Maximilian Forschner

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Maximilian Forschner Qewriva και Στωικη Aρετή MAXIMILIAN FORSCHNER Aυτή η ανακοίνωση έχει διπλό στόχο: η πρωταρχική της πρόθεση είναι να υποστηρίξει ότι η στωική αντίληψη της αρετής δεν ήταν, αρχικά, κυριαρικά ηθική· αποδεικνύοντας αυτό, η ανακοίνωση έχει την πρόθεση επίσης να σκιαγραφήσει τους λόγους που έκαναν τον Kικέρωνα να αναλάβει μια τέτοιου είδους ηθικοποίησης (moralisation). Όσον αφορά τον πρώτο στόχο, η ανακοίνωση καθοδηγείται από την υπόθεση ότι ούτε το κεντρικό δόγμα της Στωικής φιλοσοφίας, δηλαδή η ταύτιση της αρετής με την ευδαιμονία, ούτε η ιδιοτυπία των δογμάτων τους για τα πάθη (emotions) μπορούν να γίνουν κατανοητά χωρίς να λάβει κανείς υπόψη τον κεντρικό ρόλο που η qewriva πρέπει να είχε διαδραματίσει στην αντίληψή τους για την τέλεια ανθρώπινη ζωή. Όσον αφορά το δεύτερο στόχο, η ανακοίνωση καθοδηγείται από την ιδέα, ότι αυτός ο (αναγκαστικά “δογματικός”) ρόλος της qewriva" δεν εναρμονίζονταν με τη μορφή του ακαδημαϊκού σκεπτικισμού του Kικέρωνα. Έτεινε, επομένως, ο Kικέρωνας, για να μην πούμε ότι ήταν αναγκασμένος, να τον τροποποιήσει και να τον υποβαθμίσει. O ηγετικός ρόλος που πρώτιστα διαδραματίζονταν από τη qewriva εντός της στωικής αντίληψης της αρετής είναι ακόμη ευδιάκριτος στο Kικέρωνα, οποτεδήποτε εκθέτει απλώς στωικά δόγματα ή όπου επιχειρηματολογεί υπέρ μιας στωικής θέσης χρησιμοποιώντας το σκεπτικό του λόγο και τη μέθοδο της αντιλογίας (counter-speech method). Όπως η ανακοίνωση προσπαθεί να δείξει, κάπως λεπτομερεικά, ακριβώς αυτό αποδεικνύεται με παραδειγματικό τρόπο στο έργο Tusculanae (Disputationes). Theoria and Stoic Virtue Zeno's Legacy in Cicero, Tusculanae disputationes V MAXIMILIAN FORSCHNER Nec tamen istas quaestiones physicorum exterminandas puto. est enim animorum ingeniorumque naturale quoddam quasi pabulum consideratio contemplatioque naturae: erigimur, altiores fieri videmur, humana despicimus cogitantesque supera atque caelestia haec nostra ut exigua et minima contemnimus. indagatio ipsa rerum cum maximarum tum etiam occultissimarum habet oblectationem; si vero aliquid occurrit, quod verisimile videatur, humanissima completur animus voluptate. quaeret igitur haec et vester sapiens et hic noster, sed vester, ut adsentiatur credat adfirmet, noster, ut vereatur temere opinari praeclareque agi secum putet, si in eius modi rebus, veri simile quod sit invenerit. Cicero, Acad. libr. Lucullus 127/8. Cicero owes his philosophical chattels partly to the legacy of Zeno. As he puts it himself quite clearly, he worked with the heritage of Greek philosophy "according to his own judgement and discretion"1 and he has passed it on in a considerably altered form. 1 Cf. De off. I, 6: Sequimur igitur hoc quidem tempore et hac in quaestione potissimum Stoicos, non ut interpretes, sed, ut solemus, e fontibus eorum iudicio arbitrioque nostro, quantum quoque modo videbitur, hauriemus (italics M. F.). Cf. De fin. I, 6. 262 Maximilian Forschner Among the stock of traditional doctrines which bear his stamp is a predominantly moral reading of the Stoic concept of virtue,2 a concept developed in exemplary manner in De officiis, the very work which has ensured the lasting influence of this idea even until the present day. This paper3 pursues a twofold goal: its primary intention is to argue that the Stoic conception of virtue was not, originally, a predominantly moral one; in demonstrating this the paper is also intended to sketch the reasons for Cicero’s undertaking of such moralisation. As far as the first goal is concerned, I am guided by the assumption that neither the central dogma of the Stoics' philosophy, i. e. the identification of virtue with happiness, nor the peculiarity of their doctrine of the emotions, can be understood without consideration of the central role theoria must have played in their idea of the perfect human life. With regard to the second goal, I am guided by the idea that this (necessarily "dogmatic") role of theoria did not fit in with Cicero's form of