some inkling of what we have shown here to be an activity of thinking, the purpose of which is to organize the world-content systematically. But the fact that he believed that the a priori laws of pure science could be derived from the rules according to which this synthesis takes place, shows how little this inkling brought to his consciousness the essential task of thinking. He did not realize that this synthetic activity of thinking is only a preparation for discovering natural laws as such.123

To demonstrate further what he means, Steiner invites the reader to extract one content, a, from the world-picture and another content, b, from the world-picture124 and to assume that a and b are causally related, and that a is the cause and b the effect. From this he concludes that the fact that a and b are causally connected could never become knowledge if thinking were not able to form the concept of causality.125 What Steiner does not address is that Kant also gives a great deal of attention to causation, and argues from the Introduction that causation is a pure a priori judgment, which precedes both experience and thinking in the process of cognition.126

5.1 Steiner’s extrapolation from Fichte’s concept of intellectual intuition

Steiner develops his concept of intellectual intuition in the sixth chapter of Truth and Knowledge, which is entitled Theory of knowledge free of assumptions and Fichte’s science of knowledge. Steiner critiques Fichte’s conception of the relationship between the I, thinking and consciousness, but begins with a restatement of his own derivation of the distinction between knowledge of the given and knowledge of consciousness. Knowledge of the given world leads to a consideration of the idea of knowledge,127 which itself requires a consideration of the activity of consciousness. This is because, unlike the elements of knowledge of the external given world, …the concept and the given reality of consciousness are originally separated.128 As a result, …the idea of knowledge can be united with its corresponding given only by the activity of consciousness, and hence consciousness as a reality exists only if it produces itself.129

127 TK, p. 73: In contrast to the given world, a second world – the world of thinking – rises up to meet the I, and the I unites the two through its own free decision, producing what we have defined as the idea of knowledge.

128 Ibid, p. 74

129 Loc. cit.

130Ibid, p. 75: The science of knowledge … is built up … through a determination of freedom … to become conscious of the general manner of acting of the intelligence. Steiner cites the full text from Fichte, J. (1845) Sämtliche Werke: Berlin, Volume 1, p. 71f.

At this point Steiner believes he has cleared the ground sufficiently, so that it is possible to see with clarity the fundamental mistake in Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre. Steiner begins by

Page 35 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt arguing that the derivation of what Fichte calls the acting of intelligence is nothing other than a less clearly articulated version of Steiner’s postulation of the idea of knowledge. Steiner cites Fichte’s Sämtliche Werke130 and observes:

What does Fichte here mean by the acting of intelligence if we express in clear concepts what he dimly felt? Nothing other than the production of the idea of knowledge, taking place in consciousness. Had Fichte become clear about this, then he would have formulated the above principle as follows: A science of knowledge has the task of bringing to consciousness the act of cognition, insofar as it is still an

unconscious activity of the I; it must show that to objectify the idea of knowledge is a necessary deed of the I.131

131 Loc. Cit.

132 Ibid, pp 76-77.

Fichte, Steiner argues, fails to identify the acting of intelligence with the specific act of knowing. As a result, Steiner claims, Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre is in the end not a theory of knowledge at all, but rather of practical application, or of ethics. Steiner concludes:

The I is to do something, but what is it to do? Fichte did not formulate the concept of knowledge which the I must produce, and in consequence he strove in vain to define any further activity of the I beyond its original deed. In fact, he finally stated that to investigate any such further activity does not lie within the scope of theory. In his deduction of representation, he does not begin from any absolute activity of the I or of the not-I, but he starts from a state of determination which, at the same time, itself determines, because in his view nothing else is, or can be contained directly in consciousness. What in turn determines the state of determination is left completely undecided in his theory; and because of this uncertainty, one is forced beyond theory into practical application of the science of knowledge. However, through this statement Fichte completely abolishes all cognition. For the practical activity of the I belongs to a different sphere altogether. … But if epistemology is to be the foundation of all knowledge, the decisive point is not to have a definition of an I that is free, but of an I that cognizes. 132

At this point the argument of the Wisssenschaftslehre as Steiner understands it, and Steiner’s identification of Fichte’s fundamental mistake, might be expressed by the following propositions. Fichte argues in effect that:

(1) Only a theory of consciousness can provide the foundation for knowledge; now

(2) The ground of consciousness is the I’s postulating of its own existence, which is an intellectual intuition; but

(3) The I’s postulation of its own existence is an activity of the I; and

Page 36 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt (4) This activity is a free process. The ground of all knowledge, therefore, is the free activity of the I in coming to self-consciousness.

According to Steiner, Fichte’s argument ends at this point. Fichte’s fundamental mistake is the failure to take the argument one step further, and to recognize that:

(5) The free activity of the I is a cognitive activity: the I is being active, specifically, in the act of knowing itself.133

133 Ibid, p. 75-78.

134 Ibid, p. 75: Harms, in his address, On the Philosophy of Fichte, (p15) rightly says: His world-view is predominantly and exclusively ethical, and his theory of knowledge has no other feature.

135 Breazeale, D. (1994) Philosophy and the Divided Self, in H. Girndt and W. Schrader (eds) Realität und Gewißheit, Rodopi: Amsterdam and Atlanta, p19: The theoretical quest that animates the Jena Wissenschaftslehre, that is, the quest for a coherent and certain philosophical system able to furnish us with a fully adequate, transcendental account of the full range of everyday experience (including both our practical certainty of our own freedom and our experience of objective reality) is not conceived of by Fichte as an end in itself. Instead, this scientific project is itself a response to a deeper, practical demand – a demand not for theoretical or even for practical certainty, but rather for personal unity or wholeness. We seek systematic unity in the realm of theory (philosophy) not primarily for its own sake, but rather, as a means for coming to terms with and if possible mitigating the painful, existential division within our own selves.

136 IWL, p. 77.

Steiner’s explanation for Fichte’s failure to take the step of identifying the activity of the I with knowing is that Fichte’s real interest, and real agenda, is to formulate a ground for ethics, rather than for epistemology. This is a view of Fichte shared by sources from which Steiner drew134, and by contemporary interpreters of Fichte.135 The effects of this are that Fichte does not complete the epistemological task, and nor, according to Steiner, does he arrive at a credible grounding of the I. As a consequence:

Cognition would have no task to fulfil whatever if all spheres of reality were given in their totality. But the I, so long as it has not been inserted by thinking into the systematic whole of the world-picture, also exists as something merely directly given, so that it does not suffice to point to its activity. Yet Fichte is of the opinion that where the I is concerned, all that is necessary is to seek and find it. … We have seen that the only instance where proof and definitions are not required is in regard to the content of pure logic. The I, however, belongs to reality, where it is necessary to establish the presence of this or that category within the given. This Fichte does not do. And this is why he gave his science of knowledge a mistaken form.136

Page 37 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt Fichte’s endeavour to provide an absolute grounding for the freedom of the I, Steiner argues, leaves him with two possibilities, and the various versions of the Wissenschaftslehre can be seen as a shift from one of these to the other. Steiner observes:

When it is realized that, owing to the whole trend of his philosophy, Fichte could not be content with any starting point for knowledge other than an absolute decree, it becomes clear that he has only two possibilities for making this beginning appear intelligible. One possibility is to focus the attention on one or another of the empirical activities of consciousness, and then crystallize out the pure concept of the I by gradually stripping away everything that did not originally belong to consciousness. The other possibility is to start directly with the original activity of the I, and then to bring its nature to light through self-contemplation and self- observation. Fichte chose the first possibility at the beginning of his philosophical path, but gradually went over to the second.137

137 Ibid, p. 78.

138 Ibid, p. 80: Unless the I sets to work on something given which it postulates, it can do nothing and hence cannot postulate either. Fichte’s own principle actually shows this: The I postulates its existence. This existence is a category. This means we have arrived at our principle: The activity of the I is to postulate, as a free decision, the concepts and ideas of the given. Fichte arrives at his conclusion only because he unconsciously sets out to that the I exists. Had he worked out the concept of cognition, he would then have arrived at the true starting point of a theory of knowledge, namely: The I postulates cognition.

139 Ibid, p. 81.

In both cases Fichte’s argument amounts to an ontological grounding for ethics, rather than for the ground for an epistemology. The crystallizing out of the pure concept of the I could lead to an epistemology, Steiner claims, but Fichte does not allow it to do so.138 The other approach, which Fichte takes from the time of the First Introduction, is more likely to lead immediately to a theory of knowledge. This is because:

In self-observation, the activity of the I is actually seen, not one-sidedly turned in a particular direction, not as merely postulating existence, but revealing many aspects of itself as it strives to grasp the directly given world-content in thinking. Self- observation reveals the I engaged in the activity of building up the world-picture by combining the given with concepts.139

Fichte’s interest, however, is focused so little on the world of the directly given, and so much on the operations of consciousness, that he confuses knowledge with self-consciousness.140 The consequence, according to Steiner, is that the Wissenschaftslehre can never become the basis for the sciences Fichte intended it to be, and the capacity for intuitive knowledge has to be left to a completely new sense organ, which is not yet developed in the human being.141

140 Ibid, p. 82: … for him, the process of knowledge appears to consist in spinning the world out of the I itself. This is why Fichte sees the world-picture more and more as a construction of the I. He emphasizes ever more

Page 38 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt strongly that for the science of knowledge it is essential to awaken the faculty for watching the I while it constructs the world.

141 Loc. cit; Steiner cites Fichte’s Introductory Lecture to the Science of Knowledge, delivered at Berlin University in the autumn of 1813: This science presupposes a completely new inner sense organ, through which a new world is revealed which does not exist for the ordinary man at all.

142 IWL, p. 20.

143TK, p. 84.

Fichte’s failure to recognize that the activity of the I’ is specifically thinking activity is illuminated by Steiner in his commentary on Fichte’s famous dictum: The kind of philosophy one chooses thus depends upon the kind of person one is.142 Fichte is referring to a choice between what he (and Kant) call dogmatism’ and idealism’ – self-consistent world views, which take as their given either the existence of things, or the existence of the I’. Fichte leaves the choice of system to the individual, but, as Steiner says in paraphrasing Fichte: … if one wishes the I to retain its independence, then one will cease to believe in the external things and devote oneself to idealism.143 Fichte does not appear to give any thought to how we might set about making the choice between dogmatism and idealism. Steiner argues that an enquiry into this process leads inexorably to the activity of thinking:

This line of thought fails to consider one thing, namely that the I cannot reach any choice or decision which has some real foundation if it does not presuppose something which enables it to do so. Everything determined by the I remains empty and without content if the I does not find something that is full of content and determined through and through, which then makes it possible for the I to determine the given and, in doing so, also enables it to choose between idealism and dogmatism. This something which is permeated with content through and through is, however, the world of thinking. And to determine the given by means of thinking is to cognize.

No matter from what aspect Fichte is considered, we shall find that his line of thought gains power and life when we think of the activity of the I, which he presents as grey and empty of content, as filled and organized by what we have called the process of cognition.144

144 Loc. Cit.

145 Ibid, p. 85: The present discussion shows that the I is free when it cognizes, when it objectifies the ideas of cognition. For when the directly given and the thought-form belonging to it are united by the I in the process of cognition, then the union of these two elements of reality – which otherwise would forever remain separated in consciousness – can only take place through a free act. Steiner is using the language of Fichte’s earlier descriptions of the derivation of self-consciousness, but the point would remain the same with the third formulation as an activity into which an eye is inserted.

146Loc. cit: Anyone who has acquainted himself intimately with Fichte’s system will know that it was a point

Page 39 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt of vital importance for this philosopher to uphold the principle that nothing from the external world can enter the I, that nothing takes place in the I which is not originally postulated by the I itself.

147See the earlier discussion of Fichte’s claim that there is no essential difference between his philosophy and Kant’s.

Steiner is claiming that the activity of thinking is not grey and empty like Fichte’s picture of the activity of the I, because it is suffused with the content of the directly given world, which it combines with the concepts produced by intellectual intuition. The I does also act freely when it generates the idea of knowledge, when it produces the category of cognition through self-determination145, but otherwise it is only in the activity of thinking itself, that the I can be said to be free. Steiner claims that his discussion sheds a completely new light on critical idealism. It is clear that Steiner has in mind Fichte’s subjective idealism in particular,146 and while Fichte might assert that the same would therefore apply to Kant’s critical idealism as well147, Kant’s presentation of perception in the First Critique suggests that for him, as much as for Steiner, the information we obtain of the world through sense perception is objective and real. Despite the dualism of the critical philosophy there is nothing about Kant’s presentation that detracts from the variety of the manifold of experience, of the directly given world.

But even if Steiner’s criticism of the subjectivity of critical idealism is limited to Fichte’s subjective idealism there are still some serious difficulties with it. Steiner wants to differentiate his own position from Fichte’s, and therefore claims:

Yet it is beyond all doubt that no idealism can derive from the I that form of the world-content which is here described as the directly given. This form of the world- content can only be given; it can never be constructed out of thinking.148

148 TK, p. 85.

Steiner now appears to be opting for a na„ve realist perspective, rather than positioning himself within the idealist tradition, for which the starting point of cognition will always be that what we take as the directly given is mediated to us through our senses together with the activity of consciousness. He also appears to be assuming the critical idealist will seek to assert that the form of the world content can be constructed specifically out of thinking. It is Steiner himself who has introduced thinking as the active element in the process of cognition. The critical idealist need only reply that Steiner has provided an argument against his own removal of the process of cognition from the self-consciousness of intellectual intuition to thinking.

