Representing Model Theory in a Type-Theoretical Logical Framework Fulya Horozal, Florian Rabe ∗ Jacobs University Bremen, Germany Article Info a B S T R a C T
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more
Recommended publications
-
Lecture Slides
Program Verification: Lecture 3 Jos´eMeseguer Computer Science Department University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign 1 Algebras An (unsorted, many-sorted, or order-sorted) signature Σ is just syntax: provides the symbols for a language; but what is that language talking about? what is its semantics? It is obviously talking about algebras, which are the mathematical models in which we interpret the syntax of Σ, giving it concrete meaning. Unsorted algebras are the simplest example: children become familiar with them from the early awakenings of reason. They consist of a set of data elements, and various chosen constants among those elements, and operations on such data. 2 Algebras (II) For example, for Σ the unsorted signature of the module NAT-MIXFIX we can define many different algebras, such as the following: 1. IN, the algebra of natural numbers in whatever notation we wish (Peano, binary, base 10, etc.) with 0 interpreted as the zero element, s interpreted as successor, and + and * interpreted as natural number addition and multiplication. 2. INk, the algebra of residue classes modulo k, for k a nonzero natural number. This is a finite algebra whose set of elements can be represented as the set {0,...,k − 1}. We interpret 0 as 0, and for the other 3 operations we perform them in IN and then take the residue modulo k. For example, in IN7 we have 6+6=5. 3. Z, the algebra of the integers, with 0 interpreted as the zero element, s interpreted as successor, and + and * interpreted as integer addition and multiplication. 4. -
The Metamathematics of Putnam's Model-Theoretic Arguments
The Metamathematics of Putnam's Model-Theoretic Arguments Tim Button Abstract. Putnam famously attempted to use model theory to draw metaphysical conclusions. His Skolemisation argument sought to show metaphysical realists that their favourite theories have countable models. His permutation argument sought to show that they have permuted mod- els. His constructivisation argument sought to show that any empirical evidence is compatible with the Axiom of Constructibility. Here, I exam- ine the metamathematics of all three model-theoretic arguments, and I argue against Bays (2001, 2007) that Putnam is largely immune to meta- mathematical challenges. Copyright notice. This paper is due to appear in Erkenntnis. This is a pre-print, and may be subject to minor changes. The authoritative version should be obtained from Erkenntnis, once it has been published. Hilary Putnam famously attempted to use model theory to draw metaphys- ical conclusions. Specifically, he attacked metaphysical realism, a position characterised by the following credo: [T]he world consists of a fixed totality of mind-independent objects. (Putnam 1981, p. 49; cf. 1978, p. 125). Truth involves some sort of correspondence relation between words or thought-signs and external things and sets of things. (1981, p. 49; cf. 1989, p. 214) [W]hat is epistemically most justifiable to believe may nonetheless be false. (1980, p. 473; cf. 1978, p. 125) To sum up these claims, Putnam characterised metaphysical realism as an \externalist perspective" whose \favorite point of view is a God's Eye point of view" (1981, p. 49). Putnam sought to show that this externalist perspective is deeply untenable. To this end, he treated correspondence in terms of model-theoretic satisfaction. -
Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness . -
Foundational Proof Checkers with Small Witnesses
Foundational Proof Checkers with Small Witnesses Dinghao Wu Andrew W. Appel Aaron Stump Princeton University Washington University in St. Louis dinghao,appel @cs.princeton.edu [email protected] f g ABSTRACT tion of the proof witness to the size of the binary machine- Proof checkers for proof-carrying code (and similar) systems language program. Necula's LFi proof witnesses were about can suffer from two problems: huge proof witnesses and un- 4 times as big as the programs whose properties they proved. trustworthy proof rules. No previous design has addressed both of these problems simultaneously. We show the theory, Pfenning's Elf and Twelf systems [14, 15] are implementa- design, and implementation of a proof-checker that permits tions of the Edinburgh Logical