A Study of the Moral, Political, and Educational

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Study of the Moral, Political, and Educational AN HONEST HEART AND A KNOWING HEAD: A STUDY OF THE MORAL, POLITICAL, AND EDUCATIONAL THOUGHT OF JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU AND THOMAS JEFFERSON by JASON ROBLES B.A., University of California, San Diego, 2005 M.A., University of Colorado, 2007 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Colorado in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science 2012 This thesis entitled: An Honest Heart and a Knowing Head: A Study of the Moral, Political, and Educational Thought of Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Thomas Jefferson written by Jason Robles has been approved for the Department of Political Science. David R. Mapel, Chair Horst Mewes Steven J. Vanderheiden Claudia Mills Ethan Putterman Date The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories and we find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline. Robles, Jason (Ph.D., Political Science) An Honest Heart and a Knowing Head: A Study of the Moral, Political, and Educational Thought of Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Thomas Jefferson Thesis directed by Associate Professor David R. Mapel The picture of democracy we get from both Thomas Jefferson and Jean-Jacques Rousseau is one that is characterized by potentiality or possibility: the development of democracy and the cultivation of virtuous, republican citizens are processes of perpetual becoming, or perpetual improvement and progress towards an ideal form of freedom. My primary objective is to demonstrate an affinity in principle between the moral, political, and educational thought of Thomas Jefferson and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. While similarity is demonstrable, I do not claim that Jeffersonian republicanism and Rousseauian republicanism are merely ideological or theoretical carbon copies; each is, in fact, distinct in its own right and the two are, at times, seemingly disparate, if not incompatible. Nevertheless, I suggest that the core of the Jeffersonian vision of republican government—perhaps best defined nearly four decades after Jefferson’s death by Abraham Lincoln as a government “of the people, by the people, and for the people”—sits comfortably alongside Rousseau’s theory. In fact, we might say that Jefferson’s theory is something of an indirect adaptation of Rousseau’s overly romanticized vision of a pastoral sort of republicanism—a much more practical adaptation to the unique circumstances of late eighteenth and early nineteenth century America, no doubt, but an adaptation nonetheless. Jefferson and Rousseau each embrace a notion of transcendent moral and political right and each subscribes to a natural rights philosophy informed by that standard. However, scholars either reject the Rousseauian overtones in Jefferson’s thought or fail to appreciate fully those facets of his thought that substantiate the heretofore unrecognized affinity between Rousseauian and Jeffersonian idealism. While there have been a few (misguided) attempts to show that Jefferson was, historically, quite the Rousseauist, that is not my aim; rather, I wish to show that Jefferson’s moral and political thought has more in common with Rousseau’s at the level of principle than many scholars (and perhaps Jefferson himself) seem ready to recognize. iii For Gene and Elliot ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am eternally grateful for my loving wife, Andrea, without whom this project would not have been possible. Her patience, confidence, and untiring support sustained me until the end, and I shall be forever in her debt. Amor meus amplior quam verba est. I am also especially grateful for the love and support of family and friends, especially my two children, Elliot and Sara; my dear friend and longtime partner in crime, David Agado; and my colleague and friend, Heather Roff (“better a nettle in the side of your friend than his echo”). I would like to thank my committee members: Horst Mewes, Steven Vanderheiden, Claudia Mills, and Ethan Putterman, as well as Michaele Ferguson, who commented on an earlier draft of Chapter Two and provided invaluable feedback. I would also like to thank the Robert H. Smith International Center for Jefferson Studies for their generous support. I would like especially to thank Andrew O’Shaughnessy and Peter Onuf, as well as the staff and research librarians at the Jefferson Library, particularly Jack Robertson, Anna Berkes, and Endrina Tay. I would also like to thank Nathalie Caron, Csaba Lévai, and all of the other research fellows and visiting scholars who provided me with invaluable feedback and assistance. And last, but certainly not least, I am grateful for the support and encouragement of my advisor and mentor, David Mapel. A bove majori discit arare minor. v CONTENTS INTRODUCTION……………………………………………………………………….. 1 I. ROUSSEAU’S REPUBLICAN IDEAL: VOLONTÉ GÉNÉRALE AND THE PRIORITY OF RIGHT…………………………………............ 15 II. FATHERS AS FOUNDERS AND FOUNDERS AS FATHERS: ROUSSEAU, CIVIC EDUCATION, AND THE PROBLEM OF MAKING CITIZENS AND MEN…………………………….