Steiner must, of course, argue for the independent reality of the directly given if he is establish his case for access to essences, and if he is to be consistent with the theory of knowledge he has extracted from Goethe’s scientific studies. These two sources of Steiner’s epistemology now start to merge as he draws a distinction between the sense-perceptible and

Page 40 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt the essential nature of the given. Steiner returns to his claim that human cognition can have access to essences when he says:

It is, however, one thing merely to be aware of the given world; it is quite another to recognize its essential nature. This latter, though intimately connected with the world-content, does not become clear to us unless we ourselves build up reality out of the given and the activity of thinking. The essential What of the given is postulated

for the I only through the I itself. Yet the I would have no occasion to postulate within itself the nature of something given if it did not first find itself confronted by a completely undetermined given. Therefore, what is postulated by the I as the nature and being of the world is not postulated without the I, but through it.149

149 Loc. cit.

150 or positings; WW: Das eigentliche Was des Gegebenen wird für das Ich nur durch das letzten selbst gesetzt [writer’s italics].

151 TK, p. 87.

152 Steiner may yet qualify as an idealist; see, for example, Rockmore, T. (2007) Kant and Idealism, Yale UP: New Haven and London, p. 2: Though some of the most interesting thinkers in the Western philosophical

Steiner’s essential What of the given is not, of course, the Kantian thing-in-itself. Steiner is building a case that the essential What of the given is accessible as knowledge through the postulations150 of the I, and through the activity of thinking. That is, the connection he had sought to establish between the given world and cognition through Goethe’s way of seeing he is now seeking to establish by starting from a critique of the activity of thinking. Steiner therefore claims that, through his examination of the activity of thinking, he has constructed a true idealism grounded in the world as it really is, and concludes:

Our theory of knowledge supplies the foundation for true idealism in the real sense of the word. It establishes the conviction that in thinking the essence of the world is mediated. Through thinking alone the relationship between the details of the world- content become manifest, be it the relation of the sun to the stone it warms, or the relation of the I to the external world. In thinking alone the element is given which determines all things in their relations to one another.151

Bearing in mind his trenchant criticism of Kant, the move he is now making away from Fichte, and his evident attachment to Goethe’s form of empirical enquiry, one might wonder why Steiner feels impelled to regard his own epistemology as any form of idealism. There is little in the structure of Steiner’s argument which would qualify him as an idealist. The explanation may simply be that Steiner is looking to position himself amongst his contemporaries in the neo-Kantian tradition.152

tradition are widely taken to be, and even took themselves to be, idealists, there is no agreement on the

Page 41 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt meaning of idealism.

153 TK, pp 89-91.

154 Ibid, pp 93-95.

155 Ibid, p. 89.

156 By subjective idealism Steiner means Kant’s and Fichte’s critical idealism, Schelling’s and Hegel’s absolute idealism, and all other forms of transcendental idealism, so as to distinguish them from what he describes as his objective idealism.

157 By definition; in this, Steiner is following Fichte, who elaborates the one-sidedness both of dogmatism and idealism in the First Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre; IWL, p. 11ff

158 TK, p. 90: The adherent of skepticism must cease to doubt the possibility of knowing the world, for there is no room for doubt in regard to the given – it is still untouched by all predicates later bestowed on it by means of cognition. Should the sceptic maintain that our cognitive thinking can never approach the world, he can only maintain this with the help of thinking, and in so doing refutes himself. Whoever attempts to establish doubt in thinking by means of thinking itself admits, by implication, that thinking contains a power strong enough to support a conviction.

5.2 From intellectual intuition to intuitive thinking

Steiner concludes Truth and Knowledge with two short chapters, an Epistemological Conclusion153 and a Practical Conclusion.154 The Epistemological Conclusion states the position Steiner’s argument has reached, which is to assert that knowledge arises from the activity of thinking. He has not yet sought to demonstrate how the activity of thinking will provide knowledge of essences. Steiner makes several bold claims about what he has achieved. He claims:

We acquire positive insight through particular judgments; through the theory of knowledge we learn the value of this insight for reality. Because we have adhered strictly to this absolutely fundamental principle and have not evaluated any particular instances of knowledge in our discussion, we have transcended all one-sided world- views.155

This transcendence is said to encompass dogmatism, subjective idealism156 and all forms of skepticism. Dogmatism and subjective idealism, according to Steiner, are clearly one- sided,157 while skepticism is one-sided by dint of its failure to acknowledge the reality of the given, and to acknowledge its own dependency upon thinking.158 The second bold claim is to have succeeded where Kant, and many others, had failed:

Page 42 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt

… our theory of knowledge transcends both one-sided empiricism and one-sided rationalism by uniting them at a higher level. In this way, justice is done to both.

Empiricism is justified by showing that as far as content is concerned, all knowledge of the given is to be attained only through direct contact with the given. And it will be found that this view also does justice to rationalism in that thinking is declared to be both the necessary and the only mediator of knowledge.159

159 Loc. cit.

160 TK, p. 91; WW, p. 57: Und wir glauben in der Tat gezeigt zu haben, daß der Streit der Weltanschauungen daher kommt, daß man ein Wissen über ein Objektives (Ding, Ich, Bewußtsein usw.) zu erwerben trachtet, ohne vorher desjenigen genau zu kennen, was allein erst über alle andere Wissen Auschluß geben kann: die Natur des Wissens selbst [this writer’s italics]

Steiner speaks as if all empiricists make no attempt to account for the deficits identified by rationalists in an empiricist view of knowledge, and that rationalists, likewise, never allow for interplay between thinking and an empirical reality. The contrary, of course, is the case, and the history both of empiricism and of rationalism is the history of ever more sophisticated attempts to account for the whole of inner and of outer reality from a specific base. Steiner does not explain what he means by uniting empiricism and rationalism at a higher level, but this is, presumably, the level at which the activity of thinking emerges as the mediator between the directly given world content and intellectual intuition. Steiner’s final epistemological claim is a summary of the others, namely:

And we believe that we have shown that all conflicts between world-views result from a tendency to attempt to attain knowledge of something objective (thing, I, consciousness, etc) without having first gained a sufficiently exact knowledge of what alone can elucidate all knowledge: the nature of knowledge itself.160

This claim leads on to Steiner’s Practical Conclusion, from which it is apparent that Steiner’s search for knowledge of essences will inevitably lead on to wider, cosmological implications:

It is part of man’s task to bring into the sphere of apparent reality the fundamental laws of the universe which, although they rule all existence, would never come to existence as such. The very nature of knowledge [Natur des Wissens] is that the world-foundation [Weltengrund], which is not to be found as such in objective reality,

is present in it. Our knowledge [Erkennen] – pictorially expressed – is a gradual, living penetration into the world’s foundation.161

161 TK, p. 93; Natur des Wissens is better translated as nature of knowing, and should be distinguished from

Page 43 15 Part 2 Chapter 6 INTELLECTUAL INTUITION.txt Erkennen, which does translate as knowledge; Weltengrund is better translated as world-ground, which is clumsy in English, but retains the Fichtean and German Idealist concept of ground.

In Philosophy of Freedom Steiner elaborates his arguments for grounding both his epistemological and his practical conclusions on intuitive thinking.

Page 44 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt PART 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING

The fourth disjunction between Kantian epistemology and Steiner’s notion of cognition concerns the activity of thinking, and it follows on from the disjunction over intellectual intuition. If it is accepted that a case can be made (as it is by Fichte) for intellectual intuition as a function of human cognition, it then becomes a question of the role intellectual intuition is to be designated in the act of knowing. Fichte shows that intellectual intuition leads to an activity, but does not specify what that activity is said to be. In Truth and Knowledge Steiner argues that this activity is, specifically, the activity of thinking engaged in producing ideas and concepts. Steiner designates this mode of thinking as intuitive thinking, and makes the claim in Philosophy of Freedom that it is in the process of thinking intuitively that human beings experience freedom.1 For Steiner there is an immediate and necessary association between intuitive thinking and freedom. Kant, on the other hand, claims in the Preface to the Second Edition of the First Critique that freedom, and our consciousness of freedom, is an ethical, rather than a cognitive, concept and is neither regulative nor constitutive of the activity of pure reason.2 The fourth disjunction, therefore, represents a further step for Steiner away from the epistemology of the critical philosophy. It is, in fact, the last step Steiner takes before abandoning his project of attempting to ground knowledge of essences within the framework of the neo-Kantian tradition.

1 Ph F, Ch 12 Addendum [1], ITSP, pp 192-193: It is especially significant that the justification for calling a will free comes from the experience that a conceptual intuition realizes itself in the will. … This is achievable because in conceptual intuition nothing but its self-based essence is at work. … If I observe willing that is the image of an intuition, then all organically necessary activity has withdrawn from that willing. The will is free.

2 CPR, B xxxiii, p. 31: the consciousness of freedom rests exclusively on the clear exhibition of duties …

The argument of this chapter is developed over six sections. The first and second sections give an account of Kant’s concepts of thinking and freedom, as these two concepts are

intertwined by Steiner in Philosophy of Freedom in the course of his argument for intuitive thinking. The first section shows that thinking must be transparent and discursive for Kant, rather than creative and intuitive as Steiner would have it. The second section is an account of Kant’s concept of freedom, and of the ambiguous role Kant assigns to freedom within the critical philosophy. The third section then examines Steiner’s presentations of thinking and freedom in Philosophy of Freedom, for it is from these two concepts that he derives intuitive thinking. The derivation of intuitive thinking is central to Steiner’s epistemological project and it is the ground of the epistemological claims of his anthroposophical spiritual science. There are difficulties within the derivation, and for that reason it has become the source of heated debate amongst philosophically-inclined anthroposophists. The fourth section is concerned with these difficulties and the implications they will have for Steiner’s prospects of demonstrating that the critical philosophy can be extended to include knowledge of essences. The fifth section is a short discussion of the observation debate, the question of whether it is possible to observe oneself in the process of thinking. The final section asserts that, as with the perception of archetypes, Steiner has again been unable to ground the apperception of essences from within the framework of the neo-Kantian tradition.

1. Kant’s concept of thinking

Page 1 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt

Kant introduces thinking into the argument of the First Critique in the Transcendental Deduction of the Transcendental Analytic, but does so in the form of what he calls the I think’.3 It is noteworthy that although the whole argument of the critical philosophy

3 Ibid, B131, p. 152.

depends to a considerable extent upon the capacity of thinking to generate concepts,4 Kant does not direct his attention to thinking itself until he is accounting for how the elements of cognition adhere, when he is describing the unification of those elements as the synthetic unity of apperception and the transcendental unity of self-consciousness.5 In the course of this argument Kant identifies the I think’ as the unseen element in all cognitive activity, which he describes as being present within the consciousness of all representations of experience. Kant then introduces the I think’ and its association with representations and consciousness in the following way:6

4 Ibid, A19, B33, p. 65: Objects are given to us by means of sensibility, and it alone yields us intuitions; they are thought through the understanding, and from the understanding arise concepts.

5 Ibid, B132, p. 153.

6 Ibid, B131-132, pp 152-153.

7The contrast Kant wants to draw is that the I think is a reality for Descartes, while for Kant it is merely contingent. In the introduction to the Paralogisms of Pure Reason Kant says at A 347, B405. p. 332: The proposition I think’, is, however, here taken only problematically, not in so far as it may contain perception of an existent (the Cartesian cogito, ergo sum), but in respect of its mere possibility, in order to see what properties applicable to its subject (be that subject actually existent or not) may follow from so simple a proposition.

8 Ibid, B131-132, pp 152-153.

It must be possible for the I think’ to accompany all my representations; for otherwise something would be represented in me which could not be thought at all, and that is equivalent to saying that the representation would be impossible, or at least would be nothing to me. That representation which can be given prior to all thought is entitled intuition. All the manifold of intuition has, therefore, a necessary relation to the I think’ in the same subject in which this manifold is found.

It is striking that Kant speaks in terms of the I think’ rather than the activity of thinking, and that he presents the I think’ as the ground of all intuitions. It may be that Kant does this to contrast his conception of the role of thinking with Descartes’ cogito.7 Kant no doubt has sensory intuitions in mind, but he continues his account of the I think’ in the Transcendental Deduction in a way which is suggestive of intellectual intuition, for he says:8

But this representation is an act of spontaneity, that is, it cannot be regarded as

Page 2 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt belonging to sensibility. I call it pure apperception, to distinguish it from empirical apperception, or, again, original apperception, because it is that self-consciousness which, while generating the representation I think’ (a representation which must be capable of accompanying all other representations, and which in all consciousness is one and the same), cannot itself be accompanied by any further representation.

The difference between the I think’ and intellectual intuition is that although the I think’ is also generated by an act of spontaneity it is nevertheless a representation [Vorstellung] generated by another representation, namely self-consciousness. For Kant both self- consciousness and the I think’, therefore, are not to be regarded as anything more than representations and they are not elements of consciousness of which we can have immediate knowledge.

Because the I think’ can be no more accessible to cognition than in the form of a representation Kant does not consider the activity of thinking separately from the substance’, the I’, which thinks. The Paralogisms of Pure Reason are designed to demonstrate that while the I think’ ... contains the form of each and every judgment of understanding and accompanies all categories as their vehicle9 the consequence is that thinking, like the I’, has no substance of its own. As a result, it could never be the case for Kant that thinking of itself could provide knowledge of an object.10 Indeed, thinking for Kant could never be anything more than Steiner’s description of it as ... the unobserved element in our normal spiritual life11 and, from Kant’s perspective, it would never be possible to observe the I’ in the act of thinking, for ... I do not know myself through being conscious of myself as thinking, but

9Ibid, B406, p. 368.