Framework. In these sys- small proof witnesses and machine-checkable proofs of the tems, proof-search engines can be represented as logic pro- soundness of the system. grams, much like (dependently typed, higher-order) Prolog. Elf and Twelf build proof witnesses automatically; if each logic-program clause is viewed as an inference rule, then the 1. INTRODUCTION proof witness is a trace of the successful goals and subgoals In a proof-carrying code (PCC) system [10], or in other executed by the logic program. That is, the proof witness proof-carrying applications [3], an untrusted prover must is a tree whose nodes are the names of clauses and whose convince a trusted checker of the validity of a theorem by subtrees correspond to the subgoals of these clauses. sending a proof. Two of the potential problems with this approach are that the proofs might be too large, and that Necula's theorem provers were written in this style, origi- the checker might not be trustworthy. -
A Taste of Set Theory for Philosophers
Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, Vol. XXVII, No. 2. A Special Issue on "Logic and Philosophy Today", 143-163, 2010. Reprinted in "Logic and Philosophy Today" (edited by A. Gupta ans J.v.Benthem), College Publications vol 29, 141-162, 2011. A taste of set theory for philosophers Jouko Va¨an¨ anen¨ ∗ Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Helsinki and Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam November 17, 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Elementary set theory 2 3 Cardinal and ordinal numbers 3 3.1 Equipollence . 4 3.2 Countable sets . 6 3.3 Ordinals . 7 3.4 Cardinals . 8 4 Axiomatic set theory 9 5 Axiom of Choice 12 6 Independence results 13 7 Some recent work 14 7.1 Descriptive Set Theory . 14 7.2 Non well-founded set theory . 14 7.3 Constructive set theory . 15 8 Historical Remarks and Further Reading 15 ∗Research partially supported by grant 40734 of the Academy of Finland and by the EUROCORES LogICCC LINT programme. I Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, Vol. XXVII, No. 2. A Special Issue on "Logic and Philosophy Today", 143-163, 2010. Reprinted in "Logic and Philosophy Today" (edited by A. Gupta ans J.v.Benthem), College Publications vol 29, 141-162, 2011. 1 Introduction Originally set theory was a theory of infinity, an attempt to understand infinity in ex- act terms. Later it became a universal language for mathematics and an attempt to give a foundation for all of mathematics, and thereby to all sciences that are based on mathematics. -
FOUNDATIONS of RECURSIVE MODEL THEORY Mathematics Department, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Van Vleck Hall, 480 Lincoln Drive
Annals of Mathematical Logic 13 (1978) 45-72 © North-H011and Publishing Company FOUNDATIONS OF RECURSIVE MODEL THEORY Terrence S. MILLAR Mathematics Department, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Van Vleck Hall, 480 Lincoln Drive, Madison, WI 53706, U.S.A. Received 6 July 1976 A model is decidable if it has a decidable satisfaction predicate. To be more precise, let T be a decidable theory, let {0, I n < to} be an effective enumeration of all formula3 in L(T), and let 92 be a countable model of T. For any indexing E={a~ I i<to} of I~1, and any formula ~eL(T), let '~z' denote the result of substituting 'a{ for every free occurrence of 'x~' in q~, ~<o,. Then 92 is decidable just in case, for some indexing E of 192[, {n 192~0~ is a recursive set of integers. It is easy, to show that the decidability of a model does not depend on the choice of the effective enumeration of the formulas in L(T); we omit details. By a simple 'effectivizaton' of Henkin's proof of the completeness theorem [2] we have Fact 1. Every decidable theory has a decidable model. Assume next that T is a complete decidable theory and {On ln<to} is an effective enumeration of all formulas of L(T). A type F of T is recursive just in case {nlO, ~ F} is a recursive set of integers. Again, it is easy to see that the recursiveness of F does not depend .on which effective enumeration of L(T) is used. -
The Common HOL Platform
