1 Existence and the Empty Set 2 the Axiom of Pairing

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Existence and the Empty Set 2 the Axiom of Pairing Naive Set Theory Sec 03 Jeyan Burns-Oorjitham https://jeyoor.com 1 Existence and The Empty Set For now, we assume that there exists a set. Later, we will have more advanced assumptions of existence. If a set exists, then we can show as a consequence that there exists a set with no elements. We can find this empty set by applying the Axiom of Specification with a sentence that excludes all the elements within the set. A sentence that is always false (such as x 6= x) will exclude all elements within the set. The empty set is denoted ;. 1.1 Empty Set as a Subset The empty set is a subset of every set. 8A[; ⊂ A] At first, this vacuous truth may seem strange or counterintuitive. However, we can illuminate this fact with a bit of logical argument. Consider what would be required to prove this statement false. By the definition of ⊂, we would have to find an element within ; which does not exist in A for some set A. However, ; has no elements. Thus, the statement can never be shown to be false. Thus, the statement is true. 2 The Axiom of Pairing For any two sets B and C, there exists a set D to which both B and C belong. 8B; C[9D[B 2 D ^ C 2 D]] 2.1 Discussion and Terminology This axiom provides a powerful tool for constructing new sets. It can be repeatedly applied to construct larger and larger sets from multiple elements. It is important to note that, by itself, the Axiom of Pairing does not limit its contents to only the elements listed. In the specific language of the theorem above, D may contain elements other than B and C. However, the Axiom of Extension could be applied to reduce D to only B and C as follows: Let E be the elements f in D for which f = B or f = C. E = ff 2 D : f = B _ f = Cg 1 Naive Set Theory Sec 03 Burns-Oorjitham 2 The generality of set theoretic language allows us to relabel the sets above without changing meaning as long as we do not modify any of the criteria. In other words, 8G; H[9I[G 2 I ^ H 2 I]] and J = fi 2 I : i = G _ i = Hg are equivalent statements to the ones earlier in this section. By the Axiom of Extension, J is unique. (Any other set that met the criteria used to specify J would, in fact, be J itself.) A set specified in this way via a combination of the Axiom of Pairing and the Axiom of Extension is called an unordered pair. An unordered pair containing sets K and L is often denoted fK; Lg. 2.2 Second Look at Notation We can use slightly different notation to restate some of the previous statements to emphasize their importance. Let M(n) be the sentence n = o _ n = p where o and p are both sets. Then, the axiom of pairing states: There will always exist some set N such that [n 2 N () M(n) is true] Let Y represent this statement. The axiom of specification, applied to set Q states There exists a set R such that [r 2 R () (r 2 Q ^ M(r) is true)] Let Z represent this statement. Z is equivalent to the Axiom of Specification with M(r) as the sentence. Y is equivalent to the Axiom of Pairing for o and p. Thus, Y can be viewed as a pseudo special case of Z. The Axiom of Pairing alone does not specify uniqueness. However, if we are able to use the Axiom of Pairing to show that a set containing o and p exists, we can then apply the Axiom of Specification to create a unique set that only contains o and p. This pattern of showing that a set exists containing all elements having a certain property, and then showing that there is a unique subset only those elements having the given property, will be repeated several times in the sections ahead. 