10Loc. cit: The following general remark may, at the outset, aid us in our scrutiny of this kind of argument. I do not know an object merely in that I think …

11Ph F, Ch 3 [12], ITSP, p. 33.

only when I am conscious of the intuition of myself as determined with respect to the functions of thought.12

12 CPR, B 406, p. 368.

13 Kant, I. (1972) (ed H Paton) The Moral Law: Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, Hutchinson University Library: London; hereinafter Groundwork and GW

14 CPR, B xxvii-xxviii, p. 28.

2. Kant’s concept of freedom

Kant says a great deal more about freedom than he does about thinking. Freedom is the constitutive principle of practical reason, and is therefore at the centre of the arguments both of the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals13 and of the Second Critique. There is, however, also some discussion of freedom in the First Critique, and it is particularly interesting, because it gives the impression that for Kant, as much as for Fichte and for Steiner, the epistemological argument is designed to ground an ethics within which moral

Page 3 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt choices are to be made by a free will. Kant’s references to freedom begin in the Preface to the Second Edition of the First Critique. Here Kant is referring to the division between appearances and things-in-itself as a way of accounting for the seeming contradiction between natural determination and freedom of the will. He then says of human freedom:

But if our Critique is not in error in teaching that the object is to be taken in a twofold sense, namely as appearance and as thing in itself … then there is no contradiction in supposing that one and the same will is, in the appearance, that is, in its visible acts, necessarily subject to the law of nature, and so far not free, while yet, as belonging to a thing in itself, it is not subject to that law, and is therefore free. My soul, viewed from the latter standpoint, cannot indeed be known by means of speculative reason (and still less through empirical observation); and freedom as a property of a being to which I attribute effects in the sensible world, is therefore also not knowable in any such fashion.14

Although there is freedom of the will, Kant argues, we are not able to know whether or not we are free or can exercise freedom.15 This is because, even though we can think freedom, our actual knowledge is limited to the world of appearances.16 That is also why freedom must enter into our understanding of practical reason but not of pure reason. The exercise of freedom of the will, as the determinative principle of moral action, does not itself require that we understand freedom,17 nor even that we have any consciousness of it.18

15 Loc. cit: But though I cannot know, I can yet think freedom.

16 Ibid, B xxix, p. 29.

17 Loc Cit

18Ibid, B xxxiii, p. 31: the consciousness of freedom rests exclusively on the clear exhibition of duties, in opposition to all claims of the inclinations;

19 Ibid, B473, p. 409.

Even though Kant has already dispensed with freedom as an element of the epistemological argument in the Preface to the Second Edition, he deals with freedom again in the Antinomies of the Transcendental Aesthetic. In the third antinomy Kant sets out the maxims for the arguments for and against the existence of freedom as freedom of the will in the form of the following dialectic:

Thesis Antithesis

Causality in accordance with the There is no freedom; everything in the laws of nature is not the only world takes place solely in accordance causality from which the appear- with laws of nature. ances of the world can one and all

Page 4 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt be derived. To explain these appearances it is necessary to assume that there is also another causality, that of freedom.19

He then provides the proofs for each of the thesis and the antithesis. The proof for the thesis is concluded in this way:

We must, then, assume a causality through which something takes place, the cause of which is not itself determined, in accordance with necessary laws, by another cause antecedent to it, that is to say, an absolute spontaneity of the cause, whereby a series of appearances, which proceeds in accordance with laws of nature, begins of itself. This is transcendental freedom, without which, even in the [ordinary] course of nature, the series of appearances on the side of the causes can never be complete.20

20 Ibid, B474-475, pp 410-411.

21 Loc. Cit.

The proof Kant devises for the antithesis relies upon the apparent contradiction between freedom and conformity to law, and concludes:

If freedom were determined in accordance with laws, it would not be freedom; it would simply be nature under another name. Nature and transcendental freedom differ as do conformity to law and lawlessness.21

It is clear from the way in which Kant structures these proofs of the third antinomy that he is leaving the way open for a conception of freedom in the Second Critique, which will not be transcendent but immanent, and in which freedom is consistent with conformity to law, but to moral law rather than to natural law.

Despite Kant’s arguments against the possibility of the knowledge of freedom, and the equivocation of the third antinomy as to the actuality of freedom, there is a sense in which freedom is a necessary constituent of his epistemological argument as well. A critique of pure reason, as Kant recognizes towards the end of the First Critique in the Transcendental Doctrine of Method, requires the liberty, or freedom (as freedom from restriction), to subject reason to recurrent criticism. In setting out the Discipline of Pure Reason Kant then observes:

Reason must in all its undertakings subject itself to criticism; should it limit freedom of criticism by any prohibitions, it must harm itself, drawing upon itself a damaging suspicion. Nothing is so important through its usefulness, nothing so sacred, that it

Page 5 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt

may be exempted from this searching examination, which knows no respect for persons. Reason depends on this freedom for its very existence.22

22 Ibid, B 766, p. 593.

23 GW, p. 107: Will is a kind of causality belonging to living beings so far as they are rational. Freedom would then be the property this causality has of being able to work independently of determination by alien causes.

24Loc. cit: The above definition of freedom is negative and consequently unfruitful as a way of grasping its essence …

25Loc. cit: The concept of causality carries with it that of laws (Gesetze) in accordance with which, because of something else we call a cause, something else – namely, its effect – must be posited (gesetzt). Hence freedom of will, although it is not the property of conforming to laws of nature, is not for this reason lawless …

26 Ibid, p. 108.

27Ibid, p. 119: Reason would overstep its limits if it took upon itself to explain how pure reason can be practical. This would be identical with explaining how freedom is possible.

This kind of freedom, which is exercised in the process of self-criticism, will be super- rational, and will be consistent with conformity to the laws of reason.

Kant’s subsequent elaborations of freedom as free will in the Groundwork and in the Second Critique shed further light on the limitations he is applying to the concept of freedom. In the Groundwork Kant only begins to speak about freedom after he has formulated the metaphysic of moral action in terms of the will, duty, the categorical imperative and the various formulations of the moral law. He then introduces freedom as a function of causality23 and acknowledges that this is a negative definition of freedom,24 the positive aspect of which is freedom’s capacity to conform to causal laws.25 Freedom, then, must be presupposed as a property of the will of all rational beings,26 though we cannot claim to know how freedom is possible.27 Kant’s conception of freedom in the Groundwork, then, might be said to amount to a rational construct for the law-abiding operation of the will, for Kant concludes the argument by saying:

Thus the Idea of freedom can never admit of full comprehension, or indeed of insight, since it can never by any analogy have an example falling under it. It holds only as a

necessary presupposition of reason in a being who believes himself to be conscious of a will – that is, of a power distinct from mere appetition ...28

28 Loc Cit, appetition appears to be an attempt to translate Willkür without the range of connotations of desire.

Page 6 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt 29 C Pr R, pp 3-4.

30 Ibid, p. 75: What is essential in the moral worth of actions is that the moral law should directly determine the will. p. 76: The essential point in all determination of the will through the moral law is this: as a free will, and thus not only without co-operating with sensuous impulses but even rejecting all of them and checking all inclinations so far as they could be antagonistic to the law, it is determined by the law.

31Ibid, p. 82.

As the Groundwork is designed to set out Kant’s ethical argument in a form which is readily understood by a wider public, it appears that Kant intends to subsume freedom within his deontological ethical position.

In the Preface to the Second Critique Kant identifies freedom as the ground of practical reason and of the speculative concepts, for which he is attempting to find some justification. Kant then says of freedom:

The concept of freedom, in so far as its reality is proved by an apodictic law of practical reason, is the keystone of the whole architecture of the system of pure reason and even of speculative reason. All other concepts (those of God and immortality) which, as mere Ideas, are unsupported by anything in speculative reason now attach themselves to the concept of freedom and gain, with it and through it, stability and objective reality. That is, their possibility is proved by the fact that there really is freedom, for this Idea is revealed by the moral law.29

Freedom is again defined negatively by Kant, this time as the freedom to avoid temptations to disregard the moral law. This is because a free will, in Kant’s view, is a will freed from non- rational feelings, impulses and desires.30 As a result of this not only is free will, but freedom itself is a limiting factor within the critical philosophy:

Freedom, the causality of which is determinable only through the law, consists, however, only in the fact that it limits all inclinations, including self-esteem, to the condition of obedience to its pure law.31

Kant’s concept of freedom, then, is a capacity to exercise moral choice, but only in accordance with the moral law. Thus Kant can exclaim:

Duty! Thou sublime and mighty name that dost embrace nothing charming or insinuating but requires submission and yet seekest not to move the will by threatening aught that would arouse natural aversion or terror, but only holdest forth a law which of itself finds entrance into the mind and yet gains reluctant reverence (though not always obedience) – a law before which all inclinations are mute even though they secretly work against it: what origin is worthy of thee, and where is the root of thy noble descent which proudly rejects all kinship with the inclinations and from which to be descended is the indispensable condition of the only worth which men alone can give themselves?32

32 Ibid, p. 90: the antiquated language is the Lewis White Beck translation.

Page 7 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt

33 ITSP, pp 159-160.

We can gauge the extent of Steiner’s rejection of the Kantian formulation of a concept of freedom from his parodying rejoinder to Kant in The Philosophy of Freedom:

Kant says, Duty! You exalted, mighty name, you who contain nothing lovable, nothing ingratiatingly agreeable, but who demand submission, (you who) establish a law ... before which all inclinations fall dumb, though in secret they might work against it! To this, a human being, out of the consciousness of the free spirit, replies: Freedom! You friendly, human name, you who contain everything morally beloved, everything that most dignifies my humanity, and who make me into no-one’s servant, you who do not merely establish a law, but wait for what my moral love itself will recognize as law, because it feels unfree in the face of every merely imposed law!33

In juxtaposing duty and freedom in this way Steiner is able to avoid the difficulties Kant faces in interpreting freedom as a function of duty, but he exposes himself to the much greater practical problem of distinguishing between the exercise of freedom, when it is determined by moral love and when it is merely the expression of wilfulness, desire and self-gratification.

In view of the form in which Kant structures his moral law it may seem puzzling at first that he should describe freedom in the Second Critique as the keystone of the whole architecture

of the system of pure reason and even of speculative reason. Kant’s description of freedom as the keystone is, however, very apt once we recognize that the driving force of the critical philosophy is to establish a ground for the justification of metaphysical judgments about God, human freedom and immortality of the soul. Of these three purported sources of metaphysical knowledge, freedom is the most accessible. If, through the critical philosophy, Kant can establish the reality of human freedom, he is on the way to a constitutive, rather than a merely regulative, system of metaphysics. In this sense, then, Kant’s epistemological project is like Steiner’s, in that cognition is seen to be the underpinning for a philosophy of freedom. The difference between Kant and Steiner lies in the means by which freedom is sought to be derived from the theory of knowledge, and the implications which can be drawn from that derivation.

Although Kant discusses freedom as a possibility in the First Critique and in the Groundwork, it is not until the Second Critique that he proposes the actuality of freedom. In the Preface to the Second Critique, as we have seen, Kant claims that there really is freedom, for this Idea is revealed by the moral law.34 That is, while speculative reason allows us to think freedom, but not to know it, practical reason allows us to know that there actually is freedom. We know there really is freedom because freedom is an essential element of the moral law, and we have immediate experience of the moral law. Kant is mindful of the apparent circularity of his argument, and explains in a footnote:

34 C Pr R, p. 4.

To avoid having anyone imagine that there is an inconsistency when I say that freedom is the condition of the moral law and later assert that the moral law is the

Page 8 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt only condition under which freedom can be known, I will only remind the reader that, though freedom is certainly the ratio essendi of the moral law, the latter is the ratio

cognoscendi of freedom. For had not the moral law already been distinctly thought in our reason, we would never have been justified in assuming anything like freedom, even though it is not self-contradictory. But if there were no freedom, the moral law would never have been encountered in us.35

35 Loc. cit.

36 Ibid, p. 169: Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing wonder and awe, the oftener and the more steadily we reflect on them: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me. I do not merely conjecture them and seek them as though obscured in darkness or in the transcendent region beyond my horizon: I see them before me, and I associate them directly with the consciousness of my own existence.

37 Ibid, pp 28-30: The first formulation, the Fundamental Law of Pure Practical Reason, So act that the maxim of your will could always hold at the same time as the principle giving universal law, indicates that freedom for Kant does not mean freedom of action in any absolute sense, but freedom to act in accordance with the universal moral law.

From this it appears that there are three separable steps in Kant’s derivation of freedom, which takes the form of a syllogism. The first step is the distinct thought of the existence of the moral law. Kant appears to be saying that, because we can think of the existence of a moral law if there is freedom of the will, then there must be a moral law if it can be shown that there is freedom. The second step is the assertion of the logical possibility of the idea of freedom, which is established in the Third Antinomy of the First Critique as being not self-contradictory, and therefore possible as a practical reality. The third step is the conclusion that there must in fact be freedom, because we encounter the moral law within ourselves. Kant’s derivation of freedom, then, appears to depend upon accepting the moral law within as an unassailable fact of the human condition.36 Kant will not, however, grant our recognition of the moral law the status of an intellectual intuition, though it might seem that there could hardly be a better way one could describe it.

As Kant’s derivation of freedom depends upon the existence of the moral law, the form the moral law takes will tell us something about what Kant means by freedom. Kant deals with the relationship between the will, the moral law and freedom in the sections of the Second Critique leading to the first formulation of the categorical imperative.37 In these sections

Kant argues that the will can only be determined by a law, which is not a law of nature, and to that extent, at least, it must be independent, and therefore free. He then asks what kind of law would be required to ground an independent and free will, and concludes that it must be the mere legislative form of the law.38 As a result, therefore, freedom and unconditional practical law reciprocally imply each other39 and and it is the moral law which leads directly to the concept of freedom.40 In other words, the kind of freedom, which can be

Page 9 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt derived from the moral law, will be nothing more than the regulative idea of a freedom to comply with the moral law.