academic scepticism. He was, therefore, inclined if not forced to modify and downgrade it . It seems to me that the leading role originally played by theoria within the Stoic concept of virtue is still detectable in Cicero, 2 Originally it was Ariston of Chios, the cynic-sceptic disciple of Zeno, who in a self-willed way moralized the Stoic concept of virtue. It probably makes good sense when in the doxographic context of Tusc. V, beside Zeno, the founder and head of the Stoic school, only Ariston of Chios is mentioned (V, 21; V, 33). After all, we know Ariston wanted philosophy to be restricted to ethics; logic and physics seemed to him of no use for the ars vivendi nor for ethics, because we cannot reach exact and certain knowledge as far as the genuine objects of physics are concerned (cf. SVF I, 351 - 355; 378; Steinmetz 1994, 560). The "heresy" of Ariston’s position presumably touched the essential role theoria has played within the frame of the "orthodox" Zenonian concept of virtue. And this could explain why Ariston, representing a cynic-sceptic variant of Stoic philosophy, was of some lasting importance for Cicero, as is manifest also in De finibus (III, 11; 12; 50) . 3 I am grateful to F. Buddensiek, M. Erler, W. Görler and J. Kulenkampff for their helpful comments on and critique of an earlier draft of this paper, and, above all, to W. Ertl for its English version. Theoria and Stoic Virtue 263 whenever he is simply reporting Stoic doctrine, or where he argues for a Stoic position using his sceptical speech and counter-speech method. As I shall try to show, exactly this is demonstrated in an exemplary manner in the Tusculanae. But even there, the original conception of virtue is overshadowed by Cicero's own view which, notwithstanding the acknowledgement of the outstanding rank of theoretical wisdom,4 in respect of which we are similar to the gods, is primarily concerned with engagement in the societas vitae.5 By nature, man strives for knowledge; exploring, inquiring, and contemplating basic, hidden, difficult, and miraculous things are activities closest to our nature6 and accordingly this striving is "the one most delightful food of the soul".7 But the striving which supports the agitatio mentis and keeps it going finds no rest in this life (because of the earthly state of the human soul)8 and our knowledge (of nature and its underlying order) in fact remains defective and dubious.9 Only after death, when it has left behind its earthly weight, the pressure of desire, its neediness and its vulnerability (if this should ever come to pass), will the most splendid thing be possible for the human soul: namely, the divine and unhindered knowing contemplation of heavenly and earthly things. In virtue of this anthropologically based sceptical position Cicero seems to hold the view that the most important task for man is the political and moral care of society and the concomitant actio vitae.10 In a wholly non-Stoic manner he therefore divides life into the realms of otium and negotium and relates theoria to otium. It is for 4 Cf. De off. I, 13; I, 18. 5 Cf. De off. I, 19; I, 22. 6 De off. I, 18: maxime naturam attingit humanam. 7 Tusc V, 66: unus suavissimus pastus animorum; cf. De off. I, 13. 8 De off. I, 19: ... agitatio mentis, quae numquam adquiescit ... 9 Cf. W. Burkert, Cicero als Platoniker und Skeptiker, in: Gymnasium 72 (1965), 175 - 200. This article most impressively reveals Cicero’s kind of scepticism concerning the genuine items of physics. 10 The only people who are exempt from the obligation to engage practically in public matters are those who are not fit for it or not capable of it because of their personal circumstances. Cf. De off. I, 71 sq. 264 Maximilian Forschner this reason that he castigates those who, because of their dominating interest in research and study, let down people who ought to be protected.11 He considers it to be a vitium that "some men bestow far too much eagerness on obscure, difficult, but unnecessary things"12, and he even characterises the life of first-rate philosophers as an "escape into leisure".13 It is for this reason that he has theoria reach a perfect state only in the hoped-for beyond.14 For this same reason, too, he passes lightly over the systematically important question of how in the Stoic position the cardinal virtues unite to form the unity of virtue15 and the question of how prudent and just conduct in everyday life results from Stoic wisdom. 