3 Singletons Let S be any set. By the Axiom of Pairing, we can form the unordered pair fS; Sg. Since it contains only one element, such an unordered pair is often written simply as fSg and referred to as a singleton. A singleton can likewise be uniquely defined as a set that has S as its only element. Per the discussion above, ; and femptysetg are different sets. The first set has no elements. The second set has one element, namely ;. The statement B 2 C is the same as fBg ⊂ C Naive Set Theory Sec 03 Burns-Oorjitham 3 4 Repeated Applications of Pairing 4.1 Motivation The Axiom of Pairing implies that any two sets D and E are both members of some other set F = fD; Eg. It also implies that every individual set G belongs to a set fGg. From these basic implications, larger and larger sets can be constructed. For example, consider these sets: ;; f;g; ff;gg; fff;ggg From these sets, we may construct unordered pairs such as f;; f;gg Each of the preceding singletons or pairs constructed could be combined into still larger pairs or singletons, and so on. 4.2 Exercise Are all of the sets constructed in 4.1 unique? 4.3 Solution Yes, all of the sets constructed in this way are unique. Here is a proof provided by gblikas via GitHub Let H and I be any different sets formed in the manner described in 4.1. By the Axiom of Specification, H is the only set which contains exactly the elements in H. Likewise, I is the only set which contains exactly the elements in I. We will prove that H 6= I by contradiction. Assume H = I. Statement 1: Since H = I, for all h 2 H, h 2 I and for all i 2 I, i 2 H. The sets formed in ?? are either unordered pairs or singletons. • If H and I are singletons, H = fhg and I = fig. By Statement 1 and the Axiom of Extension, h = i. Since h = i, H and I must have been formed in the same way. This contradicts the fact that H and I were formed differently. • If H and I are unordered pairs, H = fh; h0g and I = fi; i0g. By Statement 1 and the Axiom of Extension, either [h = i ^ h0 = i0] or [h = i0 ^ h0 = i] { If [h = i ^ h0 = i0], then H and I must have been formed in the same manner (because their respective elements are the same). This contradicts the fact that H and I were formed differently. { If [h = i0 ^ h0 = i], then H and I must have been formed in the same manner (because their respective elements are the same. This contradicts the fact that H and I were formed differently. In every case, the assumption that H = I leads to a contradiction. Therefore, H 6= I. Naive Set Theory Sec 03 Burns-Oorjitham 4 5 Third Look at Notation There are several ways to denote some of the sets we have seen so far. Recall statement Y from 2.2 which was written [n 2 N () [n = o _ n = p]] We could equivalently describe N like this fn : n = o _ n = pg We could similarly describe the set N as fo; pg. This more compact representation will be used where possible. If J(q) is a sentence that produces a valid set of qs, then we can denote that set as fq : J(q)g. We can even describe an arbitrary set K as fl : l 2 Kg If we want to restrict K to only items that meet some criteria M(l), we can shorten fl : l 2 K ^ M(l)g down to fl 2 K : M(l)g Additionally, fx : x 6= xg = ; and fx : x = ag = fag As proven toward the end of Section 2, if R(s) is (s = s), then fs : R(s)g is not a set (there is no universe). Simlarly, if T (s) is (s2 = s), then fs : T (s)g is not a set. Although the structures described by T and S are not sets and thus will not be discussed further in these notes, it is possible to create a theory that addresses them. Most theories that include objects such as those described by T and S refer to them as classes. For more information on classes, see a textbook or course on axiomatic set theory such as Discovering Modern Set Theory by Winfried Just and Martin Weese..