……….…… 49 III. ROUSSEAUIAN ROMANTICISM IN THE MORAL AND POLITICAL THOUGHT OF THOMAS JEFFERSON………………….… 84 IV. JEFFERSON AND THE IDEA OF PUBLIC RELIGION…………...…… 121 V. SENTINELS AND CYNOSURES: THOMAS JEFFERSON, AFFECTIONATE MENTORS, AND THE EDUCATION OF REPUBLICAN CITIZENS……………………………………………...… 152 CONCLUSION………………………………………………………………………... 201 BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………………………………………………...… 215 APPENDIX……………………………………………………………………………. 235 vi INTRODUCTION We of the United States are constitutionally and conscientiously democrats. We consider society as one of the natural wants with which man has been created; that he has been endowed with faculties and qualities to effect its satisfaction by concurrence of others having the same want; that when, by the exercise of these faculties, he has procured a state of society, it is one of his acquisitions which he has a right to regulate and control, jointly indeed with all those who have concurred in the procurement, whom he cannot exclude from its use or direction more than they him.1 Born a citizen of a free State, and a member of the sovereign, the right to vote in it is enough to impose on me the duty to learn about public affairs, regardless of how weak might be the influence of my voice on them. Happy whenever I meditate about Governments, always to find in my inquiries new reasons for loving that of my country.2 I. The Sage of Monticello and the Enfant Terrible of the Enlightenment: Strange Bedfellows? My primary objective is to demonstrate an affinity between the moral, political, and educational thought of Thomas Jefferson and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. While similarity is demonstrable, I do not claim that Jeffersonian republicanism and Rousseauian republicanism are merely ideological or theoretical carbon copies; each is, in fact, distinct in its own right and the two are, at times, seemingly disparate, if not incompatible. Nevertheless, I suggest that the core of the Jeffersonian vision of republican government—perhaps best defined nearly four decades after Jefferson’s death by Abraham Lincoln as a government “of the people, by the people, and for the people”— sits comfortably alongside Rousseau’s theory. In fact, we might say that Jefferson’s 1 Thomas Jefferson to Pierre Samuel Dupont de Nemours, 24 April 1816, in Merrill D. Peterson, ed., Thomas Jefferson: Writings (New York: Library of America, 1984), 1387. Hereafter, Writings. 2 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Social Contract, Preface, Book I, in The Basic Political Writings, trans. Donald A. Cress (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1987). Hereafter, SC. 1 theory is something of an indirect adaptation of Rousseau’s overly romanticized vision of a pastoral sort of republicanism—a much more practical adaptation to the unique circumstances of late eighteenth and early nineteenth century America, no doubt, but an adaptation nonetheless. While I try to relate Jefferson’s republican vision to Rousseau’s by way of careful textual analysis, I do not mean simply to point out parallel or ostensibly parallel passages in the texts. Textual similarities do exist and I highlight them as needed. However, my primary aim is to call attention to the ways in which Rousseau and Jefferson overlap at the level of principle, or the ways in which their respective moral and political theories converge. It is my contention that an examination of either figure outside of their historical context is wholly inadequate. Likewise, simply studying Rousseau’s Social Contract or Jefferson’s Notes on the State of Virginia, will ultimately afford the reader very little in the way of a systematic understanding of either man’s moral and political philosophy. While Rousseau had the luxury of remaining aloof and virtually disengaged from public life, Jefferson did not. Jefferson’s theory might not always agree with his practice, but this much is to be expected, especially from a man who was wrapped up in the politics of revolution for the better part of two decades and who would, in one way or another, be embroiled in political controversy for the rest of his life. Another of my goals—an ambitious goal, to be sure—is to offer a more precise account of Jefferson’s moral and political thought. In particular, I mean to profile the coherence and unity of Jefferson’s thoughts on the relationship between natural rights, republicanism, and moral virtue. I seek to glean from Jefferson’s political philosophy a better understanding of his thoughts on the quality of character that is necessary to the 2 preservation of liberty and a democratic way of life.3 This entails an exploration of several facets of Jefferson’s thought: from his understanding of natural right and conventional right4 to the primacy of majority rule; his nuanced emphasis on the importance of civic virtue of a particular type and a separate, but no less significant emphasis on the importance of moral virtue; and the often overlooked (or at least underemphasized) notion of a rationalized or “republicanized” Christianity (something akin to Rousseau’s “civil religion”).
