Consciousness Reconsidered by Owen Flanagan
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Journal of Philosophy, Inc
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Harder Problem of Consciousness Author(s): Ned Block Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 99, No. 8 (Aug., 2002), pp. 391-425 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3655621 Accessed: 04-08-2015 15:41 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME XCIX, NO. 8, AUGUST 2002 THE HARDER PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS* H. Huxley' famously said: "How it is that anything so re- T. markable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the ap- pearance of Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp" (ibid., p. 19). We do not see how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological basis. This is the hard problemof consciousness.2 My aim here is to present another problem of consciousness. -
Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World
Reconciling Eros and Neuroscience: Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World by ANDREW J. PELLITIERI* Boston University Abstract Many people currently working in the sciences of the mind believe terms such as “love” will soon be rendered philosophically obsolete. This belief results from a common assumption that such terms are irreconcilable with the naturalistic worldview that most modern scientists might require. Some philosophers reject the meaning of the terms, claiming that as science progresses words like ‘love’ and ‘happiness’ will be replaced completely by language that is more descriptive of the material phenomena taking place. This paper attempts to defend these meaningful concepts in philosophy of mind without appealing to concepts a materialist could not accept. Introduction hilosophy engages the meaning of the word “love” in a myriad of complex discourses ranging from ancient musings on happiness, Pto modern work in the philosophy of mind. The eliminative and reductive forms of materialism threaten to reduce the importance of our everyday language and devalue the meaning we attach to words like “love,” in the name of scientific progress. Faced with this threat, some philosophers, such as Owen Flanagan, have attempted to defend meaningful words and concepts important to the contemporary philosopher, while simultaneously promoting widespread acceptance of materialism. While I believe that the available work is useful, I think * [email protected]. Received 1/2011, revised December 2011. © the author. Arché Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy, Volume V, Issue 1: Winter 2012. pp. 60-82 RECONCILING EROS AND NEUROSCIENCE 61 more needs to be said about the functional role of words like “love” in the script of progressing neuroscience, and further the important implications this yields for our current mode of practical reasoning. -
Buddhism and Cognitive Science: How Can the Dialogue Move Forward?
Buddhism and Cognitive Science: How Can the Dialogue Move Forward? Keynote Lecture for the Conference “Buddhism, Mind, and Cognitive Science” University of California, Berkeley April 25, 2014. Evan Thompson University of British Columbia The main proposition of my lecture is that the Buddhism-cognitive science encounter needs to be fundamentally reoriented in order to have a chance of becoming a genuine dialogue. At present, the encounter takes its direction from scientific research on meditation and gives primacy to the measurable biological and behavioural effects of meditation practices in controlled experimental and clinical situations. Although this research is worthwhile, it is neither the same as nor sufficient for a dialogue between Buddhism and cognitive science about the mind. I intend to argue that the Buddhism- cognitive science encounter should take its direction from philosophy and give primacy to the constitution of meaning in human experience. Buddhist philosophy especially must be central to this dialogue. The Embodied Mind To set the context, I would like to go back to the book, The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, which I wrote with Francisco Varela and Eleanor Rosch almost twenty-five years ago. Since this book helped launch the Buddhism-cognitive science discussion, and since parts of it were written here at Berkeley, it seems fitting to begin by recalling some of its main ideas in relation to our conference theme, “Buddhism, Mind, and Cognitive Science.” I would also like to take this opportunity to explain what I now see as the book’s limitations. Our aim in The Embodied Mind was to create what we called a circulation between cognitive science and human experience. -