Recommended publications
  • A Taste of Set Theory for Philosophers
    Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, Vol. XXVII, No. 2. A Special Issue on "Logic and Philosophy Today", 143-163, 2010. Reprinted in "Logic and Philosophy Today" (edited by A. Gupta ans J.v.Benthem), College Publications vol 29, 141-162, 2011. A taste of set theory for philosophers Jouko Va¨an¨ anen¨ ∗ Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Helsinki and Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam November 17, 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Elementary set theory 2 3 Cardinal and ordinal numbers 3 3.1 Equipollence . 4 3.2 Countable sets . 6 3.3 Ordinals . 7 3.4 Cardinals . 8 4 Axiomatic set theory 9 5 Axiom of Choice 12 6 Independence results 13 7 Some recent work 14 7.1 Descriptive Set Theory . 14 7.2 Non well-founded set theory . 14 7.3 Constructive set theory . 15 8 Historical Remarks and Further Reading 15 ∗Research partially supported by grant 40734 of the Academy of Finland and by the EUROCORES LogICCC LINT programme. I Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, Vol. XXVII, No. 2. A Special Issue on "Logic and Philosophy Today", 143-163, 2010. Reprinted in "Logic and Philosophy Today" (edited by A. Gupta ans J.v.Benthem), College Publications vol 29, 141-162, 2011. 1 Introduction Originally set theory was a theory of infinity, an attempt to understand infinity in ex- act terms. Later it became a universal language for mathematics and an attempt to give a foundation for all of mathematics, and thereby to all sciences that are based on mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Indiscernible Pairs of Countable Sets of Reals at a Given Projective Level
    Indiscernible pairs of countable sets of reals at a given projective level Vladimir Kanovei∗ Vassily Lyubetsky† January 1, 2020 Abstract 1 Using an invariant modification of Jensen’s “minimal Π2 singleton” forcing, we define a model of ZFC, in which, for a given n ≥ 2, there exists 1 an Πn unordered pair of non-OD (hence, OD-indiscernible) countable sets 1 of reals, but there is no Σn unordered pairs of this kind. Any two reals x1 6= x2 are discernible by a simple formula ϕ(x) := x < r for a suitable rational r. Therefore, the lowest (type-theoretic) level of sets where one may hope to find indiscernible elements, is the level of sets of reals. And in- deed, identifying the informal notion of definability with the ordinal definability (OD), one finds indiscernible sets of reals in appropriate generic models. Example 1. If reals a 6= b in 2ω form a Cohen-generic pair over L, then ω the constructibility degrees [a]L = {x ∈ 2 : L[x] = L[a]} and [b]L are OD- indiscernible disjoint sets of reals in L[a, b], by rather straightforward forcing arguments, see [2, Theorem 3.1] and a similar argument in [3, Theorem 2.5]. Example 2. As observed in [5], if reals a 6= b in 2ω form a Sacks-generic pair over L, then the constructibility degrees [a]L and [b]L still are OD-indiscernible disjoint sets in L[a, b], with the additional advantage that the unordered pair arXiv:1912.12962v1 [math.LO] 30 Dec 2019 {[a]L, [b]L } is an OD set in L[a, b] because [a]L, [b]L are the only two minimal degrees in L[a, b].
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE THOMAS J. JECH State University of New York at Bufalo and The Institute for Advanced Study Princeton, New Jersey 1973 NORTH-HOLLAND PUBLISHING COMPANY - AMSTERDAM LONDON AMERICAN ELSEVIER PUBLISHING COMPANY, INC. - NEW YORK 0 NORTH-HOLLAND PUBLISHING COMPANY - 1973 AN Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the Copyright owner. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 73-15535 North-Holland ISBN for the series 0 7204 2200 0 for this volume 0 1204 2215 2 American Elsevier ISBN 0 444 10484 4 Published by: North-Holland Publishing Company - Amsterdam North-Holland Publishing Company, Ltd. - London Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada: American Elsevier Publishing Company, Inc. 52 Vanderbilt Avenue New York, N.Y. 10017 PRINTED IN THE NETHERLANDS To my parents PREFACE The book was written in the long Buffalo winter of 1971-72. It is an attempt to show the place of the Axiom of Choice in contemporary mathe- matics. Most of the material covered in the book deals with independence and relative strength of various weaker versions and consequences of the Axiom of Choice. Also included are some other results that I found relevant to the subject. The selection of the topics and results is fairly comprehensive, nevertheless it is a selection and as such reflects the personal taste of the author. So does the treatment of the subject. The main tool used throughout the text is Cohen’s method of forcing.