Recommended publications
  • Political Ideas and Movements That Created the Modern World
    harri+b.cov 27/5/03 4:15 pm Page 1 UNDERSTANDINGPOLITICS Understanding RITTEN with the A2 component of the GCE WGovernment and Politics A level in mind, this book is a comprehensive introduction to the political ideas and movements that created the modern world. Underpinned by the work of major thinkers such as Hobbes, Locke, Marx, Mill, Weber and others, the first half of the book looks at core political concepts including the British and European political issues state and sovereignty, the nation, democracy, representation and legitimacy, freedom, equality and rights, obligation and citizenship. The role of ideology in modern politics and society is also discussed. The second half of the book addresses established ideologies such as Conservatism, Liberalism, Socialism, Marxism and Nationalism, before moving on to more recent movements such as Environmentalism and Ecologism, Fascism, and Feminism. The subject is covered in a clear, accessible style, including Understanding a number of student-friendly features, such as chapter summaries, key points to consider, definitions and tips for further sources of information. There is a definite need for a text of this kind. It will be invaluable for students of Government and Politics on introductory courses, whether they be A level candidates or undergraduates. political ideas KEVIN HARRISON IS A LECTURER IN POLITICS AND HISTORY AT MANCHESTER COLLEGE OF ARTS AND TECHNOLOGY. HE IS ALSO AN ASSOCIATE McNAUGHTON LECTURER IN SOCIAL SCIENCES WITH THE OPEN UNIVERSITY. HE HAS WRITTEN ARTICLES ON POLITICS AND HISTORY AND IS JOINT AUTHOR, WITH TONY BOYD, OF THE BRITISH CONSTITUTION: EVOLUTION OR REVOLUTION? and TONY BOYD WAS FORMERLY HEAD OF GENERAL STUDIES AT XAVERIAN VI FORM COLLEGE, MANCHESTER, WHERE HE TAUGHT POLITICS AND HISTORY.
    [Show full text]
  • Gothic Riffs Anon., the Secret Tribunal
    Gothic Riffs Anon., The Secret Tribunal. courtesy of the sadleir-Black collection, University of Virginia Library Gothic Riffs Secularizing the Uncanny in the European Imaginary, 1780–1820 ) Diane Long hoeveler The OhiO STaTe UniverSiT y Press Columbus Copyright © 2010 by The Ohio State University. all rights reserved. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data hoeveler, Diane Long. Gothic riffs : secularizing the uncanny in the european imaginary, 1780–1820 / Diane Long hoeveler. p. cm. includes bibliographical references and index. iSBn-13: 978-0-8142-1131-1 (cloth : alk. paper) iSBn-10: 0-8142-1131-3 (cloth : alk. paper) iSBn-13: 978-0-8142-9230-3 (cd-rom) 1. Gothic revival (Literature)—influence. 2. Gothic revival (Literature)—history and criticism. 3. Gothic fiction (Literary genre)—history and criticism. i. Title. Pn3435.h59 2010 809'.9164—dc22 2009050593 This book is available in the following editions: Cloth (iSBn 978-0-8142-1131-1) CD-rOM (iSBn 978-0-8142-9230-3) Cover design by Jennifer Shoffey Forsythe. Type set in adobe Minion Pro. Printed by Thomson-Shore, inc. The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the american national Standard for information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials. ANSi Z39.48-1992. 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 This book is for David: January 29, 2010 Riff: A simple musical phrase repeated over and over, often with a strong or syncopated rhythm, and frequently used as background to a solo improvisa- tion. —OED - c o n t e n t s - List of figures xi Preface and Acknowledgments xiii introduction Gothic Riffs: songs in the Key of secularization 1 chapter 1 Gothic Mediations: shakespeare, the sentimental, and the secularization of Virtue 35 chapter 2 Rescue operas” and Providential Deism 74 chapter 3 Ghostly Visitants: the Gothic Drama and the coexistence of immanence and transcendence 103 chapter 4 Entr’acte.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    BIBLIOGRAPHY Adams, William Howard, ed. The Eye of Thomas Jefferson. Blake, Channing. “The Early Interiors of Carrère and Hastings.” Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1981. The Magazine Antiques 110 (1976): 344–351. Aikman, Lonnelle. We, the People: The Story of the United Blum, John M., et. al., eds. The National Experience. New States Capitol. Washington: U. S. Capitol Historical Society, 1991. York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., 1963. Alex, William. Calvert Vaux: Architect & Planner. New York: Bowling, Kenneth R. Creating the Federal City, 1774–1800: Ink, Inc., 1994. Potomac Fever. Washington: The American Institute of Archi- tects Press, 1988. Alexander, R. L. “The Grand Federal Edifice.” Documentary Editing 9 (June 1987): 13–17. Bowling, Kenneth R., and Helen E. Veit., eds. The Diary of William Maclay and Other Notes On Senate Debates. Balti- Allen, William C. “In The Greatest Solemn Dignity”: The Capi- more: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1988. tol’s Four Cornerstones. Washington: Government Printing Bristow, Ian C. Interior House-Painting Colours and Tech- Office, 1995. nology 1615–1840. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996. ———. “‘Seat of Broils, Confusion, and Squandered Thousands’: Brown, Glenn. “Dr. William Thornton, Architect.” Architectural Building the Capitol, 1790–1802.” The United States Capitol: Record 6 (1896): 53–70. Designing and Decorating a National Icon. Athens: Ohio University Press, 2000. ———. History of the United States Capitol. 2 vols. Washing- ton: Government Printing Office, 1900, 1902. ———. The Dome of the United States Capitol: An Architec- tural History. Washington: Government Printing Office, 1992. ———. Memories: A Winning Crusade to Revive George Washington’s Vision of a Capital City.
    [Show full text]
  • Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-2012)
    É T U D E 5 5 U R L E 1 8' 5 1 È ( L E X V 1 1 1 Revue fondée par Ro land Mortier et Hervé Hasquin DIRECTEURS Valérie André et Brigitte D'Hainaut-Zveny COMITt tDITORIAL Bruno Bernard, Claude Bruneel (Université catholique de Louvain), Carlo Capra (Università degli studi, Milan), David Charlton (Roya l Holloway College, Londres), Manuel Couvreur, Nicolas Cronk (Vo ltaire Foundation, University of Oxford), Michèle Galand, Jan Herman (Katholi eke Universiteit Leuven), Michel Jangoux, Huguette Krief (Un iversité de Provence, Aix-en-Provence), Christophe Loir, Roland Mortier, Fabrice Preyat, Dan iel Rabreau (U niverSité de Paris l, Panthéon-Sorbonne), Daniel Roche (Collège de France), Raymond Trousson et Renate Zedinger (Universitat Wien) GROUPE D'ÉTUDE D U 1 8' 5 1 È ( L E tCRIREÀ Valérie André [email protected] Brigitte D'Hainaut-Zveny Brigitte.D Hainaut @ulb.ac.be ou à l'adresse suivante Groupe d'étude du XVIII' siècle Université libre de Bruxelles (CP 175/01) Avenue F.D. Roosevelt 50 • B -1050 Bruxelles JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU (1712-2012) MATÉRIAUX POUR UN RENOUVEAU CRITIQUE Publié avec l'aide financière du Fonds de la recherche scientifique - FNRS Ë T U DES 5 URL E 1 8' 5 1 È ( L E x v 1 1 1 JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU (1712-2012) MATÉRIAUX POUR UN RENOUVEAU CRITIQUE VOLUME COMPOSÉ ET ÉDITÉ PAR CHRISTOPHE VAN STAEN 2 0 1 2 ÉDITIONS DE L'UNIVERSITÉ DE BRUXELLES DAN 5 L A M Ê M E COLLECTION Les préoccupations économiques et sociales des philosophes, littérateurs et artistes au XVIII e siècle, 1976 Bruxelles au XVIIIe siècle, 1977 L'Europe et les révolutions (1770-1800), 1980 La noblesse belge au XVIIIe siècle, 1982 Idéologies de la noblesse, 1984 Une famille noble de hauts fonctionnaires: les Neny, 1985 Le livre à Liège et à Bruxelles au XVIIIe siècle, 1987 Unité et diversité de l'empire des Habsbourg à la fin du XVIIIe siècle, 1988 Deux aspects contestés de la politique révolutionnaire en Belgique: langue et culte, 1989 Fêtes et musiques révolutionnaires: Grétry et Gossec, 1990 Rocaille.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism, Contractarianism, and the Problem of Exclusion