38 Ibid, p. 28: Now, as no determining ground of the will except the universal legislative form [of its maxim] can serve as a law for it, such a will must be conceived as wholly independent of the natural law of appearances in their mutual relations, i.e. the law of causality. Such independence is called freedom in the strictest, i.e. transcendental, sense. Therefore, a will to which only the law-giving form of the maxim can serve as a law is a free will.

39 Ibid, p. 29.

40 Loc. cit.

41 Ibid, p. 31.

Kant’s derivation of freedom and the form it takes is also prescribed, to some extent, by his determination that we do not possess a faculty for intellectual intuition. In discussing the relationship between law and will Kant comments that the will’s independence of empirical conditions is remarkable and unique.41 He then considers the derivation of the principle of a law, and observes:

... it is at least not impossible to conceive of a law that alone serves the purpose of the subjective form of principles and yet is a ground of determination by virtue of the objective form of a law in general. The consciousness of this fundamental law may be called a fact of reason, since one cannot ferret it out from antecedent data of reason, such as the consciousness of freedom (for this is not antecedently given), and since it forces itself upon us as a synthetic proposition a priori based on no pure or empirical intuition. It would be analytic if the freedom of the will were presupposed, but for this, as a positive concept, an intellectual intuition would be needed, and here we cannot assume it. In order to regard this law without any misinterpretation as

given, one must note that it is not an empirical fact but the sole fact of pure reason, which by it proclaims itself as originating law.42

42 Ibid, pp 31-32.

43Steiner suggested that the English translation of Freiheit be spiritual activity. The American edition avoids the problem by changing the title entirely to Intuitive thinking as a spiritual path.

44Steiner gives the title Conscious Human Action to the first chapter of Philosophy of Freedom and commences his argument with: Is a human being spiritually free, or subject to the iron necessity of purely natural law? Ph F [1], ITSP, p. 5.

45The title page of the original edition of Wahrheit und Wissenschaft describes the work as Vorspiel einer Philosophie der Freiheit [Prelude to a Philosophy of Freedom], TK, p. 2.

Because he denies that intellectual intuition is available to human consciousness Kant must

Page 10 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt argue for consciousness of the moral law as the sole fact of pure reason. Had Kant, like Fichte, Schelling and Steiner, incorporated intellectual intuition into his conception of cognition, he would not need to have seen consciousness of the moral law as the sole fact of pure reason, but could have understood it as an instance of intellectual intuition.

3. Steiner’s concepts of thinking and freedom

Because there is such a degree of interdependence between Steiner’s concepts of thinking and freedom, they will to a considerable extent be dealt with together. Steiner’s epistemological project is to proceed from intellectual intuition to intuitive thinking, in the course of which he identifies intuitive thinking with freedom. Steiner has an idiosyncratic notion of freedom, which has resulted in the freedom of the title of Philosophy of Freedom being substituted at times with spiritual activity or intuitive thinking.43 Freedom, in Steiner’s sense, is nothing to do with the exercise of rights, but everything to do with the conscious and moral exercise of the will.44

Although Steiner’s account of freedom is contained substantially in Philosophy of Freedom, it is anticipated to some extent in Truth and Knowledge.45 In the Preface to Truth and Knowledge Steiner indicates already that freedom will be at the centre of his argument. His

analysis of cognition leads him to conclude that ... truth is not, as is usually assumed, an ideal reflection of something real, but is a product of the human spirit, created by an activity which is free; ... 46 Similarly, our deeds or moral ideals ... are to be considered not as copies of something existing outside us, but as being present solely within us,47 and as a result ... the insight that truth is the outcome of a free deed also establishes a philosophy of morality, the foundation of which is the completely free personality.48 The impression Steiner creates in the Preface to Truth and Knowledge is that his agenda, like Kant’s and Fichte’s, is to provide the epistemological ground for the establishment of moral freedom. Although the focus is on intellectual intuition in Truth and Knowledge this impression is reinforced by its Practical Conclusion. The Practical Conclusion claims that moral freedom has been demonstrated by the fact of cognitive freedom, and that awareness of moral freedom is itself the essence of the free personality alluded to in the Preface.49 In fact, however, Steiner’s purpose is not to embark upon an epistemological enquiry merely to ground an ethical position. Steiner is critical of Fichte for doing just this; in contrast Steiner’s project is both ontological and epistemological, and he is committed to finding a way of demonstrating that human beings have access to knowledge of essences.50

46 Ibid, p. 11.

47 Ibid, p. 12.

48 Loc. cit.

49Ibid, pp 94-95: To carry out a deed under the influence of a law external to the person who brings the deed to realization, is a deed done in unfreedom. To carry out a deed ruled by a law that lies within the one who brings it about, is a deed done in freedom. To recognize the laws of one’s deeds, means to become conscious of one’s

Page 11 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt own freedom. Thus the process of knowledge is the process of development toward freedom.

50Ibid, p. 77: But if epistemology is to be the foundation of all knowledge, the decisive point is not to have a definition of an I that is free, but of an I that cognizes. Fichte has allowed himself to be too much influenced by his subjective inclinations to present the freedom of the human personality in the clearest possible light. Harms, in his address, On the Philosophy of Fichte, (p15) rightly says: His world-view is predominantly and exclusively ethical, and his theory of knowledge has no other feature.

The account Steiner gives of cognition and thinking in Truth and Knowledge is already bound together with the account he is developing of freedom. Having claimed to have shown that the given world-picture becomes complete only through that other, indirect kind of given which is brought to it by thinking51, Steiner isolates the idea of knowledge as the one element of consciousness, which does not arise from the activity of thinking - the separating and re-uniting of the given world and the world of ideas and concepts - and says:

51 Ibid, p. 70.

52 Ibid, p. 73.

53 Ibid, p. 74.

54 Loc. cit: I believe I have now cleared the ground sufficiently to enable us to understand Fichte’s Science of Knowledge through recognition of the fundamental mistake contained in it.

We have now defined the idea of knowledge. In the act of cognition this idea is directly given in human consciousness. Both outer and inner perceptions, as well as its own presence are given directly to the I, which is the centre of consciousness. ... In contrast to the given world, a second world – the world of thinking – rises up to meet the I, and the I unites the two through its own free decision, producing what we have defined as the idea of knowledge.52

Freedom, then, is a capacity of the I’, the centre of consciousness, to exercise its own free decision to produce the idea of knowledge. Indeed, consciousness has no choice but to exercise this freedom, for:

All other categories (ideas), whether or not they are grasped in cognition, are necessarily united with their corresponding forms of the given. But the idea of consciousness can be united with its corresponding given only by the activity of consciousness. Consciousness as a reality exists only if it produces itself.53

In other words, there is a necessary freedom in conscious activity. Steiner develops this insight into a critique of the difficulties Fichte encounters in the Wissenschaftslehre.54 By the end of Truth and Knowledge it is clear that Steiner’s promised philosophy of freedom will be an argument for freedom of the will grounded upon the freedom exercised in the kind of thinking, which is generated by intellectual intuition.

Page 12 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt In Philosophy of Freedom Steiner builds his argument for intuitive thinking upon a critique of the activity of thinking and the identification of that activity as the source of all human moral action. In the first chapter, Conscious Human Action, he argues that the question of whether or not there is freedom of the will first requires an answer to question of whether there is a difference between a conscious motive and an unconscious drive, that is, what does it mean to have knowledge of the motives of one’s actions?55 If the question of human freedom is really a question about consciousness of human action it then becomes a question about the nature of thinking, for what distinguishes humans from all other organic beings rests on rational thinking.56 This leads Steiner to embark upon an enquiry into the origin and significance of thinking.57 In the next chapter, The Fundamental Urge for Knowledge, Steiner moves his focus to the question of knowledge and presents the pursuit of knowledge as an instance of existential angst.58 We demand explanations for what we observe and find ourselves setting up a barrier between ourselves and the world. Indeed, according to Steiner, our cultural history is the story of attempting to overcome this barrier.59 Scientists and thinkers do this by striving to penetrate in thinking what they experience through observation.60 Steiner observes that all dualistic and monistic world views are attempts to

55 Ph F, Ch 1 [8]-[9], ITSP, p. 12.

56 Ibid, Ch 1[15], ITSP, p. 14: this claim reflects Steiner’s historical context. Most lovers of animals today would argue that many of the higher animals demonstrate a capacity for rational thinking.

57 Ibid, Ch 1[17], ITSP, pp 15-16: Obviously, my action cannot be free if I, as the actor, do not know why I carry it out. But what about an action for which the reasons are known? This leads us to ask: what is the origin and significance of thinking? For without understanding the soul’s activity of thinking, no concept of the knowledge of anything is possible. When we understand what thinking means in general, it will be easy to clarify the role that thinking plays in human action.

58 Ibid, Ch 2 [1], ITSP, p. 18: We seem born for dissatisfaction. The urge to know is only a special case of this dissatisfaction.

59 Ph F, Ch 2 [4], ITSP p. 19: This feeling [that we are creatures not outside but within the universe] engenders an effort to bridge the opposition. And, in the final analysis, the whole spiritual striving of humankind consists in bridging this opposition. The history of spiritual life is a continual searching for the unity between the I and the world. Religion, art and science share this as their goal.

60 Ph F, Ch 2 [4], ITSP, p. 20.

reconcile I and the world. This will only be possible, however, if we descend into the depths of our own being, to find there those elements that we have saved in our flight out of nature.61 Those elements will have to do with the activity of thinking.62

61 Ph F, Ch 2 [12], ITSP, p. 26.

62Ph F, Ch 2 [4], ITSP p. 20: Only when we have made the world content into our thought content do we rediscover the connection from which we have sundered ourselves.

Page 13 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt

63 Ph F, Ch 3 [4], ITSP, pp 29-30: Insofar as we are conscious of it, observation and thinking are the two points of departure for all human spiritual striving. The workings of both common human understanding and the most complicated scientific investigations rest on these two pillars of our spirit. For Kant the essentials of cognition are sensibility and understanding: CPR, A19, B33 p. 65: Objects are given to us by means of sensibility, and it alone yields us intuitions; they are thought through the understanding, and from the understanding arise concepts.

64 Ph F, Ch 2 [7], ITSP p. 31: Chronologically, observation even precedes thinking. For we can become aware of thinking, too, only through observation. For Kant thinking precedes observation: CPR B xiii, p20: Accidental observations, made in obedience to no previously thought-out plan, can never be made to yield a necessary law, which alone reason is concerned to discover.

65 Ph F, Ch 2 [3], ITSP p. 29: Mere observation can follow the parts of a given event in succession, but their connection remains obscure until concepts are brought in to help.

66 loc cit

67 CPR, A20, B34 p. 65: The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far as we are affected by it, is sensation.

In Chapter 3 of Philosophy of Freedom, Thinking in the Service of Understanding the World, Steiner argues that observation and thinking are the essentials of cognition.63 Observation precedes thinking,64 but thinking is required for knowledge to arise.65 Steiner does not explain what he means by observation. He distinguishes between mere observation and observations which follow the addition of concepts,66 but does not say whether mere observation might be equated with Kant’s notion of sensation or the representation of a sensation.67 He also does not say whether by observation he means something to the effect of thought-directed seeing, or whether he is attempting to exclude the activity of thinking from his concept of observation. This is unfortunate, because Steiner next embarks upon an extended discussion of the observation of thinking. He first notes that ... when we observe thinking, we are applying to thinking a procedure that is normal when we consider all the rest

of our world-content but that is not normally applied to thinking.68 Steiner emphasises that the observation of thinking is an exceptional state, for in it we externalise and observe something we have ourselves created, namely the ideas and concepts we attach to our observations. At all other times [thinking] is the unobserved element in our normal spiritual life.69

68 Ph F, Ch 3 [8], ISTP pp 31-32.

69 Ph F, Ch 3 [12], ITSP p. 33.

Page 14 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt

70 Ph F, Ch 3 [14], ITSP p. 34.

71 Ph F, Ch 3 [15], ITSP p. 34.

72 Ph F, Ch 3 [16], ITSP pp 34-35.

73 Ph F, Ch 3 [17], ITSP p. 35.

74 The original does not assist: Ph F, Ch 3 [17], p. 37: Diese durchsichtige Klarheit in bezug auf den Denkprozeß ist ganz unabhängig von unserer Kenntnis der physiologischen Grundlagen des Denkens.

In his discussion of the observation of thinking Steiner notes that I can never observe my present thinking; only after I have thought can I take the experiences I have had during my thinking process as the object of my thinking.70 As a result these two are therefore incompatible: active production and contemplative confrontation.71 When it comes to the contemplative confrontation of thinking:72

It is impossible for us to observe thinking as it occurs at each moment for the same reason that we can know our thinking more immediately and intimately than any other process in the world. Precisely because we ourselves produce our thinking, we know the characteristics of its course and how it occurs. What can be found only indirectly in other spheres of observation – the appropriate connections and the relationship of individual objects – we know in a completely immediate way in thinking.

Our completely immediate knowledge of our own thinking is accompanied by the transparent clarity we experience in relation to the thinking process.73 Steiner does not say whether, in referring to the transparent clarity of the thinking process he is reminding us that thinking is imperceptible as the unobserved element in our normal spiritual life, or whether he means just the opposite – that thinking is observable with transparent clarity.74 If

he means the former he is describing something similar to Kant’s depiction of the I think as the pure apperception, which unifies all representations.75 It seems however, as one reads on, that Steiner means the latter and that his interest is in constructing an account of thinking as an observable phenomenon.

75 CPR, B132 p. 153: That representation which can be given prior to all thought is entitled intuition. All the manifold of intuition has, therefore, a necessary relation to the I think’ n the same subject in which this manifold is found. But this representation is an act of spontaneity, that is, it cannot be regarded as belonging to sensibility. I call it pure apperception, to distinguish it from empirical apperception, or, again, original apperception, because it is that self-consciousness which, while generating the representation I think’ ... cannot itself be accompanied by any further representation.