Philosophy of Mind
From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy of Mind Frank Jackson, Georges Rey Philosophical Concept ‘Philosophy of mind’, and ‘philosophy of psychology’ are two terms for the same general area of philosophical inquiry: the nature of mental phenomena and their connection with behaviour and, in more recent discussions, the brain. Much work in this area reflects a revolution in psychology that began mid-century. Before then, largely in reaction to traditional claims about the mind being non-physical (see Dualism; Descartes), many thought that a scientific psychology should avoid talk of ‘private’ mental states. Investigation of such states had seemed to be based on unreliable introspection (see Introspection, psychology of), not subject to independent checking (see Private language argument), and to invite dubious ideas of telepathy (see Parapsychology). Consequently, psychologists like B.F. Skinner and J.B. Watson, and philosophers like W.V. Quine and Gilbert Ryle argued that scientific psychology should confine itself to studying publicly observable relations between stimuli and responses (see Behaviourism, methodological and scientific; Behaviourism, analytic). However, in the late 1950s, several developments began to change all this: (i) The experiments behaviourists themselves ran on animals tended to refute behaviouristic hypotheses, suggesting that the behaviour of even rats had to be understood in terms of mental states (see Learning; Animal language and thought). (ii) The linguist Noam Chomsky drew attention to the surprising complexity of the natural languages that children effortlessly learn, and proposed ways of explaining this complexity in terms of largely unconscious mental phenomena. (iii) The revolutionary work of Alan Turing (see Turing machines) led to the development of the modern digital computer. -
Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience
Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience Edited by Gregg D. Caruso and Owen Flanagan Oxford University Press New York, 2017 In Memory of Louis J. Caruso Table of Contents Preface Contributor List (1) Neuroexistentialism: Third-Wave Existentialism Owen Flanagan and Gregg D. Caruso I. Morality, Love, and Emotion (2) The Impact of Social Neuroscience on Moral Philosophy Patricia Smith Churchland (3) All You Need is Love(s): Exploring the Biological Platform of Morality Maureen Sie (4) Does Neuroscience Undermine Morality? Paul Henne and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (5) The Neuroscience of Purpose, Meaning, and Morals Edmund T. Rolls (6) Moral Sedimentation Jesse Prinz II. Autonomy, Consciousness, and the Self (7) Choices Without Choosers: Towards a Neuropsychologically Plausible Existentialism Neil Levy (8) Relational Authenticity Shaun Gallagher, Ben Morgan, and Naomi Rokotnitz (9) Behavior Control, Meaning, and Neuroscience Walter Glannon (10) Two Types of Libertarian Free Will are Realized in the Human Brain Peter U. Tse III. Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Meaning in Life (11) Hard-Incompatibilist Existentialism: Neuroscience, Punishment, and Meaning in Life Derk Pereboom and Gregg D. Caruso (12) On Determinism and Human Responsibility Michael S. Gazzaniga (13) Free Will Skepticism, Freedom, and Criminal Behavior Farah Focquaert, Andrea L. Glenn, Adrian Raine (14) Your Brain as the Source of Free Will Worth Wanting: Understanding Free Will in the Age of Neuroscience Eddy Nahmias (15) Humility, Free Will Beliefs, and Existential Angst: How We Got from a Preliminary Investigation to a Cautionary Tale Thomas Nadelhoffer and Jennifer Cole Wright (16) Purpose, Freedom, and the Laws of Nature Sean M. -
Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind Edited by Jonathan Cohen∗and Brian McLaughliny This volume will introduce the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume will include ten pairs of newly commissioned essays ad- vocating opposing viewpoints | one for each of the ten topics listed below. In addition, the editors will provide a substantive introduction that will lay out the necessary background for the debates and locate the individual topics within philosophy of mind and in relation to one another. The essays will each be around 6000 to 8000 words in length, and will be accessible to upper-level undergraduates and graduate students. Consequently, we expect that the volume could be used as text for advanced