1 The 5th and final conversation of the Tusculanae disputationes deals with the central and most controversial dogma of Stoic ethics, according to which virtue is sufficient for a happy life.17 It is a dogma the acceptance of which indicates decisively membership or otherwise of the School, and a dogma which - from the very beginning - has clearly marked the frontier between competing philosophical positions.18 This doctrine of the self-sufficiency of virtue must seem to be paradoxical, if not absurd, against the background of a modern conception of ethics, be this conception Kantian or utilitarian. In fact, this impression of paradox was appreciated in antiquity as well. People then were also acquainted with the fickleness of fate, with the 11 Cf. De off. I, 29: discendi enim studio impediti, quos tueri debent, deserunt. 12 De off. I, 19. 13 Cf. De off. I, 69. 14 Cf. Tusc. I, 42 - 47. 15 Cf. De off. I, 15. 16 Cf. Tusc. V, 72. 17 Tusc. V, 1: virtutem ad beate vivendum se ipsa esse contentam. 18 Cf. Tusc. V, 32 - 33. Theoria and Stoic Virtue 265 endangerment of institutions, and with the fragility and proneness to suffering of human life. Right at the beginning of the conversation, Cicero's scepticism readily adds its voice to the vox populi: "It is to be feared that as regards our hope for a happy life we may not base our confidence on virtue, but we must rather, it seems, resort to prayers".19 And he does indeed formulate a prayer in the prooimion, but the addressee is not one of the great divine figures which popular faith believed to be benevolent, but an elitist, completely rational institution, i.
Recommended publications
  • Cicero on the Gods and Roman Religious Practices
    Studia Antiqua et Archaeologica 23(2): 303–313 Cicero on the gods and Roman religious practices Arina BRAGOVA1 Abstract. The article analyses Cicero’s attitude to gods, religion, divination, and superstition. Cicero follows tradition in acknowledging the existence of the gods, considering them immortal, blissful, animate, and anthropomorphic. He is ambivalent about the interaction between the gods and people. Cicero considers religion important for the Roman people because this was the popular belief — it was not his own viewpoint. Cicero thinks that people obtain divination from the gods. According to Cicero, there are two types of divination: artificial (auspices, haruspices, divination by lightning, stars, and other signs of nature) and natural (predictions in a dream, in a state of ecstasy, before death). In relation to divination, we see how multi- dimensional Cicero’s beliefs were: as a philosopher, he can accept or deny divination; as a Roman politician, he regards divination as an important instrument of the Roman religious rituals. Cicero opposes superstition to religion in his theological works, but in his secular works, he uses superstition and religion as synonyms. Rezumat. În articolul de față este analizată atitudinea lui Cicero față de zei, religie, divinație și superstiție. Cicero urmează tradiția recunoscând existența zeilor și considerându-i nemuritori, cu suflet și antropomorfi. El este ambivalent în ceea ce privește interacțiunea divinitate-oameni. Cicero consideră că religia este importantă pentru romani ca o consecință a unei tradiții populare — nu era propriul său punct de vedre. Divinația, în viziunea lui, se putea obține de la zei. După Cicero, există două tipuri de divinație: artificială (auspicii, haruspicii, divinație prin fulger, stele, alte semne ale naturii) și naturală (preziceri într-un vis, într-o stare de extaz, înainte de moarte).
