4. Accepted: 11.01.2015
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Journal of Philosophy, Inc
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Harder Problem of Consciousness Author(s): Ned Block Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 99, No. 8 (Aug., 2002), pp. 391-425 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3655621 Accessed: 04-08-2015 15:41 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME XCIX, NO. 8, AUGUST 2002 THE HARDER PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS* H. Huxley' famously said: "How it is that anything so re- T. markable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the ap- pearance of Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp" (ibid., p. 19). We do not see how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological basis. This is the hard problemof consciousness.2 My aim here is to present another problem of consciousness. -
Philosophy of Mind
From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy of Mind Frank Jackson, Georges Rey Philosophical Concept ‘Philosophy of mind’, and ‘philosophy of psychology’ are two terms for the same general area of philosophical inquiry: the nature of mental phenomena and their connection with behaviour and, in more recent discussions, the brain. Much work in this area reflects a revolution in psychology that began mid-century. Before then, largely in reaction to traditional claims about the mind being non-physical (see Dualism; Descartes), many thought that a scientific psychology should avoid talk of ‘private’ mental states. Investigation of such states had seemed to be based on unreliable introspection (see Introspection, psychology of), not subject to independent checking (see Private language argument), and to invite dubious ideas of telepathy (see Parapsychology). Consequently, psychologists like B.F. Skinner and J.B. Watson, and philosophers like W.V. Quine and Gilbert Ryle argued that scientific psychology should confine itself to studying publicly observable relations between stimuli and responses (see Behaviourism, methodological and scientific; Behaviourism, analytic). However, in the late 1950s, several developments began to change all this: (i) The experiments behaviourists themselves ran on animals tended to refute behaviouristic hypotheses, suggesting that the behaviour of even rats had to be understood in terms of mental states (see Learning; Animal language and thought). (ii) The linguist Noam Chomsky drew attention to the surprising complexity of the natural languages that children effortlessly learn, and proposed ways of explaining this complexity in terms of largely unconscious mental phenomena. (iii) The revolutionary work of Alan Turing (see Turing machines) led to the development of the modern digital computer. -
Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind Edited by Jonathan Cohen∗and Brian McLaughliny This volume will introduce the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume will include ten pairs of newly commissioned essays ad- vocating opposing viewpoints | one for each of the ten topics listed below. In addition, the editors will provide a substantive introduction that will lay out the necessary background for the debates and locate the individual topics within philosophy of mind and in relation to one another. The essays will each be around 6000 to 8000 words in length, and will be accessible to upper-level undergraduates and graduate students. Consequently, we expect that the volume could be used as text for advanced courses in phi- losophy of mind. However, the essays will also represent the state of play in the areas, and will contain original argumentation by eminent philosophers, so it will also be an important text for academics working in philosophy of mind and adjoining areas. We have organized our questions under the three headings that, in our minds, structure the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind: questions about the ontology of the mental, questions about the nature of mental content, and questions about the nature of consciousness. For many of the questions on our list, we have suggested a number of backup authors in case our first choices are unable to write the essays. Although some names appear more than once on our list (including appearances as backup authors) we would not allow more than one piece by a single author in the volume. -
Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected]
Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected] NEW 2009 VERSION (an expansion of the version that appeared in Martin, R. and Kolak, D., The Experience of Philosophy, 6th ed., Oxford UP, 2005) 21 October 2009 Meta-atheism: Religious Avowal as Self-Deception (Long Version)1 1. Introduction I’m not a professional philosopher of religion and have no special knowledge of theology. However, I regularly teach an introductory course in philosophy in which I discuss the standard arguments for the existence of God. The exercise has produced in me a certain incredulity: I have come increasingly to wonder how such extremely smart people, like Aquinas or Descartes, could advance such patently bad arguments, as I think most philosophers (even those who claim to “believe”) would take those arguments to be. At any rate, I find it hard to believe that anyone really buys the “ontological argument,” or any of Aquinas’ “five ways.” Existence may or may not be a predicate, and there may or may not be unmoved movers, uncaused causers, and undesigned teleological systems, but these arguments don’t remotely establish their intended conclusion, the existence of anything like the traditional Christian God with His astounding properties of, e.g., eternality, omniscience, omnipotence and necessary benevolence (for brevity, I’ll refer to these latter properties as “omni” properties, a being possessing them as an “omni” being). And “religious experiences” or “intuitions” no matter how ecstatic or profound, could obviously be explained by any number of other far more modest hypotheses (I'll briefly discuss all these issues in §2 below). -
A Brief Tour of the Introductions to Consciousness Studies
Epilogue: A Brief Tour of the Introductions to Consciousness Studies That a man should simply and profoundly say that he cannot understand how consciousness has come into existence – is perfectly natural. But that a man should glue his eye to a microscope and stare and stare – and still not be able to see how it happens – is ridiculous, and it is particularly ridiculous when it is supposed to be serious. […] If the natural scientists had been developed in Socrates’ day as they are now, all the sophists would have been scientists. One would have hung a microscope outside his shop in order to attract custom, and then would have had a sign painted saying: “Learn and see through a giant microscope how a man thinks” (Soren Kierkegaard, diary entry of 1846 ) Like a fortress under siege, consciousness has so far resisted any attempts to provide convincing solutions to the many questions it poses. The great neurophysiologist Sir Charles Sherrington (Fig. 1 ) neatly captured the problem of understanding the very nature of consciousness as a phenomenon which appears to elude scientifi c explana- tion within the domain of physical science: “The energy-concept […] embraces and unifi es much. […] Immense as it is, and self-satisfying as it is, and self-contained as it is, it yet seems but an introduction to something else. For instance a star which we perceive. The energy-scheme deals with it, describes the passing of radiation thence into the eye, the little light-image of it formed at the bottom of the eye, the ensuing photo-chemical action in the retina, the trains of action- potentials travelling along the nerve to the brain, the further electrical disturbance in the brain, the action- potentials streaming thence to the muscles of eye-balls and of the pupil, the contrac- tion of them sharpening the light-image and placing the best seeing part of the retina under it. -
The Experience of Philosophy
Contents Preface Vtl Part I: Beginning Philosophy 1. Plato, The Trial of Socrates 2 2. Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority 23 3. Jiddu Krishnamurti, The Function ofEducation 30 4. Bertrand Russell, The Value of Philosophy 34 Part II: Where and When 5. Edwin Abbott, Flatland 40 6. Daniel Kolak and David Goloff, The Incredible Shrinking Zeno 57 7. Daniel Dennett, Where Am I? 71 8. Albert Einstein, On the Idea ofTime in Physics 80 9. Kadri Vihvelin, Time Travel: The Rules of the Road 84 Part III: Who 10. Daniel Kolak, Descartes among the Ruins 96 ll. Buddha, On Having No Self 104 12. D. E. Harding, On Having No Head 107 13. René Descartes, On Self and Substance 111 14. John Locke, Personal Identity 120 15. David Hume, Personal Identity 128 16. Thomas Reid, Critique ofLocke and Hume on BehalfofCommon Sense 131 17. Raymond Martin, Personal Identity from Plato to Padit 139 18. Char10tte Perkins Gilman, The Yellow Wallpaper 155 19. AdamjLinda Parascandola, Trans or Me? 168 lil iv CONTENTS Part IV: Preedom 20. Baron Holbach, The Illusion ofFree Will 176 21. David Hume, Liberty and Necessity 182 22. William James, The Dilemma of Determinism 194 23. G. E. Moore, Free Will 201 24. Richard Taylor, Freedom and Determinism 209 25. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Human Freedom 219 Part V: J(nowledge 26. Plato, Knowledge 226 27. René Descartes, Meditations 250 28. John Locke, Where Our 1deas Come From 259 29. George Berkeley, To Be ls to Be Perceived 263 30. Bertrand Russell, Perception, Knowledge, and 1nduction 268 31. -
Crime and Consciousness: Science and Involuntary Acts Deborah W