    [Show full text]
  • On Equivalents of Well-Foundedness
    On Equivalents of Wellfoundedness An experiment in Mizar Piotr Rudnicki Department of Computing Science University of Alberta Canada email piotrcsualbertaca Andrzej Trybulec Institute of Mathematics Warsaw University in Bialystok Poland email trybulecmathuwbedupl Received Accepted in nal form Abstract Four statements equivalent to wellfoundedness wellfounded induction existence of recursively dened functions uniqueness of recursively dened func tions and absence of descending chains have b een proved in Mizar and the pro ofs mechanicall y checked for correctness It seems not to b e widely known that the existence without the uniqueness assumption of recursively dened functions implies wellfoundedness In the pro of we used regular cardinals a fairly advanced notion of set theory The theory of cardinals in Mizar was develop ed earlier by G Bancerek With the current state of the Mizar system the pro ofs turned out to b e an exercise with only minor additions at the fundamental level We would like to stress the imp ortance of a systematic development of a mechanized data base for mathematics in the spirit of the QED Pro ject ENOD Experience Not Only Doctrine G Kreisel Key words Mizar QED Pro ject set theory wellfoundedness regular cardinals Abbreviations The Mizar Mathematical Library MML Octob er Piotr Rudnicki and Andrzej Trybulec Contents Intro duction Mizar The Mizar language Anatomy and pro cessing of a Mizar article Builtin notions Set theory of Mizar The Mizar Mathematical Library Mizar abstracts How to learn
    [Show full text]
  • Codomain from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Contents
    Codomain From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Algebra of sets 1 1.1 Fundamentals ............................................. 1 1.2 The fundamental laws of set algebra .................................. 1 1.3 The principle of duality ........................................ 2 1.4 Some additional laws for unions and intersections .......................... 2 1.5 Some additional laws for complements ................................ 3 1.6 The algebra of inclusion ........................................ 3 1.7 The algebra of relative complements ................................. 4 1.8 See also ................................................ 5 1.9 References ............................................... 5 1.10 External links ............................................. 5 2 Axiom of choice 6 2.1 Statement ............................................... 6 2.1.1 Nomenclature ZF, AC, and ZFC ............................... 7 2.1.2 Variants ............................................ 7 2.1.3 Restriction to finite sets .................................... 7 2.2 Usage ................................................. 8 2.3 Examples ............................................... 8 2.4 Criticism and acceptance ....................................... 8 2.5 In constructive mathematics ..................................... 9 2.6 Independence ............................................. 10 2.7 Stronger axioms ............................................ 10 2.8 Equivalents .............................................. 10 2.8.1 Category
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory – an Overview 1 of 34 Set Theory – an Overview Gary Hardegree Department of Philosophy University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003
    Hardegree, Set Theory – An Overview 1 of 34 Set Theory – An Overview Gary Hardegree Department of Philosophy University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003 1. Membership ...................................................................................................................... 2 2. Extensionality ................................................................................................................... 2 3. The Empty Set .................................................................................................................. 2 4. Simple Sets; Singletons, Doubletons, etc. ........................................................................ 2 5. Pure and Impure Sets ....................................................................................................... 4 6. Set-Abstraction ................................................................................................................. 4 7. Set-Abstract Conversion .................................................................................................. 5 8. Propriety and Impropriety Among Set-Abstracts ............................................................ 5 9. Simple Sets Revisited ....................................................................................................... 6 10. Specific Set-Abstraction ................................................................................................... 6 11. Generalized Set-Abstraction ...........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Representing Model Theory in a Type-Theoretical Logical Framework Fulya Horozal, Florian Rabe ∗ Jacobs University Bremen, Germany Article Info a B S T R a C T
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Theoretical Computer Science 412 (2011) 4919–4945 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Theoretical Computer Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs Representing model theory in a type-theoretical logical framework Fulya Horozal, Florian Rabe ∗ Jacobs University Bremen, Germany article info a b s t r a c t Keywords: In a broad sense, logic is the field of formal languages for knowledge and truth that have a Logical framework formal semantics. It tends to be difficult to give a narrower definition because very different Model theory kinds of logics exist. One of the most fundamental contrasts is between the different Proof theory First-order logic methods of assigning semantics. Here two classes can be distinguished: model theoretical Module system semantics based on a foundation of mathematics such as set theory, and proof theoretical semantics based on an inference system possibly formulated within a type theory. Logical frameworks have been developed to cope with the variety of available logics unifying the underlying ontological notions and providing a meta-theory to reason abstractly about logics. While these have been very successful, they have so far focused on either model or proof theoretical semantics. We contribute to a unified framework by showing how the type/proof theoretical Edinburgh Logical Framework (LF) can be applied to the representation of model theoretical logics. We give a comprehensive formal representation of first-order logic, covering both its proof and its model theoretical semantics as well as its soundness in LF.