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Liberalism, Contractarianism, and the Problem of Exclusion Citation for published version: Cook, P 2015, Liberalism, Contractarianism, and the Problem of Exclusion. in S Wall (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism. Cambridge Companions to Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 87-111. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139942478 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1017/CBO9781139942478 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 28. Sep. 2021 LIBERALISM, CONTRACTARIANISM AND THE PROBLEM OF EXCLUSION Philip Cook University of Edinburgh [email protected] Final Pre-Publication Draft Published Version Appeared in The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism. Wall, S. (ed.). (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015), p. 87-111 Introduction For liberal contractarians, moral and political principles are justified if agreeable to persons as free and equals.1 But for critics of liberal contractarianism, this justification does not apply to all those who should be treated as free and equal, but only to those capable of agreement.
    [Show full text]
  • Adams and Jefferson : Personal Politics in the Early Republic
    d ADAMS AND JEFFERSON: Personal Politics in the Early Republic John Connor The deterioration of the friendship between John Adams and Thomas Jefferson remains a controversial subject among his­ torians. The two men were once the best of friends, spending personal time with each other’s family, and enjoying a profes­ sional collaboration that would become famous—drafting the Declaration of Independence. Furthermore, they freely ac­ knowledged their mutual fondness. In 1784, Adams wrote that his colleague Thomas Jefferson was “an old friend with whom I have often had occasion to labor at many a knotty problem and in whose ability and steadiness I always found great cause to confide.”1 Jefferson wrote similar words of praise to his friend James Madison: “[Adams] is profound in his views, and accurate in his judgments. He is so amiable, that I pronounce you will love him if ever you become acquainted with him.”2 But despite this initial close friendship, by the 1790s Adams called Jefferson “weak, confused, uninformed, and ignorant.”3 At the same time, Jefferson called Adams actions as President “the most grotesque scene in the tragic­comedy of govern­ ment.”4 What led these two men who once worked so closely together to turn from close friends to bitter enemies in only ten years? How their friendship dissolved has been discussed by Stephen Kurtz, Stanley Elkins, and Eric McKitrick, who em­ 58 phasize certain events in the Adams Presidency as precise mo­ ments in which the two men parted ways.5 Noble Cunningham Jr., points to the passage of the Alien and Sedition Act and the creation of a Standing Army as the point at which the two men’s differences became irreconcilable.6 Recent scholarship by James Sharp argues that a dinner conversation held before Adams was even elected led to their disbanding.7 A second school of thought, led by Merrill Peterson, Dumas Malone, and John Ferling, links the divide not so much to a particular event but to the actions of a third party, often Alexander Hamilton.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Pilgrimage to Monticello
    Notes 1 The Pilgrimage to Monticello 1. Cited by E. J. Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution: Europe 1789-1848 (London: Sphere Books, 1973/1962) p. 164. 2. The best account of the iconography of La Fayette's tour of the United States isS. J. Idzerda, A. C. Loveland, M. H. Miller, Lafayette, Hero of Two Worlds: The Art and Pageantry of His Farewell Tour of America, 1824-1825 (Hanover and London: the Queen's Museum, 1989). There is a sub­ stantial bibliography. There are good illustrations also in M. Klamkin, The Return of Lafayette 1824-1825 (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1975). Contemporary accounts are reprinted in E. E. Brandon, Lafayette, Guest of the Nation: a Contemporary Account of the Triumphal Tour of General Lafayette through the United States in 1824-1825, as Reported by the Local Newspapers, 3 vols (Oxford, Ohio: Oxford Historical Press, 1950-57). Also useful is J. B. Nolan, Lafayette in America Day by Day (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1934). I have drawn parti­ cularly on the contemporary newspaper (and other) material reprinted in 'General La Fayette's Visit to Monticello and the University' in The Virginia Uniz,ersity Magazine, IV, 3 (December, 1859) 113-25; Auguste Levasseur, Lafayette in America, in 1824 and 1825, translated from the French (2 vols, 1829), and Jane Blair, Cary Smith, 'The Carysbrook Memoir', Wilson Miles Cary Memorial Collection (University of Virgi­ nia Ac. No. 1378) pp. 55-62. These have been supplemented by the newspapers on file at the International Center for Jefferson Studies, Charlottesville. For analysis of the influence of La Fayette's tour on forming national consciousness in the USA, see F.