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Sides and the Prehistory of Impartiality
    1. PREHISTORIES OF IMPARTIALITY TAKING SIDES AND THE PREHISTORY OF IMPARTIALITY Anita Traninger 1. Introduction: Taking Sides In his article “Taking Sides in Philosophy”, Gilbert Ryle inveighs against the ‘party-labels’ commonly awarded in philosophy. He impugns in partic- ular the conventional requirement to declare to what school one belongs because ‘[t]here is no place for “isms” in philosophy’.1 In concluding, how- ever, he is prepared to make ‘a few concessions’: Although, as I think, the motive of allegiance to a school or a leader is a non- philosophic and often an anti-philosophic motive, it may have some good results. Partisanship does generate zeal, combativeness, and team-spirit. [. .] Pedagogically, there is some utility in the superstition that philosophers are divided into Whigs and Tories. For we can work on the match-winning propensities of the young, and trick them into philosophizing by encourag- ing them to try to “dish” the Rationalists, or “scupper” the Hedonists.2 Even though Ryle chooses to reduce the value of taking sides to a propae- deutic set-up as a helpmeet for the young to come up with striking argu- ments, what he describes is precisely the modus operandi of dialectics, which had since antiquity been the methodological basis of philosophy. Dialectics conceived of thinking as a dialogue, and an agonistic one at that: it consisted in propounding a thesis and attacking it through questions. Problems were conceived of as being a choice between two positions, whence the name the procedure received in Roman times: in utramque partem disserere, arguing both sides of a question or arguing pro and con- tra.
    [Show full text]
  • The Self-Sufficiency of the Good Man Against the Need for Friendship
    THE SELF-SUFFICIENCY OF THE GOOD MAN AGAINST THE NEED FOR FRIENDSHIP. A DISCUSSION CONCERNING THE IMPORTANCE OF FRIENDSHIP FOR THE GOOD MAN IN CICERO. CORY SLOAN SUBMITTED WITH A VIEW TO OBTAIN THE DEGREE OF M.LITT. NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF IRELAND, MAYNOOTH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, FACULTY OR ARTS, CELTIC STUDIES, AND PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2012 HEAD OF DEPARTMENT DR. MICHAEL DUNNE SUPERVISED BY DR. AMOS EDELHEIT 1 Summary Cicero wrote in Book Three of On Duties, that the Stoic sage being absolutely good and and perfect was the only one that could be truly happy. For his happiness was based in his virtue and as he had perfect virtue, he had perfect and lasting happiness. Yet the Peripatetics saw that happiness was not a self-sufficient idea and was instead an amalgamation of external goods. Virtue for them was a factor that contributed to happiness, for the Stoics it was essential for happiness. It would appear on inital observation that the life of the Stoic sage was a solitary one, aloof from the rest of humanity. Yet the Stoics maintained that this was the best and happiest form of life, a life lived in accordance with Nature. However, the Peripatetics maintained that nature loves nothing solitary and man is not a solitary animal. In order for him to fullfill his natural end and achieve eudaimonia he would natually be drawn towards the company of others. Cicero highlights the tension between Stoic idealism and Peripatetic pragmatism in his discussion on happiness. When he essentially he askes in Book Five of the Tusculan Disputations.
    [Show full text]
  • Sondaggi Sulla Presenza Di Pitagora Negli Scritti Ciceroniani: Le Sezioni Frammentarie Del De Re Publica E Il De Legibus
    Sondaggi sulla presenza di Pitagora negli scritti ciceroniani: le sezioni frammentarie del De re publica e il De legibus Andrea Balbo DOI – 10.7358/erga-2013-002-balb ABSTraCT – This paper is a part of a research work concerning Pythagoras’ importance in Cicero’s thought and aims to describe some aspects of the role of Pythagoras’ figure in Cicero’s treatises De re publica and De legibus (with exception for Somnium Scipionis). The analysis will deal with the passages where Pythagoras is mentioned or there is an explicit reference to Pythagoric doctrine; a little appendix concerns some little references to Architas, Zaleucus and Carondas: rep. 1, 16; 1, 59; 1, 60; 2, 28; 2, 29; 3, 19; leg. 1, 33; 2, 14; 2, 26. From the examination of the passages it is possible to extract the certainty of the importance of Pythagoric thought in Cicero’s works, even if it is impossible to define exactly the boundaries of this influence, because many Pythagoric elements were a part of the Roman cultural context in this age. KEYWOrdS – Cicero, Pythagoras, De re publica, De legibus, Philosophy. 