    [Show full text]
  • The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis Implies the Axiom of Choice in Coq
    The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis Implies the Axiom of Choice in Coq Dominik Kirst Felix Rech Saarland University Saarland University Saarland Informatics Campus, Saarbrücken, Germany Saarland Informatics Campus, Saarbrücken, Germany [email protected] [email protected] Abstract between X and P¹Xº for every infinite X. Therefore, GCH We discuss and compare two Coq mechanisations of Sier- narrows the range of the power set operation otherwise left piński’s result that the generalised continuum hypothesis rather underspecified by the usual Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) (GCH) implies the axiom of choice (AC). The first version axioms. AC, in one typical set-theoretic formulation, states shows the result, originally stated in first-order ZF set-theory, that every set X of non-empty sets admits a choice function for a higher-order set theory convenient to work with in Coq. f such that f ¹xº 2 x for all x 2 X. The second version presents a corresponding theorem for That GCH as a statement about power sets and cardinal- Coq’s type theory itself, concerning type-theoretic formu- ity implies AC, a statement providing a means to uniformly lations of GCH and AC. Both versions rely on the classical pick elements from non-empty sets, may seem surprising law of excluded middle and extensionality assumptions but indeed [14]. However, since AC is equivalent to the well- we localise the use of axioms where possible. ordering theorem (WO), asserting that every (infinite) set can be well-ordered, and since well-orders transport along in- CCS Concepts: • Theory of computation ! Type the- jections, there is a well-established strategy how Sierpiński’s ory; Constructive mathematics; Higher order logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets, Relations, Functions
    Part I Sets, Relations, Functions 1 Chapter 1 Sets 1.1 Basics sfr:set:bas: Sets are the most fundamental building blocks of mathematical objects. In explanation sec fact, almost every mathematical object can be seen as a set of some kind. In logic, as in other parts of mathematics, sets and set-theoretical talk is ubiq- uitous. So it will be important to discuss what sets are, and introduce the notations necessary to talk about sets and operations on sets in a standard way. Definition 1.1 (Set). A set is a collection of objects, considered independently of the way it is specified, of the order of the objects in the set, or of their multiplicity. The objects making up the set are called elements or members of the set. If a is an element of a set X, we write a 2 X (otherwise, a2 = X). The set which has no elements is called the empty set and denoted by the symbol ;. Example 1.2. Whenever you have a bunch of objects, you can collect them together in a set. The set of Richard's siblings, for instance, is a set that contains one person, and we could write it as S = fRuthg. In general, when we have some objects a1,..., an, then the set consisting of exactly those objects is written fa1; : : : ; ang. Frequently we'll specify a set by some property that its elements share|as we just did, for instance, by specifying S as the set of Richard's siblings. We'll use the following shorthand notation for that: fx : : : : x : : :g, where the : : : x : : : stands for the property that x has to have in order to be counted among the elements of the set.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory and Logic
    SET THEORY AND LOGIC SET THEORY AND LOGIC by Robert R. Stoll Cle;laixi State University Dover Publications, Inc. NewYork Copyright Copyright (0 1961, 1963 by Robert R. Stoll. All rights reserved. Bibliographical Note This Dover edition, first published in 1979, is an unabridged and corrected republication of the work originally published in 1963 by W H. Freeman and Company. International Standard Book Number ISBN-13: 978-0-486-63829-4 ISBN-10: 0-486-63829-4 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 79-87812 Manufactured in the United States by Courier Corporation 63829412 To Kurt, Nancy, and David PREFACE This book is an outgrowth of a course which I have developed at Oberlin College for advanced undergraduates. The purpose of the course is to introduce students to the foundations