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Notes INTRODUCTION 1. Harper's, 'Is there Virtue in Profit: Reconsidering the Morality of Capitalism', vol. 273 (December 1986 ), 38. 2. Joyce Appleby, Capitalism and a New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York, 1984), 25-50. 3. John M. McCusker & Russell R. Menard, The Economy of British America, 1607-1789 (Chapel Hill, 1985), 71. On the importance of overseas trade to individuals' income in the colonies see Alice Hansen Jones, Wealth of a Nation: The American Colonies on the Eve of the Revolution (New York, 1980), 65-66. 4. James A. Field Jr., 'All Economists, All Diplomats', in William H. Becker and Samuel F. Wells Jr., eds, Economic and World Power (New York, 1989), 1. 5. Jefferson to James Madison, January 30, 1787; to William Stephen Smith, November 13, 1787, Julian P. Boyd et al. eds, The Papers of Thomas Jefferson, 24 vols to date (Princeton, 1950- , hereafter Jefferson Papers), XI, 93, XII, 356. 6. Richard K. Mathews, The Radical Politics of Thomas Jefferson: A Revisionist View (Lawrence, Kansas, 1984), 122. 7. James Madison toN. P. Trist, May 1832, Gillard Hunted., The Writings of James Madison 9 vols (New York, 1900-1910) IX, 479. 8. Dumas Malone, Jefferson and his Time, 6 vols (Boston 1948-1981), vol. 1: Jefferson the Virginian vol. 2: Jefferson and the Rights of Man; vol. 3: Jefferson and the Ordeal Liberty; vol. 4: Jefferson the President: First Term, 1801-1805; vol. 5: Jefferson the President: Second Term, 1805-1809; vol. 6: The Sage of Monticello. 9. Merrill Peterson, Thomas Jefferson and the new Nation: A Biography (New York, 1970); idem, The Jefferson ]mage in the American Mind (New York, 1960).
    [Show full text]
  • Religious and Politics Evangelical Advocacy: a Response to Global Poverty
    Asbury Theological Seminary ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange Syllabi Advocacy on US Government Foreign Assistance 2012 Religious and Politics Evangelical Advocacy: A Response to Global Poverty Follow this and additional works at: http://place.asburyseminary.edu/advocacysyllabi Recommended Citation Evangelical Advocacy: A Response to Global Poverty, "Religious and Politics" (2012). Syllabi. Book 7. http://place.asburyseminary.edu/advocacysyllabi/7 This Document is brought to you for free and open access by the Advocacy on US Government Foreign Assistance at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Syllabi by an authorized administrator of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 4/24/12 4:00 PM POLS 375: Religion and Politics ***PLEASE NOTE THIS COURSE WEBSITE WILL BE UNDERGOING CONSTANT CONSTRUCTION AND UPDATING THROUGHOUT THE COURSE, SO YOU ARE REQUIRED TO CHECK BACK HERE AT LEAST EVERY FEW DAYS!!!*** SYLLABUS Religion and Politics Course Syllabus ASSIGNMENTS: Term Paper Details and Requirements ASSIGNED READINGS Origins of Religion and Politics Definitions of Politics and Religion Evolutionary Origins of PoliticsWhat is the proposed evolutionary basis of competition between groups? What is the proposed evolutionary basis of competition within groups? Evolutionary Origins of Morality What is the proposed evolutionary basis of morality? Evolutionary Origins of ReligionWhat is the proposed evolutionary basis of religious belief and religious practices? Can there be "politics without religion"? And, can there be a stable, sustainable political regime without religion? Unconventional Partners? The Noble Lie from Plato's Republic. What role should religion play in supporting the state, according to Plato? Democracy in America by Alexis de Tocqueville.