76 Ph F, Ch 3 [18], p. 37.

77 Ph F, Ch 3 [19], p. 37.

Page 15 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt 78 Loc. cit.

79 Ph F, Ch 3 [19], pp 37-38: What the tacked-on therefore I am might mean has been much disputed.

80 Ph F, Ch 3 [19], p. 38.

Steiner takes the observation of thinking to be the starting point of his search for knowledge of essences. For Steiner the observation of thinking is the most important observation that can be made76. This is because:77

We find ourselves facing something that to begin with is not foreign to us, but our own activity. We know how the thing we are observing comes about. We see through the relationships and the connections. A secure point has been won, from which we can reasonably hope to seek an explanation of the other world phenomena.

Steiner reads Descartes’ cogito to be making the same point, and that (Descartes) could only claim that, in thinking, I lay hold of myself in the activity that is, of all the world’s content, the most my own.78 Steiner construes Descartes’ enquiry to be essentially epistemological,79 but claims to have found firm ground in an object the meaning of whose existence I can draw out of myself.80 That firm ground, according to Steiner, is not thinking itself, but the observation of thinking. Steiner’s original insight, it might be said, is that it is the

observation of one’s own thinking activity, which lies at the core of all cognition.81 This is because it is in the observation of thinking, according to Steiner, that we realise we have the capacity to create, and it is that capacity which will ultimately constitute our freedom.82 It is also in the observation of thinking that we hold a corner of the world process,83 for we can presume to understand how we create with our thinking. For us to observe our thinking we have to have been thinking, and this is why, for the contemplation of the whole world- process, there is no more primal starting point than thinking.84

81Loc. cit: As a thinker, I am myself such an object. I endow my existence with the definite, self-reposing content of thinking activity. From there, I can now proceed to ask whether other things exist in the same or in a different sense.

82 Ph F, Ch3 [23], ITSP, p. 40: What is impossible with nature – creation before cognition – we achieve with thinking. If we waited, before thinking, until we already understood it, then we would never get to that point. We must think resolutely ahead, in order later to arrive by observation at a knowledge of what we have done. We ourselves create the object for the observation of thinking.

83 Ph F, Ch3 [25], ITSP, p. 41.

84 Loc. cit.

85 Ph F, Ch3 [29], ITSP, pp42-43: I believe I have now justified beginning my consideration of the world with thinking. When Archimedes had invented the lever, he thought he could use it to lift the whole cosmos on its hinges, if only he could find a secure point to set his instrument. For this, he needed something supported by itself, not by something else.

Page 16 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt 86 Loc. cit.

87 Ph F, Ch3 [30], ITSP, p. 43.

Having found firm ground in the observation of thinking Steiner returns to thinking itself as the starting point for cognition. Steiner compares thinking with the secure point of Archimedes’ lever,85 for in thinking we have a principle that exits through itself.86 Indeed, thinking holds such primacy for Steiner that for him it must precede consciousness. This seems to be a very peculiar position for him to adopt, particularly in light of the extent to which, in Truth and Knowledge, he relies upon Fichte’s derivation of the activity of intellectual intuition from a critique of self-consciousness. Steiner argues:87

Most contemporary philosophers would object that there has to be a consciousness before there can be thinking. According to them, we should therefore proceed from

consciousness and not from thinking since there would be no thinking without consciousness. To this I would have to reply that, if I want to understand the relationship between thinking and consciousness, I must think about it. Therefore I presuppose thinking.

He explains that he is not claiming thinking was created before consciousness, but rather that understanding the world requires thinking before it requires consciousness.88 Similarly, thinking precedes the division into subject and object, and must be considered completely neutrally, without reference to a thinking subject or a thought object. For in subject and object we already have concepts that are formed through thinking.89 Steiner is emphatic that before anything else can be understood, thinking must be understood.90

88 Loc. cit: Naturally, the creator could not let thinking arise without first having consciousness come about. For philosophers, however, it is not a question of creating the world but of understanding it. Hence they do not need a starting point for creating the world, but rather one for understanding it.

89 Ph F, Ch 3 [31], ITSP, p. 44, and Ch 4 [1], ITSP, p. 50: Concepts and ideas already presuppose thinking.

90 Loc. cit.

91 Ph F, Ch 4 [6], ITSP, p. 52.

92 Loc. cit.

93 Loc. cit.

94 Loc. cit.

In Chapter 4 of Philosophy of Freedom Steiner moves from a critique of thinking to the relationship between the activity of thinking and the thinker for it is through the thinker that

Page 17 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt thinking is linked to observation.91 This linking takes place in consciousness, which is the stage where concept and observation meet92 and which operates as the mediator between thinking and observation.93 It is apparent that Steiner has now moved well away from Fichte’s depiction of the genesis of thinking in the positing activity of consciousness, for he inverts Fichte’s derivation of thinking as arising from self-consciousness and predicates self- consciousness upon thinking. For Steiner Human consciousness must necessarily at the same time also be self-consciousness, because it is a thinking consciousness.94 It is also

apparent that Steiner is moving towards a characterisation of thinking as an entity independent of the thinker. Human consciousness is self-consciousness, he explains, for when thinking directs its gaze toward its own activity, it has before it as its object its very own being, that is, its subject.95 Steiner reminds us that thinking is beyond subject and object96 and depicts the relationship between thinking and thinker, as he understands it, from the perspective of thinking when he says:97

95 Loc. cit.

96 Ph F, Ch 4 [7], ITSP, p. 52.

97 Loc. cit, this writer’s emphasis

98 Ph F, Ch 5 [10] pp 79-80.

Thus, when we as thinking subjects relate a concept to an object, we must not regard this relationship as something merely subjective. It is not the subject that introduces the relationship, but thinking. The subject does not think because it is a subject; rather, it appears to itself as a subject because it can think. The activity that human beings exercise as thinking beings is therefore not merely subjective, but it is a kind of activity that is neither subjective nor objective; it goes beyond both these concepts. I should never say that my individual subject thinks; rather, it lives by the grace of thinking. Thus, thinking is an element that leads me beyond myself and unites me with objects. But it separates me from them at the same time, by setting me over against them as subject.

It will be remembered that, in his Goethe studies, Steiner sought to demonstrate that thinking is a sense organ. The central plank of Steiner’s epistemology is still thinking, but now thinking is an element that leads me beyond myself .... The activity of thinking itself has now separated out from its role as an activity of the thinker.

4. Intuitive thinking

In Chapter 5 of Philosophy of Freedom Steiner extends his depiction of thinking by drawing analogies with natural phenomena. He appears to be calling upon what he has taken from Goethe’s approach to science when he imagines responding to a naive realist by asking:98

By what right do you declare the world to be finished without thinking? Does not the world bring forth thinking in human heads with the same necessity as it brings forth blossoms on the plant? Plant a seed in the earth. It puts forth roots and stem. It

Page 18 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt unfolds into leaves and blossoms. Set the plant before you. It links itself to a specific concept in your soul. Why does this concept belong to the plant any less than the leaves and blossoms do? You might reply that leaves and blossoms are present without a perceiving subject, while the concept appears only when a human being confronts the plant. Very well. But blossoms and leaves arise in the plant only when there is earth in which the seed can be laid and light and air in which leaves and blossoms can unfold. Just so, the concept of the plant arises when thinking consciousness approaches the plant.

Until this point, and although he appears to have a questionable view of the relationship between thinking and consciousness, Steiner has restricted himself to the demands of rational argument. He is now moving to a pictorial, imaginative way of endeavouring to demonstrate the primacy of thinking, by claiming that it is thinking which will deliver knowledge of essences, of the totality of the objects of sense perception. If thinking unites percept and concept, and if the concept is as much a part of the object as the percept, then, Steiner seems to be saying, there could no longer be any need to postulate a world of unknowable things-in- themselves. The activity of thinking overcomes dualism, and it is through the observation of the activity of thinking that it possible to claim that there are no limits to knowledge. The argument is attractive, but it comes at a cost. The cost for Steiner is that he is likely to be subject to the scholarly and academic criticism, which is so often made against his later works, that what he is offering is more akin to self-referential phantasy than a contribution to credible intellectual discourse.

Steiner gives another two examples from the observation of nature to demonstrate his claim that it is quite arbitrary to consider as a totality, a whole, the sum of what we experience of a thing through perception alone, and to regard what results from a thinking contemplation as

something appended, that has nothing to do with the thing itself.99 One is a version of Zeno’s paradox.100 The other is a further instance from the observation of plant life, which brings to mind both Goethe’s anschauende Urteilskraft [intuitive judgment] and Kant’s accounts of intuitive understanding in the Third Critique as ways of addressing the cognition of organic nature. Steiner says:101

99 Ph F, Ch 5 [11], p. 80.

100 Ph F, Ch 5 [14], ITSP p. 81: When I throw a stone through the air horizontally, I see it in different places in succession. …

101 Ph F, Ch 5 [11] –[12], ITSP p. 80, this writer’s emphasis

102 Ph F, Ch 5 [16], ITSP, p. 82.

If I am given a rosebud today, then the picture that offers itself to my perception is limited to the present moment. But if I put the bud in water, then I will get a completely different picture of my object tomorrow. And if I can keep my eyes turned toward the rosebud, then I shall see today’s state of change continuously into tomorrow’s through countless intermediate stages. The picture offering itself to me in a specific moment is but an accidental cross-section of an object that is caught up in a

Page 19 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt continual process of becoming. If I do not put the bud in water, then it will fail to develop a whole series of states lying within it as possibilities. And tomorrow I might be prevented from observing the blossom further, and so form an incomplete picture of it.

It is completely unrealistic to grasp as accidental elements and to declare, of the picture revealed at a particular time: that is the thing.

It will be apparent that Steiner is no longer talking about the process of knowing a specific moment of the given world, the accidental cross-section of an object. His focus, along with his characterisation of the activity of thinking, has moved to a broader canvas, and has become separated off from the consciousness of the thinking observer. As a consequence Steiner can say:102

How I am organized to comprehend things has nothing to do with their nature. The divide between perceiving and thinking comes into being only at the instant that I, the observer, come over against things. Yet which elements belong to the thing, and which do not, can in no way depend upon how I come to know those elements.

In other words, what we regard as subjective – the ideas and concepts contributed by our thinking – are no less a part of the thing than what appear to us to be the objective, sense- perceptible phenomena.

Steiner completes his characterisation of thinking with expressions which indicate that, for him, thinking is the unifying force of the cosmos. The fact that there is only one concept of triangle demonstrates to Steiner that the thinking of many thinkers is itself a unity.103 But it is the activity of thinking itself, which produces that unity, for:104

103 Ph F, Ch 5 [18]-[19], ITSP pp 83-84.

104 Ph F, Ch 5 [20], ITSP, p. 84.

105 Loc. cit.

106 Ph F, Ch 5 [21], ITSP, p. 84.

In thinking, we are given the element that unites our particular individuality with the whole of the cosmos. When we sense, feel (and also perceive) we are separate; when we think, we are the all-one being that penetrates all. This is the deeper basis of our dual nature. Within us, we see an absolute force coming into existence, a force that is universal. Yet we do not come to know it as it streams forth from the centre of the world, but only at a point on the periphery. If we came to know it as it streamed forth from the centre of the world, then we would know the whole riddle of the world at the instant we came to consciousness.

It is because we stand at a point on the periphery that we must find out about the realm situated outside our own being with the help of thinking that extends into us from universal world existence.105 Steiner’s focus has moved away from epistemology as a critique of the powers of human cognition to its forming the ground for a phenomenology of thinking. He

Page 20 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt therefore now addresses cognition from the perspective of thinking, and says the urge for knowledge arises in us because thinking in us reaches out beyond our separateness and relates itself to universal world existence.106 That is, thinking itself is the active element in Steiner’s picture of the cosmos, and individual thinkers are the means for its self-expression.

It is at this point that Steiner introduces the concept of intuition [Intuition]. He has returned to the role of thinking in unifying percept and concept in the act of cognition, and says:

In contrast to perceptual content, which is given us from without, thought-content appears within. We shall call the form in which thought-content first arises intuition. Intuition is to thinking as observation is to perception. Intuition and observation are the sources of our knowledge. We remain alienated from an object we have observed in the world as long as we do not have within us the corresponding intuition, which supplies us with the piece of reality missing from the percept.107

107 Ph F, Ch 5 [25] p. 80: Im Gegensatz zum Wahrnehmungsinhalte, der uns von außen gegeben ist, erscheint der Gedankeninhalt im Innern. Die Form, in der er zunächst auftritt, wollen wir als Intuition bezeichnen. Sie is für das Denken, was die Beobachtung für die Wahrnehmung ist. Intuition und Beobachtung sind die Quellen unserer Erkenntnis. Wir stehen einem beobachteten Dinge der Welt so lange fremd gegenüber, so lange wir in unserem Innern nicht die entsprechende Intuition haben, die uns das in der Wahrnehmng fehlende Stück der Wirklichkeit ergänzt. ITSP p88

108Ph F, Ch 2 [14] ITSP p. 26: ... I attach no value to using the individual expressions, such as I, spirit, world, nature, and so forth, in the precise way that is usual in psychology and philosophy.