of mathematics, to give them initial training in the axiomatic method in mathematics, and to provide them with the necessary tools to cope successfully with graduate level courses having an abstract and axiomatic orientation. It may be in- ferred that as I use the term "foundations of mathematics" I under- stand it to mean an analysis of fundamental concepts of mathematics, intended to serve as a preparation for studying the superstructure from a general and unified perspective. The book contains adequate material for any one of a variety of one- year upper undergraduate courses with a title resembling "Introduction to Foundations of Mathematics." That is, there is sufficient material for a year's course in which the instructor chooses to emphasize the construc- tion of standard mathematical systems, or the role of logic in connection with axiomatic theories, or, simply, mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • CDM [2Ex] Sets [3Ex]
    CDM Sets Klaus Sutner Carnegie Mellon University 10-sets 2017/12/15 23:22 1 Intuitive Set Theory Extensionality Frege's Ghost Products and Sums Cantor Formalization Beyond ZFC A Definition of Set 3 Here is a first attempt at a “definition” of sets. Definition A set is an arbitrary collection of objects. In the words of Georg Cantor: By an \aggregate" we are to understand any collection into a whole M of definite and separate objects m of our intuition or our thought. The objects are called \elements" of M. In signs we express this thus: M = fmg. Modern Notation 4 Cantor's symbolic notation is rather old-fashioned. Nowadays and following G. Peano one would usually write M = f m j P (m) g indicating that we wish to collect all objects m that have property P into a set M. This set formation principle is the core of set theory. As we will see in a while, it also causes major problems. But Why? 5 As it turns out, sets alone (well, plus a bit of logic) suffice as a foundation of more or less all of mathematics and computer science. Set theory provides an extremely powerful and even elegant way to organize and structure any discourse in this domain. On the face of it, this is a huge surprise: one would suspect that sets are nowhere near powerful enough to express concepts such as natural number, prime, group, field, real number, differentiable function, probability measure, finite state machine, computable function, complexity class, and so on. Bourbaki 6 The importance of sets can be seen in the fact that Bourbaki chose to dedicate his first volume to sets: I Set Theory II Algebra III Topology IV Functions of one real variable V Topological vector spaces VI Integration VII Commutative algebra VIII Lie groups In many ways, the Bourbaki approach is still the gold standard.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Set Theory by Sidney Felder in the Words of Georg Cantor
    Elements of Set Theory by SidneyFelder In the words of GeorgCantor (1845-1918) ,the creator of Set Theory and the modern theory of the Infinite, a set (or class) is “a collection into a whole, of definite, well-distinguished objects of our perception or of our thought”. In thinking about anything, we mentally aggregate and separate things in all kinds of combinations. In any such case, we are forming sets. On various occasions, it will be convenient to speak of sets such as the fol- lowing: the set containing the twophysicists Michael Faraday and Marie Curie; the set containing the numbers 1, 2, 3, and 4; the set of all evennumbers; the set of all copies of this Handout; the set of all possible legal sequences of movesinChess; the set of all legalsequences of movesinChess that terminate in a draw; the set of all persons who have just read the words “the words”; the set of all persons who have not read this paragraph; the set of all fundamental particles in the universe; the set of all sets enumerated in this list; the set of all finite or infinite sets of natural numbers that contain the number 1,000; the set of all ways to make change from a 1 dollar bill; the set of all Kings of the United States. We express in writing the fact that selected entities form a set by exhibiting the symbolic representations of these entities enclosed in a pair of oppositely facing curly brackets (or braces), { and }. Thus {9,18,27} rep- resents the set composed of the three numbers 9, 18, and 27.
    [Show full text]