1. PREMESSA Il presente contributo costituisce il seguito dell’articolo Alcuni sondaggi sulla presenza di Pitagora negli scritti ciceroniani. Le opere del 56-54 a.C. in corso di pubblicazione per gli atti del convegno «Les Présocratiques chez Cicéron» (Université de Paris IV Sorbonne, Paris), dove mi ero occupato di alcuni passi in cui compariva il nome di Pitagora all’interno delle orazio- ni In Vatinium e Pro Scauro e del De oratore. In questo lavoro, seguendo lo stesso criterio, intendo riservare attenzione al De re publica e al De legibus 1, due opere che si collocano immediatamente dopo la composizione della 1 Non mi occupo qui del complesso problema della datazione del De legibus, per i cui dati essenziali rimando alla cronologia di N.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero on the Philosophy of Religion
    CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by John Patrick Frederick Wynne January 2008 CICERO ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION: DE NATURA DEORUM AND DE DIVINATIONE. John Patrick Frederick Wynne, Ph. D. Cornell University, 2008 Cicero wrote de Natura Deorum (dND), de Divinatione (Div.) and de Fato (Fat.) in succession and describes the latter two as continuations of the first. I argue that the three dialogues form a trilogy, in which Cicero as author indicates a stance on the material he presents (but that too little of the fragmentary Fat. remains to be useful for my purposes). There are much-debated attributions of preferences to Cicero’s propriae personae at the conclusions of dND and Div.; I take these preferences to express Cicero’s authorial stance. I examine relevant parts of the speeches to which they react and, first, make philosophical interpretations of each (often comparing other sources for Hellenistic thought) and, second, pay attention to the interaction of Cicero’s characterization of each speaker with the arguments the speaker gives. I find that Balbus in dND advocates the avoidance of superstition and the reform of religious beliefs in line with Stoic physics and that Cotta has a strong commitment to traditional Roman religious views consistent with his sceptical epistemology. Cotta’s scepticism is elusive in its details but perhaps yields a kind of fideism. I find that Quintus Cicero’s advocacy in Div.
    [Show full text]
  • CICERO in the ENCYCLOPAEDIA of GIORGIO VALLA 1. Introduction Cicero Has Been a Fundamental Reference Point for School Education
    «Ciceroniana On Line» IV, 2, 2020, 317-335 AMEDEO A. RASCHIERI CICERO IN THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA OF GIORGIO VALLA 1. Introduction Cicero has been a fundamental reference point for school education and the system of artes liberales, especially for rhetoric and philosophy, from ancient times to the Renaissance. Although many scholars have written on this subject, even in recent times, much research remains to be done, especially on the diffusion of Cicero’s work and thought dur- ing humanism and the Renaissance1. Nevertheless, it is interesting to consider how Cicero’s influence in university education and literary culture changed during humanism. To address this issue, I intend to fo- cus my attention on the Venetian environment in the second half of the 15th century2. In this context, many important phenomena co-existed: the tumultuous development of the art of printing, the wide diffusion of the study of Greek and Greek authors, and a renewed attention to the natural sciences that was conveyed by Greek works3. In particular, my discussion focuses on Giorgio Valla, a humanist who was trained in the Milanese area but carried out his teaching ac- tivity in Venice for an extended period. He distinguished himself 1 Cf., for example, Cox-Ward 2006, Steel 2013 (in particular: A.M. Gowing, Tully’s boat: responses to Cicero in imperial period, 233-250; S. MacCormack, Cicero in late antiqui- ty, 251-305; D. Marsh, Cicero in Renaissance, 306-317), La Bua 2019. On Renaissance rheto- ric cf. Green-Murphy 2006, Mack 2011, MacDonald 2017, 377-474. For Cicero’s rhetoric in the Renaissance, cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero's Style
    MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page i CICERO’S STYLE MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page ii MNEMOSYNE BIBLIOTHECA CLASSICA BATAVA COLLEGERUNT H. PINKSTER • H. S. VERSNEL D.M. SCHENKEVELD • P. H. SCHRIJVERS S.R. SLINGS BIBLIOTHECAE FASCICULOS EDENDOS CURAVIT H. PINKSTER, KLASSIEK SEMINARIUM, OUDE TURFMARKT 129, AMSTERDAM SUPPLEMENTUM DUCENTESIMUM QUADRAGESIMUM QUINTUM MICHAEL VON ALBRECHT CICERO’S STYLE MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page iii CICERO’S STYLE A SYNOPSIS FOLLOWED BY SELECTED ANALYTIC STUDIES BY MICHAEL VON ALBRECHT BRILL LEIDEN • BOSTON 2003 MNS-245-albrecht.qxd 03/04/2003 12:13 Page iv This book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Albrecht, Michael von. Cicero’s Style: a synopsis / by Michael von Albrecht. p. cm. – (Mnemosyne, bibliotheca classica Batava. Supplementum ; 245) Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 90-04-12961-8 1. Cicero, Marcus Tullius–Literary style. 2. Speeches, addresses, etc., Latin–History and criticism. 3. Latin language–Style. 4. Rhetoric, Ancient. 5. Oratory, Ancient. I. Title. II. Series. PA6357.A54 2003 875’.01–dc21 2003045375 ISSN 0169-8958 ISBN 90 04 12961 8 © Copyright 2003 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910 Danvers, MA 01923, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero As a Source for Epicurus
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Undergraduate Humanities Forum 2016-2017: Penn Humanities Forum Undergraduate Translation Research Fellows 5-2017 Cicero as a Source for Epicurus Kyle Tebo University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2017 Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Tebo, Kyle, "Cicero as a Source for Epicurus" (2017). Undergraduate Humanities Forum 2016-2017: Translation. 1. https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2017/1 This paper was part of the 2016-2017 Penn Humanities Forum on Translation. Find out more at http://wolfhumanities.upenn.edu/annual-topics/translation. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2017/1 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cicero as a Source for Epicurus Disciplines Arts and Humanities Comments This paper was part of the 2016-2017 Penn Humanities Forum on Translation. Find out more at http://wolfhumanities.upenn.edu/annual-topics/translation. This thesis or dissertation is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/uhf_2017/1 Cicero as a Source for Epicurus Kyle Tebo 2016–2017 Penn Humanities Forum Undergraduate Research Fellow University of Pennsylvania Cicero’s writings are often cited as key sources for learning about the philosophy of Epicurus. In the last years of his life Cicero hatched an impressive project to bring philosophy, which had to that point been a discipline conducted entirely in Greek, into Latin. Cicero’s philosophical project included examining some of the more popular ideas in circulation, discussing their content and criticizing or accepting them as Cicero himself saw fit. This was by no means a merely intellectual project nor was Cicero scrupulously impartial towards the various ideas he took up.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interpreter and a Latin Creator of the Aristotelian Platonic Tradition of Thought
    Philosophy Study, May 2020, Vol. 10, No. 5, 320-328 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2020.05.006 D DAVID PUBLISHING The Traditions of Thought Between Progress and Reaction. Cicero: An Interpreter and a Latin Creator of the Aristotelian Platonic Tradition of Thought Giuseppe Boscarino The Italic School, Sortino, Italy Farington’s interpretation of the philosophies of Plato and Cicero as reactionary philosophies is discussed. In the light of our interpretative category, such as that of Traditions of Thought, understood as complex rational, historical constructions, within which metaphysical and epistemological principles are mediated with socio-economic-political-cultural conflicts, all denominated as ideologies, instead it is believed that scientific theories are not actually progressive or regressive, but rather the ideologies, when they interpret the concepts of scientific fact, scientific theory and, more strongly, that of philosophy, within general conceptions of the world. In the light of our interpretative category, they thus appear more than regressive philosophers instead of regressive ideologues, if we consider that the philosopher moves within the narrower fields of the so-called metaphysics and epistemology. Cicero also appears to be the great Latin creator of a way of understanding philosophy and its history with the dominant triad Socrates-Plato-Aristotele in it. All this must be considered within my broader historical-philosophical-epistemological elaboration, enclosed in my published books and papers, cited in references. Keywords:
    [Show full text]
  • Brill's Companion to Cicero