Intuition has been introduced in this one paragraph to refer to four things at once, namely the form in which thought-content first arises, to an enhanced state of thinking, as the source of our knowledge from within and to an individualised concept (the piece of reality missing from the percept). It is difficult to know what Steiner intends by using the term intuition in these many ways, unless it is to give the impression of the range of overlapping meanings of intuition. He certainly acknowledges employing other terms in Philosophy of Freedom without precision.108 But if Steiner is to argue for intuition in some form we need to know what he means. In describing intuition as the form in which thought-content first arises Steiner seems to be implying that intuition, as intellectual intuition, is the ground of ideas and concepts, in much the same way as the sensory intuitions of space and time are the grounds of what is given us from without. When he then says, however, intuition is to thinking as observation is to perception Steiner would appear to be claiming that intuition is an enhanced form of thinking, in much the same way as observation is an enhanced, thought-

filled or thinking form of perception. Yet if this is so Steiner’s argument would seem to run counter to his clear statements in Chapter 3 of Philosophy of Freedom that any observation of one’s own thinking can only take place after the thinking.109 And if intuition is active, and is as to thinking as observation is to perception it cannot also amount to the impliedly passive form in which thought-content first arises.

Page 21 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt 109See fn. 72.

110Steiner subsequently also identifies intuitions with mental pictures: Ph F, Ch 6 [4] ITSP, p. 99: A mental picture is nothing but an intuition related to a specific percept. It is a concept, once linked to a percept, for which the relation to that percept has remained.

111Ph F, Ch 5 [26] ITSP, p. 89: ... What meets us in observation as separate details is linked, item by item, through the coherent, unitary world of our intuitions.

Steiner’s third statement about intuition is that intuition and observation are the sources of our knowledge. If observation is a source of our knowledge it must be that Steiner is referring to the point in the cognitive process at which perception has been grasped by the activity of thinking to become observation. Likewise, if intuition is to be seen as the source of our conceptual knowledge Steiner must mean that concepts have been grasped by thinking to become intuition. Finally, if intuition supplies us with the piece of reality missing from the percept it must be that it is intuition, which creates or delivers the concept to marry up with the percept.110 In the following paragraph, however, Steiner elaborates what he means by the corresponding intuition, and it becomes clear that he is also identifying intuitions with individualised concepts.111 Relating intuition to thinking, what we now have is intuition as the ground of thinking (in the form of intellectual intuition), intuition as an enhanced form of thinking, intuition as concepts grasped by thinking and intuition as individualised concepts. What Steiner appears to be doing (though he does not specifically say so) is to weave a thread of intuition into each of the ways in which he has described thinking. What

is being suggested it seems, is that what Steiner will later call intuitive thinking, rather like Fichte’s an activity in which an eye is inserted, is an enhanced form of thinking, which enables the knower, in the act of knowing, to observe the activity of thinking and in so doing to come to a knowledge of essences.112

112 Steiner implies that this ability may not be universal: Ph F, Ch 6 [7] ITSP, p. 100: The sum of everything of which I can form mental pictures I can call my experience. Hence, the greater the number of individualized concepts a person has, the richer their experience will be. A person lacking intuitive capacity, on the other hand, is unsuited to acquire experience. For such a person, once objects are out of sight they are lost, because the concepts that ought to be brought into relationship with them are lacking.

113 Ph F, Ch 9 [2] p. 121; ITSP, p. 135.

114It will be remembered that Steiner had earlier declared, Ph F, Ch 3 [14], ITSP p. 34: I can never observe my present thinking.

115 Ph F, Ch 9 [2], ITSP, p. 136.

This interpretation of what Steiner means by intuition seems to be borne out by his most developed discussion of intuition in the original text of Philosophy of Freedom, which appears in Chapter 9, The Idea of Freedom. In Chapter 9 Steiner at last brings together what he has had to say about intuition and thinking with his starting point, namely his enquiry into

Page 22 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt freedom. In doing so, however, he makes a statement at the outset which appears to contradict his critique of the observation of thinking in Chapter 3. He says:113

In the preceding discussion, an attempt was made to show that it is possible to clarify this relationship [between percept and concept] through unprejudiced observation. A proper understanding of such observation leads to the insight that thinking can be beheld directly [unmittelbar] as a self-enclosed entity.

There is no mistaking what Steiner is now claiming, for the text is clearly arguing that thinking can be beheld immediately as a self-enclosed entity.114 Steiner extrapolates from this cause for concern to another troubling claim when he then declares that:115

To observe thinking is to live, during the observation, immediately within the weaving of a self-supporting spiritual entity. We could even say that whoever wants to grasp the essence of the spirit in the form in which it first presents itself to human beings can do so in the self-sustaining activity of thinking.

Steiner appears to be conflating the self-sustaining activity of thinking with observation of the activity of thinking, and contradicting a distinction between the two that he was careful to make in Chapter 3.116

116See the discussion above, and summarized at Ph F, Ch 3 [15], ITSP, p. 34: These two are therefore incompatible: active production and contemplative confrontation.

117 Ph F Ch 9, [3] ITSP, pp 136-137.

118 Ph F Ch 9, [4] ITSP, p. 137.

Steiner has changed his position in regard to thinking and the observation of thinking, because he has a specific explanation in mind for how it is that intuition leads to knowledge of essences. Misunderstanding the nature of concept and percept can lead us to the construction of a hypothetical metaphysical world, he says:117

But, if we see what is really present in thinking, we will recognise that only one part of reality is present in the percept and that we experience the other part – which belongs to it and is necessary for it to appear as full reality – in the permeation of the percept by thinking. We shall then see, in what appears in consciousness as thinking, not a shadowy copy of reality, but a spiritual essence that sustains itself. Of this spiritual essence we can say that it becomes present to our consciousness through intuition. Intuition is the conscious experience, within what is purely spiritual, of a purely spiritual content. The essence of thinking can be grasped only through intuition.

What Steiner appears to be claiming is that a concept is not so much an individualised idea as something, which we experience ... in the permeation of the percept by thinking. A concept for Steiner, therefore, is not a shadowy copy of reality (as he appears to understand it to be for a transcendental idealist) – it is reality: it is a spiritual essence that sustains itself. And it is through intuition that we know this to be the case, for intuition is the conscious experience, within what is purely spiritual, of a purely spiritual content. It

Page 23 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt follows, then, that the essence of thinking can be grasped only through intuition. Steiner has succeeded in attaching what he now describes as the intuitive essence of thinking118 to

knowledge of essences, but it is at the cost of the credibility of his argument. Concepts are now experiences rather than the products of the thinking activity of the individual thinker,119 and the simultaneous observation of one’s own thinking has moved from being impossible to becoming central to Steiner’s critique of intuition. From this point on it could not be claimed that Steiner has argued from intuition to knowledge of essences.

119Ph F, Ch 4 [1] ITSP, p. 49: Concepts and ideas arise through thinking. … When the object disappears from our field of observation, only the conceptual counterpart remains. The latter is the concept of the object.

120Ph F, Ch 9 [14] ITSP, p. 143: If we act under the influence of intuitions, then the motive power of our actions is pure thinking. Despite his rejection of deontological ethics Steiner retains Kant’s terminology by equating pure thinking with reason and then adding: Since it is customary in philosophy to designate the capacity for pure thinking as reason, we are fully justified in calling the moral driving force characteristic of this [highest] stage [of individual life] practical reason.

121 Ph F, FQ, Addendum [2], p. 241.

Steiner uses his formulation of intuition as the conscious experience, within what is purely spiritual, of a purely spiritual content as the springboard for the ethical argument, which occupies the larger part of the remainder of Philosophy of Freedom.120 The expression intuitive thinking does not itself appear in Philosophy of Freedom until the revised edition of 1918, in which Steiner alludes to it in a number of the Addenda. In the last of these, which was referred to at the conclusion to Part 2 Chapter 1, Steiner explains the argument of Philosophy of Freedom in terms of intuitive thinking, and says:121

The content of this book is built on intuitive thinking that can be experienced purely spiritually, and through which every percept is placed within reality during the act of cognition. No more was to be presented than can be surveyed from an experience of intuitive thinking. But we must also emphasize what kind of thought formation the experience of thinking demands. It demands that intuitive thinking not be denied as a self-sustaining experience within the process of cognition. It also demands that we acknowledge its capacity, in conjunction with percepts, to experience reality, instead of seeking reality only in an inferred world outside experience, in the face of which the human activity of thinking would be merely subjective.

Steiner subsequently relates his conviction that intuitive thinking has a capacity to experience reality to his later works on spiritual science.122 The difficulty remains that the adoption of such a point of view does demand that intuitive thinking not be denied as a self-sustaining experience within the process of cognition. That is not a demand which can be made of academic philosophy.

122Ph F, FQ [3] ITSP, p. 242: In this book an attempt is made to show that the experience of thinking, properly understood, is already an experience of spirit. Therefore, it seems to me that whoever can adopt the point of

Page 24 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt view of this book in earnest will not stop short of entering the world of spiritual perception.

123These writers include Michael Muschalle, who obtained a PhD from Bielefelt University in 2001 with a dissertation on Brentano, Das Denken und seine Beobachtung [Thinking and the observation of thinking]

124Ph F, FQ [3] ITSP, p. 242: As soon as we experience it, the spiritual perceptual world cannot be anything strange to us as human beings, because we already have in intuitive thinking an experience of a purely spiritual character. A number of my later writings discuss such a world of spiritual perception. This book, Philosophy of Freedom, is their philosophical foundation.

5. The observation debate

Steiner’s discussion of thinking and the observation of thinking in Chapter 3 of The Philosophy of Freedom, and the apparent contradiction of his position in Chapter 9, have become the subject of intense debate amongst philosophically-trained anthroposophists.123 Although the work of these writers is not being undertaken from within the academy it is felt that some mention should be made of it. The reason for the intense debate is that Steiner, throughout his later work, repeatedly refers to his derivation of intuitive thinking in Philosophy of Freedom as the epistemological ground of his anthroposophical spiritual science.124 The epistemological claim of spiritual science is that intuitive thinking can be further developed into sense-free pure thinking, from which it is then possible to attain the knowledge of higher worlds, which constitutes knowledge of essences. If Steiner’s arguments for intuitive thinking in Philosophy of Freedom are unconvincing as philosophy it

becomes difficult for anthroposophists to assert that the results of his spiritual research should qualify as knowledge, rather than as beliefs held merely on faith.

The observation debate is dealt with most comprehensively in Michael Muschalle’s Beobachtung des Denkens bei Rudolf Steiner.125 Muschalle focuses on Steiner’s Spaltungsargument [splitting argument]126 and the Beobachtungsaporie [pause in observation]127 it implies. The Beobachtungsaporie arises from Steiner’s claim that it is not possible to observe one’s own thinking in the process of thinking, but that it is possible to remember it as a self-created object of consciousness.128 Muschalle, not without good reason, characterises the observation of thinking as the most important factor in Steiner’s theory of knowledge.129 Steiner certainly says as much,130 and Muschalle reminds us that, for Steiner, thinking is the lever which enables us to take hold of the world. It is the one element in the world we can take hold of through itself.131

125Muschalle, M. (2007a) Beobachtung des Denkens bei Rudolf Steiner, Books on demand: online

126Ibid, p. 9.

127Ibid, p. 11.

128Ph F, Ch 3 [14] ITSP, p. 34.

129Muschalle, op. cit, p. 11: Wie wir wissen, ist für Steiner die Beobachtung des Denkens das gewichtigste

Page 25 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt erkenntnis= theoretische Faktum überhaupt.

130Ph F, Ch 3 [18] ITSP p. 37: But for everyone who has the capacity to observe thinking, and with good will, every normally constituted human being has this capacity - the observation of thinking is the most important observation that can be made.

131Muschalle, op. cit., p. 12.

132Ph F, Ch3 [15], ITSP p. 34: These two are therefore incompatible: active production and contemplative confrontation. The first book of Moses already recognizes this. In the Book of Genesis, God produces the world in the first six days of creation; only once it is there is it possible to contemplate it: And God looked at

It appears to be incontrovertible that Steiner rejects any suggestion of a splitting between the I’ which is thinking and the I’ which observes the thinking. Steiner says without qualification, and with an allusion to the creation story in Genesis to emphasise the point, that the creative activity of thinking must take place before it is observed by the thinker.132

everything he had made, and behold, it was very good. The same holds true of our thinking. It must first be there if we are to observe it.

133 Muschalle, op cit, p. 9.

134 Ibid, p. 11.

Muschalle characterises this as an apparently unbridgeable conceptual distinction between unmittelbare Erfahrung [immediate experience] of thinking and Beobachtung [observation] of thinking.133 Muschalle describes Steiner’s position as puzzling134, but it is only puzzling in the sense that it has the potential to create difficulties for Steiner’s overall epistemological project. It is consistent, according to Muschalle, with the psychological theory of Steiner’s time, and in particular with Brentano’s conception of the mind, with which Steiner would have been very familiar.

Muschalle’s work provides a critique of the many proposals put forward by other anthroposophical thinkers to save Steiner’s position. By and large the proposals amount to redefinitions of what it is believed Steiner meant by observation, immediate, experience and thinking. A couple of the more credible positions will be mentioned, if only in order to indicate the parameters of the debate. Muschalle argues vehemently against who has written extensively on Steiner’s more philosophical works. According to Muschalle, Witzenmann accepts the incompatibility between the activity of thinking and the simultaneous observation of it, and avoids the Beobachtungsaporie by claiming that the experience of thinking is remembered. The issue then becomes whether the experience which is remembered is an Erfahrung or an Erlebnis, and whether, therefore it ought to be characterised as an observation [Beobachtung], or as a perception [Wahrnehmung]. As Muschalle notes, Witzenmann’s strategy is to move the argument away from what Steiner means by the observation of thinking into an analysis of memory, but this strategy does not

lead to a resolution of the Beobachtungsaporie.135 Muschalle next considers the arguments

Page 26 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt put forward by Lorenzo Ravagli. Ravagli’s solution to the Beobachtungsaporie is to claim that there is an immediate, intuitive knowing, which comes into play at the same time as thinking, and which might be characterised as an intuitive – as opposed to an external – form of observation. This intuitive observation, Ravagli claims, occurs immediately with the activity of thinking, and thereby resolves the observation problem in The Philosophy of Freedom.136 As Muschalle points out, Ravagli’s self-immersion of the I’ in the activity of thinking [Selbstinnesein des Ich in der Denktätigkeit] may be an indicator of the experience of thinking, but it is not the same thing as the observation of thinking as Steiner describes it. Indeed, the very fact that we can speak of experiencing an immediate, intuitive knowledge of thinking [ein unmittelbares, intuitives Wissen], according to Muschalle, seems to indicate that the possibility of the simultaneous observation of thinking must be precluded.137 Muschalle also canvasses the arguments of several other commentators on Steiner’s Beobachtungsaporie,138 in an effort to find some way of overcoming the problem Steiner appears to have created for himself, namely that he has denied the possibility of observing our thoughts as we think them, yet bases his epistemology and his ethics on the freedom he claims we experience in the immediate observation of the activity of thinking.