    [Show full text]
  • John Ben Shepperd, Jr. Memorial Library Catalog
    John Ben Shepperd, Jr. Memorial Library Catalog Author Other Authors Title Call Letter Call number Volume Closed shelf Notes Donated By In Memory Of (unkown) (unknown) history of the presidents for children E 176.1 .Un4 Closed shelf 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) Ruth Goree and Jane Brown 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) Anonymous 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) Bobbie Meadows Beulah Hodges 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) 1977 Inaugural Committee A New Spirit, A New Commitment, A New America F 200 .A17 (1977) 1981 Presidential Inaugural Committee (U.S.) A Great New Beginning: the 1981 Inaugural Story E 877.2 .G73 A Citizen of Western New York Bancroft, George Memoirs of General Andrew Jackson, Seventh President of the United States E 382 .M53 Closed shelf John Ben Shepperd A.P.F., Inc. A Catalogue of Frames, Fifteenth Century to Present N 8550 .A2 (1973) A.P.F. Inc. Aaron, Ira E. Carter, Sylvia Take a Bow PZ 8.9 .A135 Abbott, David W. Political Parties: Leadership, Organization, Linkage JK 2265 .A6 Abbott, John S.C. Conwell, Russell H. Lives of the Presidents of the United States of America E 176.1 .A249 Closed shelf Ector County Library Abbott, John S.C.
    [Show full text]
  • Consent As the Foundation of Political Authority—A Lockean Perspective*
    RMM Vol. 5, 2014, 64–78 Special Topic: Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Frank Dietrich Consent as the Foundation of Political Authority—A Lockean Perspective* Abstract: The article focuses on the justification provided by classical contract theory for the right of states to enact laws and the corresponding obligation of political allegiance. At first the distinction between political authority and parental authority developed by John Locke in his seminal work “Two Treatises of Government” is explored. Thereafter it is discussed why the interests of individuals in the creation of a state fail to vindicate the exercise of governmental power. As regards David Hume’s influential objections to contract theory, it is argued that the consent criterion of political legitimacy withstands his criticism. Hume cannot establish that the core idea of Locke’s justificatory approach is wrong; he merely demonstrates that hardly any existing state meets the consent requirement. Finally the question is discussed which conditions a state must fulfil in order to be entitled to claim that its citizens tacitly approve of its authority. Keywords: Authority, Consent, Contract Theory, David Hume, John Locke, Political Obli- gation. 1. Introduction Hillel Steiner’s (1978) classical paper, that inspired the special topic of this jour- nal, primarily focused on empirical questions about the emergence of social or- der. The article discussed two alternative models of explanation—the invisible hand process and the contractual agreement. According to the former approach, the creation of social institutions is not deliberately planned, it rather results unintendedly from the self-interested behavior of rational actors.
    [Show full text]
  • Hobbes and the Theory of Social Contract As the Context for Kant's
    Hobbes and the theory of social contract as the context for Kant’s political philosophy Gorazd Korošec f we are to deal with Kant’s political theory, we must put it in the context I of social contract theories. The theory of social contract has a central place in Kant’s political theory and by placing it in this tradition, we shall be able to see where his theory is in accordance with the tradition, and where it differs from it. Social contract theory as a mode of political thought has dominated the Age of Enlightenment, but we can also see a revival of such theories in today’s political philosophy. We can trace the origins of social contract theory in ancient and medieval thought to Augustine, who built on Seneca and Cicero, to William of Ockham and Nicholas Cusanus, and find a number of basic elements for such a theory in Francisco Suarez, a Spanish writer who saw common political consent as necessary for people to be gathered together in one political body. Talking about its origins, we can also mention the tradition of natural law theory, developed by Grotius, Althusius, Lipsius and Seiden, which was subsequently included in a large part in theories of social contract by many of its greatest authors. The idea of individual moral autonomy, grown within the movements of Reformation and Protestantism and applied to politics, provided the intellectual basis for a social contract theory. At its heart is the idea that legitimate government is the artificial product of the voluntary agreement of free moral agents, and that there is no »natural« political authority.
    [Show full text]