    BRILL’S COMPANION TO CICERO This page intentionally left blank May.vw.c 30-07-2002 10:22 Pagina 3 BRILL’S COMPANION TO CICERO Oratory and Rhetoric EDITED BY JAMES M. MAY BRILL LEIDEN • BOSTON • KÖLN 2002 May.vw.c 30-07-2002 10:22 Pagina 4 The illumination on the cover of this book is from a fifteenth-century edition of Cicero’s orationes (Florence, Biblioteca Medicea Laurenziana, MS Plut. 48.8, c. 2r). Reproduced with permission from the Ministero per i Beni e le Attività Culturali. This book is printed on acid-free paper Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Brill´s companion to Cicero : oratory and rhetoric / edited by James M. May p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 9004121471 1Cicero, Marcus Tullius. Speeches. 2. Speeches, addresses, etc., Latin—History and criticism. 3. Rome—History—Republic, 265-30 B.C.—Sources. 4.Cicero, Marcus Tullius. Rhetorical works. 5. Rhetoric, Ancient. I. May, James M. PA6285 .B75 2002 875’.01—dc21 2002066555 Die Deutsche Bibliothek - CIP-Einheitsaufnahme Brill’s companion to Cicero : oratory and rhetoric / ed. by James M. May. – Leiden ; Boston ; Köln : Brill, 2002 ISBN 90-04-12147-1 ISBN 90 04 12147 1 © Copyright 2002 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910 Danvers, MA 01923, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero on the Emotions : Tusculan Disputations  and  / Translated and with Commentary by Margaret Graver
    Translated and with Commentary by MARGARET G RAVER Margaret Graver is assistant professor of classics at Dartmouth College. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London ௠ by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published Printed in the United States of America ISBN (cloth): --- ISBN (paper): --- Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Cicero, Marcus Tullius. [Tusculanae disputationes. English. Selections] Cicero on the emotions : Tusculan disputations and / translated and with commentary by Margaret Graver. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN --- (alk. paper) — ISBN --- (pbk. : alk. paper) . Emotions—Early works to . Happiness—Early works to . I. Graver, Margaret. II. Title. PA.T G Ј.—dc o The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z.-. PREFACE vii ABBREVIATIONS AND MATTERS OF CITATION ix INTRODUCTION xi ABOUT THE TRANSLATION xxxvii A NOTEONTHETEXT xli TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS BOOK 3 3 BOOK 4 39 COMMENTARY BOOK 3: ON GRIEF 73 BOOK 4: ON EMOTIONS 129 APPENDIXES: SOURCES FOR CICERO’S ACCOUNT APPENDIX A. CRANTOR AND THE CONSOLATORY 187 TRADITION APPENDIX B. EPICURUS AND THE CYRENAICS 195 vi APPENDIX C. THE EARLY STOICS AND 203 CHRYSIPPUS APPENDIX D. POSIDONIUS 215 BIBLIOGRAPHY 225 INDEX LOCORUM 233 GENERAL INDEX 245 The third and fourth books of Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations present the reader with a self-contained treatise on the nature and management of human emotion. Cicero sets himself the task of presenting, first for grief, then for emotions in general, the insights that had been gained in Greece over many years through philosophical debate and also through practical experience in the ancient equivalent of psychotherapy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dispute Concerning Rhetoric in Hellenistic Thought
    % © 2011, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525252949 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647252940 Hypomnemata Untersuchungen zur Antike und zu ihrem Nachleben Herausgegeben von Albrecht Dihle, Siegmar Döpp, Dorothea Frede, Hans-Joachim Gehrke, Günther Patzig, Christoph Riedweg, Gisela Striker Band 185 Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht © 2011, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525252949 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647252940 Yosef Z. Liebersohn The Dispute concerning Rhetoric in Hellenistic Thought Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht © 2011, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525252949 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647252940 Verantwortliche Herausgeberin: Gisela Striker Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.d-nb.de abrufbar ISBN 978-3-525-25294-9 Hypomnemata ISSN 0085-1671 Umschlagabbildung: Cluny (Burgund, Frankreich), ehemalige Benediktinerabtei. Die Rhetorik. Skulptur, um 1095/1115. Ausschnit aus einem Kapitell mit Personifikation der sieben freien Künste. Yvan Travert/akg-images. ’ 2010, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen / Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht LLC, Oakville, CT, U.S.A. www.v-r.de Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Das Werk und seine Teile sind urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung in anderen als den gesetzlich zugelassenen Fällen bedarf der vorherigen schriftlichen Einwilligung des Verlages. Hinweis zu
    [Show full text]