University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Minnesota Law Review 2002 Crime and Consciousness: Science and Involuntary Acts Deborah W. Denno Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Denno, Deborah W., "Crime and Consciousness: Science and Involuntary Acts" (2002). Minnesota Law Review. 747. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr/747 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Minnesota Law Review collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Crime and Consciousness: Science and Involuntary Acts Deborah W. Dennot [T]he state of a man's mind is as much a fact as the state of his digestion.1 INTRODUCTION In 1906, psychologist Edouard Clapar~de experimented with the mind. He pricked the hand of a memory-impaired patient while greeting her with a pin concealed between his fingers. As always, the patient failed to recognize Claparode when the two soon met again; yet, she refused to shake his hand, explaining that it might be unpleasant but she did not know why.2 With this test, Clapar~de revealed the dynamics of 1 Professor of Law, Fordham University School of Law. I am most grateful to the following individuals for their comments on this Article: Jerome Bruner, Paul Chevigny, Edward Chikofsky, Dwight Denno, Hal Edgar, Phoebe Ellsworth, Cynthia Estlund, Robert Ferguson, Lawrence Fleischer, Katherine Franke, Kent Greenawalt, Christopher Hale, Nancy King, Dorie Klein, Benjamin Libet, Jack Litman, Henry Monaghan, Ren~e Romkens, Kendall Thomas, Vance Torbert, Lloyd Weinreb, Ian Weinstein, and R. -
Nagel, Panpsychism and Realism
Nagel, Panpsychism and Realism NICHOLAS UNWIN Abstract Thomas Nagel argues that panpsychism (that everything has mental qualities) follows from four premises, including what he calls ‘Realism’. This paper argues that he misidentifies the sort of realism that he should be concerned with, and that a useful parallel can be drawn with certain nonrealist theories of ethics, notably expressivism. An expressivist or projectivist account of conscious states is argued to be more plausible than it looks, and that adopting such a position would successfully block the argument for panpsychism. Comparisons are also drawn with David Chalmers’s position. In his celebrated paper of that name, Thomas Nagel argues that panpsychism, namely the doctrine that the basic physical constituents of the universe have mental (or ‘protomental’) qualities regardless of whether they form parts of living beings, follows from four plausible premises: 1. Material Composition Any living organism, including a human being, is a complex material system. … No constituents besides matter are needed. 2. Nonreductionism Ordinary mental states … are not physical properties of the organism … and they are not implied by physical properties alone. 3. Realism [Mental states] are [real] properties of the organism. 4. Nonemergence 1 All [nonrelational] properties of a complex system … derive from the properties of its constituents and their effects on each other when so combined.1 The derivation runs as follows: If the mental properties of an organism are not implied by any physical properties but must derive from properties of the organism's constituents, then those constituents must have nonphysical properties from which the appearance of mental properties follows when the combination is of the right kind. -
Pain Eliminativism
Baetu TM. Pain Eliminativism. J Ment Health Clin Psychol (2020) 4(3): 22-25 JOURNAL OF MENTAL HEALTH AND CLINICAL PSYCHOLOGY www.mentalhealthjournal.org Mini Review Article Open Access Pain Eliminativism Tudor M. Baetu* Department of Philosophy and Arts, University of Quebec at Trois-Rivieres, Canada Article Info Abstract Article Notes The philosophical thesis of pain eliminativism can be understood in several Received: June 24, 2020 ways. As a claim about the inadequacy and replacement of folk explanatory pain Accepted: July 17, 2020 constructs and concepts, it is congruent with scientific findings. Eliminativism is *Correspondence: controversial in as much as it demands a more or less radical recharacterization Dr. Tudor M. Baetu, Università du Québec à Trois-Rivières, of the phenomenon of pain in order to ensure compatibility with physicalism Département de philosophie et des arts, 3351, boul. des and an identity model of reductive explanation. In this respect, eliminativism Forges, Trois-Rivières (Québec) G8Z 4M3, Canada; Telephone is at odds with experimental and explanatory paradigms at work in biomedical No: 819 376-5011; Email: [email protected]. research. The latter is concerned with reproducible phenomena, controlled experiments generating evidence for causation and causal-mechanistic © 2020 Baetu TM. This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. explanations. Since nothing here supports conclusive inferences about the identity or non-identity of pain, or aspects of it, with biological activity, it is not clear what, if anything at all needs to be eliminated. In philosophy of mind, eliminative materialism is the thesis according to which folk psychological explanations of the sort ‘I removed my hand from the stove because I felt pain’ should be replaced by explanations in terms of neural mechanisms. -
Jerry Fodor (1935-2017)