The Common HOL Platform Mark Adams Proof Technologies Ltd, UK Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands The Common HOL project aims to facilitate porting source code and proofs between members of the HOL family of theorem provers. At the heart of the project is the Common HOL Platform, which defines a standard HOL theory and API that aims to be compatible with all HOL systems. So far, HOL Light and hol90 have been adapted for conformance, and HOL Zero was originally developed to conform. In this paper we provide motivation for a platform, give an overview of the Common HOL Platform’s theory and API components, and show how to adapt legacy systems. We also report on the platform’s successful application in the hand-translation of a few thousand lines of source code from HOL Light to HOL Zero. 1 Introduction The HOL family of theorem provers started in the 1980s with HOL88 [5], and has since grown to include many systems, most prominently HOL4 [16], HOL Light [8], ProofPower HOL [3] and Is- abelle/HOL [12]. These four main systems have developed their own advanced proof facilities and extensive theory libraries, and have been successfully employed in major projects in the verification of critical hardware and software [1, 11] and the formalisation of mathematics [7]. It would clearly be of benefit if these systems could “talk” to each other, specifically if theory, proofs and source code could be exchanged in a relatively seamless manner. This would reduce the considerable duplication of effort otherwise required for one system to benefit from the major projects and advanced capabilities developed on another. -
Ultraproducts and Elementary Classes *
MATHEMATICS ULTRAPRODUCTS AND ELEMENTARY CLASSES * BY H. JEROME KEISLER (Communicated by Prof. A. HEYTING at the meeting of May 27, 1961 INTRODUCTION In the theory of models of the first order predicate logic with identity we study the relationship between notions from logic and purely mathe matical objects, called relational systems, or (first order) structures, m, consisting of a set A and a sequence of relations on A corresponding to the predicate symbols of the logic. In such studies some of the most useful methods are those which permit us to form structures which have certain semantical properties. For example, the completeness theorem permits us to form a structure which satisfies a given consistent set of sentences. A more recent tool is the reduced product operation, which is particularly simple and direct from the mathematical point of view. Speaking very roughly, a reduced product Iliei ill:i/D of the structures mi, i El, is formed by first taking their direct product and then forming the quotient system determined in a certain way by the filter D on the index set 1. If D is an ultrafilter we have an ultraproduct (or prime reduced product), and if each m:i coincides with a fixed system ill: we have a reduced power, or ultrapower, ill: I j D. Ultraproducts have recently been applied to obtain new, comparatively direct mathematical proofs and at the same time stronger forms of a number of theorems in model theory. An outstanding example is the proof of the compactness theorem outlined in [33]. They have also been used to obtain several completely new results in the theory of models (for example, see [35]). -
Reasoning with Ambiguity
Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Reasoning with Ambiguity Christian Wurm the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract We treat the problem of reasoning with ambiguous propositions. Even though ambiguity is obviously problematic for reasoning, it is no less ob- vious that ambiguous propositions entail other propositions (both ambiguous and unambiguous), and are entailed by other propositions. This article gives a formal analysis of the underlying mechanisms, both from an algebraic and a logical point of view. The main result can be summarized as follows: sound (and complete) reasoning with ambiguity requires a distinction between equivalence on the one and congruence on the other side: the fact that α entails β does not imply β can be substituted for α in all contexts preserving truth. With- out this distinction, we will always run into paradoxical results. We present the (cut-free) sequent calculus ALcf , which we conjecture implements sound and complete propositional reasoning with ambiguity, and provide it with a language-theoretic semantics, where letters represent unambiguous meanings and concatenation represents ambiguity. Keywords Ambiguity, reasoning, proof theory, algebra, Computational Linguistics Acknowledgements Thanks to Timm Lichte, Roland Eibers, Roussanka Loukanova and Gerhard Schurz for helpful discussions; also I want to thank two anonymous reviewers for their many excellent remarks! 1 Introduction This article gives an extensive treatment of reasoning with ambiguity, more precisely with ambiguous propositions. We approach the problem from an Universit¨atD¨usseldorf,Germany Universit¨atsstr.1 40225 D¨usseldorf Germany E-mail: [email protected] 2 Christian Wurm algebraic and a logical perspective and show some interesting surprising results on both ends, which lead up to some interesting philosophical questions, which we address in a preliminary fashion. -