135Ibid, pp 20-35.

136Ibid, pp 38-39, citing Ravagli, L. (1997) Der esoterishce Shulungsweg der Anthroposophie im Frühwerk Rudolf Steiners, in Jahrbuch für anthroposophische Kritik, p. 88ff.

137 Ibid, p. 45: Und weil wir dieses unmittelbare Wissen haben, infolge der Selbstgegebung des Denkens, gerade deswegen ist die Beobachtung des aktuellen Denkens für Steiner ausgeschlossen.

138Muschalle cites Peter Schneider, Wilfried Gabriel and Marcello da Veiga Greuel before returning to Witzenmann.

6. The apperception of essences

The problem of the observation of thinking may not be fatal to Steiner’s formulation of intuitive thinking, but it does point to the kinds of difficulties, which would appear to be the inevitable result of any attempt to argue for an essentially non-Kantian theory of cognition from within the context of the critical tradition. Steiner has devised his concept of intuitive thinking out of Fichte’s reformulation of the intellectual intuition determined by Kant to be unavailable to human cognition. Intuitive thinking as it is presented in Truth and Knowledge and Philosophy of Freedom, therefore, is on the one hand a creature of its Kantian lineage (and the spontaneity and immediacy which are said to characterise intellectual intuition), and on the other a heightened form of thinking, which can observe what is has itself created upon subsequent reflection. Seen from a Kantian perspective, such a process is nothing other than the operation of pure reason, and could not, therefore, lead to the apperception of essences. It is not surprising then that, after Philosophy of Freedom, Steiner no longer attempts to present his epistemology as a response to neo-Kantianism.

From this point there are several alternatives open to Steiner from within the academy. One

Page 27 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt would be to continue to argue for the heightened form of awareness he has characterised as intuitive thinking, though not from a Kantian perspective. This would avoid any concerns about the temporal ordering of the observation of thinking, but it would undermine his claim that even the critical philosophy, properly reconstituted, will lead to a methodology for the apperception of essences. Another possibility for Steiner might be to reconsider whether he had been correct to insist that thinking precedes consciousness, and to have claimed that it is the activity of thinking rather than consciousness, that lies at the heart of cognition. Steiner could argue instead that it is some kind of intuitive consciousness rather than intuitive

thinking that best describes the activity Fichte had recognised as arising from intellectual intuition. A third possibility from within the academy might be to abandon the neo-Kantian framework of his epistemology and attach his standard to the mast of that other prominent Continental approach to cognition, the phenomenological school of Brentano and Husserl. It will be remembered that Steiner describes Philosophy of Freedom on its title page as investigations of the soul using the method of natural science. The difficulty with adopting this approach for Steiner is that his methodology is in the end much more akin to that of the post- and neo-Kantians and the Idealist tradition generally than it is to the orientation of the Phenomenologists. Finally, Steiner might remain within the academy, but operate as an independent scholar, as Schopenhauer and von Hartmann had done before him.

The other alternative open to Steiner after Philosophy of Freedom is to abandon the academy and to pursue the development of intuitive thinking, but not as philosophy. Indeed, the direction in which Steiner’s argument appears to be heading suggests that this is what he will do. Seen retrospectively it could be claimed that Philosophy of Freedom is already not so much philosophy as the groundwork for the world view Steiner will adopt after he leaves the academy. There is support for such a view in Steiner’s Preface to the 1918 revised edition of Philosophy of Freedom. Here Steiner appears to accept that what he had set out to establish as the ground of knowledge can be no more clearly defined by him than as a region of the soul from which the riddles of life might be unravelled, and says:139

139 Ph F, Preface [2], ITSP, p. 2.

Once achieved, this view [of the human being that can support all other knowledge] can become part of the very life of the soul itself. But no theoretical answer is given that, once acquired, is simply carried as a conviction preserved by memory. Such an answer would have to be an illusion, according to the style of thought underlying this

book. Therefore no such finished, closed-off answer is provided here; rather, reference is made to a region of soul experience in which, through the soul’s inner activity, the question answers itself in a living way, always anew, whenever a human being needs it. Once we have found the region of the soul where these questions unfold, really perceiving this region gives all that we need to answer these riddles of life.

This writer is not passing any judgment upon the efficacy of what Steiner is proposing as a practice for solving the riddles of life. From what Steiner says above, and from what he does in leaving academic philosophy, Steiner has in effect passed his own judgment upon the likelihood that his epistemological arguments will ever find favour from within the academy

Page 28 17 Part 2 Chapter 7 INTUITIVE THINKING.txt and upon the possibility, therefore, of his being able to demonstrate philosophically that human beings have access to knowledge of essences.

Page 29 18 CONCLUSION.txt CONCLUSION

The discussions of the four disjunctions between the critical philosophy and Rudolf Steiner’s theory of knowledge, which have been the subject of this study, must lead to the conclusion that Steiner has not been successful in demonstrating that there are no limits to knowledge from within the context of the neo-Kantian tradition. His arguments against the architectonic of transcendental idealism are not so compelling, as to put seriously into question the structures and claims of the critical project. Steiner’s first disjunction, his fundamental opposition to Kantian dualism, does not provide sufficient reason to abandon dualism and adopt a monistic world view. His second disjunction, the attempt to identify Kant’s concept of the intellectus archetypus with Goethe’s anschauende Urteilskraft, rests upon the claim that thinking is a sense organ, which Steiner is unable to prove.

The third disjunction challenges Kant’s assertion that human cognition does not extend to a capacity for intellectual intuition. Although a convincing case can be made for intellectual intuition, the case Steiner is arguing had already been made by Fichte. Fichte concludes that there is an activity at the core of intellectual intuition, without specifying what that activity consists in. Steiner’s fourth disjunction from the critical philosophy is to identify the activity generated by intellectual intuition as intuitive thinking – thinking in which the thinker observes her own capacity to create concepts. It is our capacity for intuitive thinking, Steiner believes, which demonstrates that we have knowledge of essences. Steiner’s argument, however, leads to the observation dilemma: if we can observe thinking as we think our minds must be split in two, and if they are not split in

two then the observation cannot be taking place simultaneously with the act of thinking. The conclusion again has to be that Steiner has been unable to show that we have access to essences.

Although Steiner has not succeeded in proving what he set out to prove, that does mean either that there are no other avenues available for the pursuit of knowledge of essences, or that there was no philosophical merit in the epistemological work he undertook. As was indicated in the Introduction to this dissertation, Steiner did seek out other avenues for the pursuit of knowledge of essences, which he continued to believe was attainable through the refinement and intensification of thinking. Steiner remained outside the world of academic philosophy after publishing Philosophy of Freedom, though he continued to write and speak about and philosophers for the rest of his public life.

Even though Steiner did not remain within the academy it might nevertheless be claimed that he has made a contribution to epistemology, both in terms of the broader interests of the Continental philosophical tradition and of his attempt to dismantle the purported limits to knowledge from within the neo-Kantian tradition. The aspect of Continental philosophy to which it might be said Steiner contributes, is what Richard Tarnas in The Passion of the Western Mind describes as a participatory perspective on the nature of cognition. As for Steiner’s neo-Kantian epistemological project there is reason to think that the points at which Steiner sought to extend the architectonic of the critical

Page 1 18 CONCLUSION.txt philosophy – Kant’s limitations upon the availability of the intellectus archetypus and intellectual intuition – have room for further exploration. This writer is aware of work being undertaken in this area by one Kant scholar, Eckart Förster.

Participatory consciousness

It will be remembered from the Introduction that, in The Passion of the Western Mind, Tarnas introduces Steiner and the concept of participatory consciousness at the same time by putting Steiner forward as a representative of a counter-movement to the mainstream philosophical and scientific intellectual tradition. It will be recalled Tarnas makes the following claim:1

1 Tarnas, op. cit, p. 433

2 Ibid, p. 434.

Although the Cartesian-Kantian epistemological position has been the dominant paradigm of the modern mind, it has not been the only one, for at almost precisely the same time that the Enlightenment reached its philosophical climax in Kant, a radically different epistemological perspective began to emerge – first visible in Goethe with his study of natural forms, developed in new directions by Schiller, Schelling, Hegel, Coleridge, and Emerson, and articulated within the past century by Rudolf Steiner. Each of these thinkers gave his own distinct emphasis to the developing perspective, but common to all was a fundamental conviction that the relation of the human mind to the world was ultimately not dualistic but participatory.

Tarnas is not referring to the ontological and methodological dualism discussed in Part 2 Chapter 1, but to a more fundamental dualism between consciousness and object, which appears to be one of the assumptions of transcendental idealism. Tarnas gives a picture of participatory consciousness, which appears to owe a great deal to Schelling and Hegel, and then says of it:2

... this participatory conception held that these subjective principles [of Kant’s critical insight] are in fact an expression of the world’s own being, and that the human mind is ultimately the organ of the world’s own process of self-revelation.

In this view, the essential reality of nature is not separate, self-contained, and complete in itself, so that the human mind can examine it objectively and register it from without. Rather, nature’s unfolding truth emerges only with the active participation of the human mind. Nature’s reality is not merely phenomenal, nor is it independent and objective; rather, it is something that comes into being through the very act of human cognition. Nature becomes intelligible to itself through the human mind.

Page 2 18 CONCLUSION.txt

Steiner makes similar comments about the relationship between nature and consciousness and about the role of thinking in mediating between nature and spirit. It will be remembered, however, that Steiner follows Goethe in claiming that his way of seeing that relationship is based upon an enhanced form of empirical observation rather than upon a theoretical reduction of dualism to a monistic world view.

Tarnas claims that participatory consciousness requires an enhanced capacity of observation and concludes that: A developed inner life is therefore indispensable for cognition.3 His account of what that developed inner life might consist in amounts to a heightening of imagination to the point that: ... the imagination directly contacts the creative process within nature, realises that process within itself, and brings nature’s reality to conscious expression.4 As a result: The human imagination is itself part of the world’s intrinsic truth; without it the world is in some sense incomplete.5 Tarnas’s articulation of a heightened imaginative capacity and the requirement of a developed inner life are so strongly reminiscent of Steiner’s discussion of intuitive thinking in Philosophy of Freedom that he could well be continuing the arguments, which had been initiated by Steiner.

3Ibid, p. 434.

4 Loc. cit: Tarnas also speaks of the intellectual imagination and imaginal intuition.

5 Loc. cit.

Contemporary neo-Kantianism

One contemporary philosopher who continues to work on what might be called the nodal points of the critical philosophy is Eckart Förster. There are several Kantian studies by Förster, which examine ways in which the critical philosophy might further be developed. Förster’s works include Kant’s Final Synthesis: An essay on the Opus Postumum,6 the journal articles The Significance of ss76 and 77 of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy7 and the recently published Die 25 Jahre der Philosophie.8 In each of these works Förster explores aspects of Kant’s work, which are amenable to fresh and further interpretation. Förster establishes every step he takes by citing Kant and there are points he develops that are reminiscent of Steiner’s efforts to ground his expanded epistemology from within the Kantian tradition.

6 Förster, E. (2000) Kant’s Final Synthesis, Press: Cambridge, Mass.

7 Förster, E. (2009), op. cit., and Förster, E. (2010) op. cit.

8 Förster, E. (2011) Die 25 Jahre der Philosophie, Vittorio Klostermann: Frankfurt am Main

9 Förster (2000), p. x.

Förster’s Kant’s Final Synthesis is a set of essays on the Opus postumum that only became available, even in German, in the 1930s. Förster was engaged to prepare an

Page 3 18 CONCLUSION.txt English translation of some of the texts, and says of the task:9

That required, first and foremost, relating them to Kant’s published writings. Very soon it became clear that just as Kant’s earlier major publications contain the key to an understanding of his last work, the Opus postunum also sheds remarkable new light on these earlier works – works that we believe we know quite well.

This remarkable new light´ includes Kant’s later reconsideration of some of the presuppositions in the Third Critique, which had led to the way in which he regards organic nature. In the essay The Green Colour of a Lawn and Kant’s Theory of Matter for example, Förster cites fascicles of the Opus postunum and says:10

10 Ibid, p. 28.

11 Förster (2009), p. 9.

Our own bodily experience functions as the paradigm for the estimation of other objects as organic; it is the primary example by which we judge all others. But as a paradigm for natural purposiveness, it cannot be subject to the as if’ principle of the third Critique: this principle fails to hold in the case of our own bodily organisation. My body thus plays a unique role in my relation to the world around me – a role Kant will explore in subsequent fascicles, in connection with the doctrine of self-positing. But even in the present drafts, the contrast with the distant analogy between natural purposes and human artefacts that lies at the foundation of the Critique of Teleological Judgment could hardly be greater.