Prolegomena 16 (2) 2017: 189–196 doi: 10 .26362/20180107 Jerry Fodor (1935-2017) Try to Fodor yourself… a bit! A legacy beyond and behind (some) theories of Fodor “Scholarship is the process by which butterflies are transmuted into caterpillars ”. Jerry Fodor “Jerry leaves an enormous legacy as a leader of a tectonic shift in the field of cognitive studies ”. Zenon Pylyshyn One day after Jerry Fodor’s passing on November 29, 2017, I posted a note in a social network in which I described my first and unique personal encounter with him ten years ago . It was during a conference at which I also met Dušan Dožudić, Prolegomena’s editor . I didn’t hesitate to accept when Dušan invited me to write a memorial piece about Fodor . However, as the days passed and the deadline became closer, the task turned out to be more challenging than I thought . I initially wanted to write an entirely anecdotal note but, day after day, several in memoriam notes appeared . They were mostly written by peo- ple, like Zenon Pylyshyn and Georges Rey, who shared their academic life with Fodor, from informal meetings to sailing . I asked myself about the value of what I was commissioned to write . Thence I realized that the value of the anecdotal part of this manuscript relies on what I thought to be its irremedi- able deficiency, namely that it would be about the effects of one conversation on the academic life of a young student . Intellectual exemplarity should not be equated to theoretical expertise: one could have written about the best achievements of an expert without hav- 190 Prolegomena 16 (2) 2017 ing said a word about someone that one considers intellectually exemplary, or whose behavior in academic contexts one thinks of as worthy of imitation . -
Remembering Jerry Fodor and His Work
DOI: 10.1111/mila.12206 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Remembering Jerry Fodor and his work1 Georges Rey Department of Philosophy, University of Maryland, College Park, Maryland This is a reminiscence and short biographical sketch of Correspondence the late philosopher and cognitive scientist Jerry Fodor. It Department of Philosophy, University of includes a summary of his main proposals about the mind: Maryland, College Park, MD 20742. his “Language of Thought” hypothesis; his rejection of Email: [email protected] analyticity and conceptual role semantics; his “mad dog nativism”; his proposal of mental modules and—by contrast—his skepticism about a computational theory of central cognition; his anti-reductionist, but still physicalist, views about psychology; and, lastly, his attacks on selec- tionism. I conclude with some discussion of his idiosyn- cratic style and of his aesthetic and other interests. An appendix provides some memorable quotes. KEYWORDS antiselectionism, confirmation holism, language of thought, nativism, referentialism 1 | SOME INTRODUCTORY PERSONAL NOTES After a long illness, the philosopher Jerry Fodor died on November 29, 2017. This was a great loss not only to his family and many friends but also to philosophy and cognitive science. For reasons I hope will emerge in this remembrance, he was indisputably the most important philosopher of psy- chology of his generation.2 I first met Fodor on a wintry evening in February 1974. I had been a graduate student at Harvard for several years, still to some extent under the spell of Wittgenstein and Quine, whose views then dominated the philosophy of mind, there and elsewhere. My entering class had been expressly warned by Quine's close colleague, Burton Dreben, to avoid (in Wittgenstein's famous phrase) “the grip of the picture” of traditional mentalism—which, he claimed, underlay the work of Chomsky and 1 I make no pretense of covering all of Fodor's views, which are far too rich for summary in a journal article. -
A New Perspective on the Mind-Body Problem. Jesse L
University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1984 A new perspective on the mind-body problem. Jesse L. Yoder University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Yoder, Jesse L., "A new perspective on the mind-body problem." (1984). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2055. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2055 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UMASS/AMHERST A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM A Dissertation Presented By Jesse L. Yoder Submitted to the Graduate School of University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 1984 Philosophy A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM A Dissertation Presented By JESSE L. YODER Approved as to style and content by: Gareth Matthews, Chairperson of Committee JinJU Vere Chappell , Member / » A Cynl^hU Freeland, Member Lf M ^ ' Michael Arbib, Member Michael Jubien, Department Department of Philosophy DEDICATION To Feroline Whitehead, Gareth Matthews, and Tech. Pubs, at Wang. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many people deserve mention for their help at various points in my career. I will mention them in roughly chronological order. While I received much valuable help from many of my philosophy teachers at the University of Maryland, several deserve particular mention. Peter Goldstone was my first philosophy teacher and spent many hours explaining philosophy to me.