Category Theory and Lambda Calculus
Category Theory and Lambda Calculus Mario Román García Trabajo Fin de Grado Doble Grado en Ingeniería Informática y Matemáticas Tutores Pedro A. García-Sánchez Manuel Bullejos Lorenzo Facultad de Ciencias E.T.S. Ingenierías Informática y de Telecomunicación Granada, a 18 de junio de 2018 Contents 1 Lambda calculus 13 1.1 Untyped λ-calculus . 13 1.1.1 Untyped λ-calculus . 14 1.1.2 Free and bound variables, substitution . 14 1.1.3 Alpha equivalence . 16 1.1.4 Beta reduction . 16 1.1.5 Eta reduction . 17 1.1.6 Confluence . 17 1.1.7 The Church-Rosser theorem . 18 1.1.8 Normalization . 20 1.1.9 Standardization and evaluation strategies . 21 1.1.10 SKI combinators . 22 1.1.11 Turing completeness . 24 1.2 Simply typed λ-calculus . 24 1.2.1 Simple types . 25 1.2.2 Typing rules for simply typed λ-calculus . 25 1.2.3 Curry-style types . 26 1.2.4 Unification and type inference . 27 1.2.5 Subject reduction and normalization . 29 1.3 The Curry-Howard correspondence . 31 1.3.1 Extending the simply typed λ-calculus . 31 1.3.2 Natural deduction . 32 1.3.3 Propositions as types . 34 1.4 Other type systems . 35 1.4.1 λ-cube..................................... 35 2 Mikrokosmos 38 2.1 Implementation of λ-expressions . 38 2.1.1 The Haskell programming language . 38 2.1.2 De Bruijn indexes . 40 2.1.3 Substitution . 41 2.1.4 De Bruijn-terms and λ-terms . 42 2.1.5 Evaluation . -
Interactive Theorem Proving (ITP) Course Web Version
Interactive Theorem Proving (ITP) Course Web Version Thomas Tuerk ([email protected]) Except where otherwise noted, this work is licened under Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License version 3c35cc2 of Mon Nov 11 10:22:43 2019 Contents Part I Preface 3 Part II Introduction 6 Part III HOL 4 History and Architecture 16 Part IV HOL's Logic 24 Part V Basic HOL Usage 38 Part VI Forward Proofs 46 Part VII Backward Proofs 61 Part VIII Basic Tactics 83 Part IX Induction Proofs 110 Part X Basic Definitions 119 Part XI Good Definitions 163 Part XII Deep and Shallow Embeddings 184 Part XIII Rewriting 192 Part XIV Advanced Definition Principles 246 Part XV Maintainable Proofs 267 Part XVI Overview of HOL 4 289 Part XVII Other Interactive Theorem Provers 302 2 / 315 Part I Preface Except where otherwise noted, this work is licened under Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. Preface these slides originate from a course for advanced master students it was given by the PROSPER group at KTH in Stockholm in 2017 (see https://www.kth.se/social/group/interactive-theorem-) the course focused on how to use HOL 4 students taking the course were expected to I know functional programming, esp. SML I understand predicate logic I have some experience with pen and paper proofs the course consisted of 9 lectures, which each took 90 minutes there were 19 supervised practical sessions, which each took 2 h usually there was 1 lecture and 2 practical sessions each week students were expected to work about 10 h each -
HOL-Testgen Version 1.8 USER GUIDE
HOL-TestGen Version 1.8 USER GUIDE Achim Brucker, Lukas Brügger, Abderrahmane Feliachi, Chantal Keller, Matthias Krieger, Delphine Longuet, Yakoub Nemouchi, Frédéric Tuong, Burkhart Wolff To cite this version: Achim Brucker, Lukas Brügger, Abderrahmane Feliachi, Chantal Keller, Matthias Krieger, et al.. HOL-TestGen Version 1.8 USER GUIDE. [Technical Report] Univeristé Paris-Saclay; LRI - CNRS, University Paris-Sud. 2016. hal-01765526 HAL Id: hal-01765526 https://hal.inria.fr/hal-01765526 Submitted on 12 Apr 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. R L R I A P P O R HOL-TestGen Version 1.8 USER GUIDE T BRUCKER A D / BRUGGER L / FELIACHI A / KELLER C / KRIEGER M P / LONGUET D / NEMOUCHI Y / TUONG F / WOLFF B D Unité Mixte de Recherche 8623 E CNRS-Université Paris Sud-LRI 04/2016 R Rapport de Recherche N° 1586 E C H E R C CNRS – Université de Paris Sud H Centre d’Orsay LABORATOIRE DE RECHERCHE EN INFORMATIQUE E Bâtiment 650 91405 ORSAY Cedex (France) HOL-TestGen 1.8.0 User Guide http://www.brucker.ch/projects/hol-testgen/ Achim D. Brucker Lukas Brügger Abderrahmane Feliachi Chantal Keller Matthias P.