Some reference has been made in Part 2 Chapter 2 of the dissertation to Förster’s papers on The Significance of ss76 and 77 of the Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy. These papers consider and expand Kant’s concepts of intellectual intuition and intuitive understanding to include the following four possible interpretations:11

(1) intellectual intuition as

(a) the productive unity of possibility (thought) and actuality (being); and

(b) the non-sensible intuition of things-in-themselves;

(2) intuitive understanding as

(a) the synthetically universal understanding; and

(b) original understanding, or rather, as the cause of the world.

Page 4 18 CONCLUSION.txt

Förster identifies (1) (a) as Fichte’s concept of intellectual intuition and is arguing for the view that (2) (a) describes Goethe’s concept of intuitive understanding [anschauende Urteilskraft]. He does not focus upon the other possibilities, but it is clear that (1) (b), the non-sensible intuition of things-in-themselves, describes the interpretation of intellectual intuition Steiner is employing to arrive at knowledge of essences.

Förster’s recent Die 25 Jahre der Philosophie is an examination of German Idealism from the publication of the First Critique in 1781 to the publication of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit in 1806. In this work, as well as dealing with Fichte’s critique of consciousness in the Wissenschaftslehre, Förster devotes a chapter to the methodology of intuitive understanding.12 This chapter discusses Goethe’s contributions to the development of German Idealism and describes in some detail the methodology implicit in the Metamorphosis of Plants and the Theory of Colours. In this chapter, as in the papers on the Third Critique, Förster explores the personal and intellectual relationships between Goethe, Fichte, Reinhold, Schelling and Hegel.

12 Förster (2010), pp. 253-276.

Förster, like Steiner before him, is working from within the Kantian tradition. Like Steiner, he also appears to be exploring whether the critical project, as Kant would have wished, might ultimately lead to the establishment of metaphysical truths as matters of knowledge, rather than merely as belief. Although this is not the place to explore Förster’s work any further, the course it has taken does seem to suggest that Steiner was able to identify those points in the critical project, at which the tensions and possible weaknesses in it invite further theoretical consideration. In this respect, at least, it might be granted that Steiner has made a contribution to the continuing neo-Kantian tradition.

Page 5 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ameriks, K. (ed.) (2000) The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, Cambridge

U.P: Cambridge.

Barfield, O. (2006) Romanticism Comes of Age, The Barfield Press: San Rafael, Cal.

_____ (1965) Saving the Appearances, Harcourt, Brace and World: New York.

_____ (1977) Participation and Isolation: A Fresh Light on Present Discontents, in

The Rediscovery of Meaning and Other Essays, Wesleyan University Press:

Middletown, Conn.

Beck, L. W. (1965) (ed.) Studies in the Philosophy of Kant, The Bobbs-Merrill

Company Inc: Indianapolis.

Bortoft, H. (1996) The Wholeness of Nature: Goethe’s Way of Science, Floris Books:

Edinburgh.

Page 1 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt _____ (1994) Philosophy and the Divided Self. In Girndt, H. & Schrader, W.

(eds) Fichte-Studien, Band 6, Rodopi: Amsterdam and Atlanta pp117-147.

Breazeale, D. & Rockmore, T. (1996) (eds.) New Perspectives on Fichte, Humanities

Press: New Jersey.

Bywater, B. & Holdrege, C. (2005) (eds.), Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism, Trivium Publications: Amherst, NY.

Carlgren, F. (2008) Education Towards Freedom: Rudolf Steiner Education, Floris

Books: Edinburgh.

Cassirer, E. (1979) The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, Princeton UP: Princeton.

______(1974) The Problem of Knowledge, Yale UP: New Haven.

______(1970) Rousseau Kant Goethe: Two Essays, Princeton UP: Princeton.

Cassirer, H. (1954) Kant’s First Critique, George Allen and Unwin: London.

Caygill, H. (1995) A Kant Dictionary, Blackwell Publishers Ltd: Oxford.

Page 2 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

Dahlin, B. and Majorek, M. (2008) On the path towards thinking: learning from Martin

Heidegger and Rudolf Steiner, EERA Conference Papers: Gothenburg.

Davenport, R. (1955) The Dignity of Man, Harper & Brothers: New York.

Descartes, R. (1960) Meditations, in Descartes, R. Discourse on Method (trans. Arthur

Wollaston), Penguin: London.

Dilloo-Heidger, E. (2005) Projekt: Grundlagen der Anthroposophie:

www.dilloo.de/anthroindex.htm.

Edelglass, S., Maier, G., Gebert, H. & Davy, J. (2006) The Physics of Human Experience

Adonis Press: Hillsdale, New York.

Fichte, G. (1994) Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre, translated and edited by

Daniel Breazeale, Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis.

Fischer, L. (2011) Goethe contra Hegel: The Question of the End of Art, Goethe

Yearbook XV111 pp 127-156.

Page 3 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt Förster, E. Die Bedeutung von ss76,77 der Kritik der Urteilskraft fuer die Entwicklung

Der nachkantischen Philosophie Teile 1 & 2 in Zeitschrift fuer philosophische

Forschung, Band 56 (2002), 2 and 3; The Significance of ss76, 77 of the

Critique of Judgment for the Development of Post-Kantian Philosophy Parts 1

& 2, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal (2009) vol 30, nr 2 and vol 31, nr 2.

______(2010) Die 25 Jahre der Philosophie, Vittorio Klostermann: Frankfurt am Main.

______(2001) Goethe and the Auge des Geistes, Deutsche Vierteljahrschrift für

Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte, vol 75, issue 1.

______(2000) Kant’s Final Synthesis, Harvard U. P.: Cambridge, Mass.

Girndt, H. & Schrader, W. (1994) (eds) Fichte-Studien, Band 6, Rodopi: Amsterdam.

Goethe, J. (1970) Italian Journey, Penguin Books: London.

______(1978) The Metamorphosis of Plants, revised translation by A. Marshall & H.

Grotzke, Bio-dynamic Literature: Wyoming, Rhode Island.

Page 4 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

____ (1921) Naturwissenschaftliche Schriften ed. Steiner, Union Deutsche

Verlagsgesellschaft, Stuttgart-Berlin-Leipzig, 1884-97.

____ (1960) Goethes Werke. C. Wegner: Hamburg (Hamburger Ausgabe).

____ Sämtliche Werke, Max Hesses Verlag: Leipzig.

____ (1970) Theory of Colours, MIT Press: Cambridge, Mass.

Guyer, P. (2000) Absolute Idealism and the Rejection of Kantian Dualism, in Ameriks, K

(ed) The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, Cambridge UP:

Cambridge.

Hammer, O. (2004) Claiming Knowledge, Koninklijke Brill: Leiden.

Henrich, D. (1982) Fichte’s Original Insight: in Contemporary German Philosophy, vol

1, Pennsylvania State UP, pp 15-53.

Honderich, T. (1995) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford UP: Oxford.

Page 5 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

Holdrege, C. (2005) Doing Goethean Science. In Bywater, B. & Holdrege, C. (eds.)

Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism Trivium Publications: Amherst, NY, pp 27-52.

Jacquette, D. (ed.) (2004) The Cambridge Companion to Brentano, Cambridge UP:

Cambridge.

Kant, I. (1987) Critique of Judgment, translated by Werner Pluhar, Hackett Publishing

Company: Indianapolis.

_____ (1993) Critique of Practical Reason, translated by Lewis White Beck, Prentice

Hall: New Jersey.

_____ (1993) Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Norman Kemp Smith, Palgrave

Macmillan: London.

_____ (1972) The Moral Law: Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals,

(ed.) Paton, Hutchinson University Library: London.

Page 6 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

_____ (1974a) Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 1 & 2, Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

_____ (1974b) Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

_____ (1974c) Kritik der Urteilskraft, Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

_____ (1967) Kant: Philosophical Correspondence 1759-99, edited and translated by

Arnulf Zweig, University of Chicago Press: Chicago.

_____ (1838) Träume eines Geistersehers, in Sämtliche Werke vol 7, Leopold Voss:

Leipzig.

Kirn, M. (1998) Das grosse Denk-Ereignis, Verlag am Goetheanum: Dornach.

______(1999) Freiheit im Leib?, Verlag am Goetheanum: Dornach.

Lehrs, E. (1985) Man or Matter: Introduction to a Spiritual Understanding of Nature

based on Goethe’s Method of Training, Observation and Thought, Rudolf

Steiner Press: London.

Page 7 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt Majorek, M. (2002) Objektivität: ein Erkenntnisideal auf dem Prüfstand, Franke Verlag:

Tübingen, Basel.

Mautner, T. (2005) (ed.) Dictionary of Philosophy, Penguin Books: London.

Mazzone, A. (2010) A Passionate Education, Griffin Press: Salisbury, South Australia.

Muschalle, M. (2001) Das Denken und seine Beobachtung, Universität Bielefeld: online

_____ (2007a) Beobachtung des Denkens bei Rudolf Steiner, Books on Demand

GmbH: Norderstedt.

_____ (2007b) Goethe, Kant und das intuitive Denken in Rudolf Steiners Philosophie

der Freiheit, in Studien zur Anthroposophie: online.

Naydler, J. (ed) (2000) Goethe on Science: An Anthology of Goethe’s Scientific Writings,

Floris Books: Edinburgh.

Nelson, L. (1970) Progress and Regress in Philosophy, Basil Blackwell: London.

Paton, H. (1970) Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience, George Allen and Unwin: London.

Page 8 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

Pfeiffer, E. (1983) Biodynamic Gardening and Farming, Mercury Press: London.

Popper, K. (1968) The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson: London.

Quinton, A. (1980) Francis Bacon, OUP: Oxford.

Redding, P. (2009) Continental Idealism, Routledge: London.

Rockmore, T. (2007) Kant and Idealism, Yale U.P: New Haven and London.

Rollinger, R. Brentano and Husserl in Jacquette, D. (ed.) Cambridge Companion to

Brentano, Cambridge UP: Cambridge.

Root, C. (2005) The Proteus Within: Thoreau’s Practice of Goethe’s Phenomenology, in

Bywater, B. & Holdrege, C. Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism, Trivium: Amherst,

New York pp 232-249.

Rorty, R. (1979) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton UP: Princeton.

Schelling, F. (1989) The Philosophy of Art (trans. Douglas Stott), University of

Page 9 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

Minnesota Press: Minneapolis.

Seamon, D. & Zajonc, A. (eds.) (1988) Goethe’s Way of Science, SUNY: New York.

Seidel, G. (1976) Activity and Ground: Fichte, Schelling and Hegel, Georg Olms Verlag:

Hildesheim, New York.

Sheldrake, R. (1990) The Rebirth of Nature, Century: London.

Sims, E. (2005) Goethe, Husserl and the Crisis of the European Sciences, In Bywater,

B. & Holdrege, C. (eds) Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism, Trivium Publications:

Amherst, New York.

Steiner, R. (1999a) Autobiography: The Course of My LIfe, translated by R. Stebbing,

Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, New York.

______(1999b) Einleitungen zu Goethes Naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften, Rudolf

Steiner Verlag: Dornach.

Page 10 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt ______(1985) Friedrich Nietzsche, Fighter for Freedom, translated by M. de Ris,

Spiritual Science Library: Blauvelt, New York.

______(1950) Goethe the Scientist: Anthroposophic Press: New York.

______(2004) Goethe’s World View, translated by W. Lindeman, Mercury Press:

Spring Valley, New York.

______(1995) Intuitive Thinking as a Spiritual Path, translated by Michael Lipson,

Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, New York.

______(1976) Knowledge of Higher Worlds: How is it achieved? Rudolf Steiner Press:

London.

______(2000) Nature’s Open Secret, translated by J. Barnes & M. Spiegler,

Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, New York.

______(1997) An Outline of Esoteric Science, Anthroposophic Press: Hudson, N. Y.

_____ (2005) Die Philosophie der Freiheit, Rudolf Steiner Verlag: Dornach.

Page 11 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

_____ (2001) The Philosophy of Freedom, translated by Michael Wilson, Rudolf

Steiner Press: Forest Row.

______(1984) Philosophie und Anthroposophie, GA35, Rudolf Steiner Verlag:

Dornach.

______(1983b) The Redemption of Thinking, translated by A. Shepherd & M. Nicoll,

Anthroposophic Press: Spring Valley, New York.

______(1973) Riddles of Philosophy, introduction by F. Koelln, Anthroposophic Press:

Spring Valley, New York.

______(1988) The Science of Knowing, translated by W. Lindeman, Mercury Press:

Spring Valley, New York.

______(1981) Truth and Knowledge, translated by R. Stebbing, Steinerbooks: Blauvelt.

______(2010) Wahrheit und Wissenschaft, Rudolf Steiner Online Archiv.

Page 12 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt

Tarnas, R. (1993) The Passion of the Western Mind, Ballantine Books: New York.

Uberoi, J.P.S. (1984) The Other Mind of Europe: Goethe as a scientist, Oxford

University Press: Delhi.

Veiga Greuel, M. (1990) Wirklichkeit und Freiheit, Gideon Spicker Verlag: Dornach.

Wahl, D. (2005) Zarte Empirie: Goethean Science as a Way of Knowing. In Bywater,

B. & Holdrege, C. Goethe’s Delicate Empiricism Trivium Publications: Amherst

NY, pp 58-76.

Welburn, A. (2004) Rudolf Steiner’s Philosophy, Floris Books: Edinburgh.

Wells, G. (1967) Goethe and the Intermaxillary Bone, British Journal for the History of

Science, Vol 3, No 12, pp 348-361.

Zajonc, A. Goethe and the Science of his Time, in Seamon, D. & Zajonc, A. (eds.)

(1988) Goethe’s Way of Science, SUNY Press: Albany, New York.

Page 13 19 BIBLIOGRAPHY.txt Zöller, G. (1996) Thinking and Willing in Fichte’s Theory of Subjectivity, in Breazeale,

D. & Rockmore, T. (eds) New Perspectives on Fichte, Humanities Press: New

Jersey.

Page 14