courses in phi- losophy of mind. However, the essays will also represent the state of play in the areas, and will contain original argumentation by eminent philosophers, so it will also be an important text for academics working in philosophy of mind and adjoining areas. We have organized our questions under the three headings that, in our minds, structure the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind: questions about the ontology of the mental, questions about the nature of mental content, and questions about the nature of consciousness. For many of the questions on our list, we have suggested a number of backup authors in case our first choices are unable to write the essays. Although some names appear more than once on our list (including appearances as backup authors) we would not allow more than one piece by a single author in the volume. -
Zombies and the Function of Consciousness Owen Flanagan
© 1 9 9 5 P o l g e r a n d F l a n a g a n Zombies and the Function of Consciousness Owen Flanagan Departments of Philosophy, Psychology, and Neurobiology, Email: [email protected]. and Thomas Polger Department of Philosophy, Email:[email protected], Box 90743 Duke University, Durham, NC, 27707, USA.* Abstract: Todd Moody’s Zombie Earth thought experiment is an attempt to show that ‘conscious inessentialism’ is false or in need of qualification. We defend conscious inessentialism against his criticisms, and argue that zombie thought experiments highlight the need to explain why consciousness evolved and what function(s) it serves. This is the hardest problem in consciousness studies. 1. Conscious Inessentialism Conscious inessentialism is “the view that for any intelligent activity i , performed in any cognitive domain d , even if we do i with conscious accompaniments, i can in principle be done without these conscious accompaniments.”1 Among other things, conscious inessentialism forces questions about the function, and thus the adaptiveness and evolutionary significance, of consciousness. This is because conscious inessentialism just is the claim that consciousness is not metaphysically or logically necessary. It is * The order of authors follows alphabetical convention. Authorship is completely equal. 1 Flanagan, O. Consciousness Reconsidered. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), 5. 1 © 1 9 9 5 P o l g e r a n d F l a n a g a n not necessary in all possible worlds where creatures who are functionally equivalent to us exist. But consciousness did emerge in this actual world—possibly among many species. -
Owen Flanagan Page 1-55 9:24 AM-10/30/071 Draft: March 14
owen flanagan Page 1-55 9:24 AM-10/30/071 Draft: March 14, 2004 Comments welcomed Rev. 1/2007 Buddhist Ethics: The Therapy of Desire and Delusion1 Owen Flanagan This alone -- one’s service to sentient beings (sattvaraddhana) is pleasing to Tathagatas [Enlightened or Awakened Ones]. This alone is the actual accomplishment of one’s goal. This alone removes the suffering of the world. Therefore, let this alone be my resolve. (Santiveda, Bodhicaryavatara, VI, 127) 1 My thinking about the topic of destructive states of mind owes much to His Holiness, the XIV Dalai Lama and the other participants in a week long conference on the topic in Dhararmsala, India in March, 2000. A splendid report on the meetings is narrated by Daniel Goleman, Destructive Emotions: How Can We Overcome Them? A Scientific Dialogue with the Dalai Lama (2003). My first paper on this topic was “Destructive Emotions” in Cognition & Emotion 1: 2 (2000) 259-281. There my aim was to defend the Tibetan Buddhist therapy of destructive emotions against those who might attempt to defend all emotions on evolutionary grounds, on grounds that all emotions are biological adaptations. owen flanagan Page 2-55 9:24 AM-10/30/072 Thus, one who has patience should cultivate zeal, because Awakening is established with zeal, and there is no merit without zeal…What is zeal? It is enthusiasm for virtue. (Santiveda, Bodhicaryavatara, VII, 1 & 2) Upon mounting the chariot of the Spirit of Awakening, which carries away all despondency and weariness, what sensible person would despair at progressing in this way from joy to joy? (Santiveda, Bodhicaryavatara,VII, 30) Virtue and Happiness in Buddhism2 In the previous chapter I offered and analysis of eudaimonia, Buddhist style. -
Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected]
Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected] NEW 2009 VERSION (an expansion of the version that appeared in Martin, R. and Kolak, D., The Experience of Philosophy, 6th ed., Oxford UP, 2005) 21 October 2009 Meta-atheism: Religious Avowal as Self-Deception (Long Version)1 1. Introduction I’m not a professional philosopher of religion and have no special knowledge of theology. However, I regularly teach an introductory course in philosophy in which I discuss the standard arguments for the existence of God. The exercise has produced in me a certain incredulity: I have come increasingly to wonder how such extremely smart people, like Aquinas or Descartes, could advance such patently bad arguments, as I think most philosophers (even those who claim to “believe”) would take those arguments to be. At any rate, I find it hard to believe that anyone really buys the “ontological argument,” or any of Aquinas’ “five ways.” Existence may or may not be a predicate, and there may or may not be unmoved movers, uncaused causers, and undesigned teleological systems, but these arguments don’t remotely establish their intended conclusion, the existence of anything like the traditional Christian God with His astounding properties of, e.g., eternality, omniscience, omnipotence and necessary benevolence (for brevity, I’ll refer to these latter properties as “omni” properties, a being possessing them as an “omni” being). And “religious experiences” or “intuitions” no matter how ecstatic or profound, could obviously be explained by any number of other far more modest hypotheses (I'll briefly discuss all these issues in §2 below). -
Examining the Bodhisattva's Brain
The Bodhisattva’s Brain: Owen Flanagan Meets Critics with Christian Coseru, “Buddhism, Comparative Neurophilosophy, and Human Flourishing”; Charles Goodman, “Buddhism, Naturalism, and the Pursuit of Happiness”; Bronwyn Finnigan, “Examining the Bodhisattva’s Brain”; and Owen Flanagan, “Buddhism and the Scientific Image: Reply to Critics.” EXAMINING THE BODHISATTVA’S BRAIN by Bronwyn Finnigan Abstract. Owen Flanagan’s The Bodhisattva’s Brain aims to intro- duce secular-minded thinkers to Buddhist thought and motivate its acceptance by analytic philosophers. I argue that Flanagan provides a compelling caution against the hasty generalizations of recent “science of happiness” literature, which correlates happiness with Buddhism on the basis of certain neurological studies. I contend, however, that his positive account of Buddhist ethics is less persuasive. I question the level of engagement with Buddhist philosophical literature and chal- lenge Flanagan’s central claim, that a Buddhist version of eudaimonia is a common core conception shared by all Buddhists. I argue that this view is not only a rational reconstruction in need of argumentation but is in tension with competing Buddhist metaphysical theories of self, including the one Flanagan himself endorses. Keywords: Buddhism; ethics; eudaimonism; Owen Flanagan; nat- uralism; neuroscience; reductionism; virtue ethics There is growing interest in Asian traditions among Western-trained philosophers. A major contributing factor has been the publication in the past 20 years of several bold philosophical works that critically engage with positions advanced by Asian philosophical thinkers. Owen Flana- gan’s The Bodhisattva’s Brain (2011; henceforth, BB) contributes to this emergent trend. BB is divided between two main lines of contention. -
Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 1
Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 1 Curriculum Vitae Owen Flanagan Duke University 201 West Duke Building Box 90743 Durham, NC 27708 +1 919.660.3050 (office) [email protected] (email) University Appointments and Honors Duke University 1993- James B. Duke Professor of Philosophy (Distinguished University Professorship) Associate Graduate Program in Literature Steering Committee Philosophy, Arts, and Literature Initiative (PAL) Professor of Psychology & Neuroscience Professor of Neurobiology Faculty Associate Center for Cognitive Neuroscience Distinguished Visiting Professor, City University of Hong Kong, August-December 2013. Indian Council of Philosophical Research (ICPR) Distinguished Annual Lecturer 2012 (Delhi, Kolkata, Lucknow, Allahabad) Distinguished Visiting Professor, University of Vienna, Dec-Jan, 2011-2012. Jack Lynch Distinguished Professor, Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem NC, Spring 2009. Templeton Distinguished Research Fellow, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA 2006. Six Lectures on “Human Flourishing in the Age of Mind Science” Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 2 February 2006. Distinguished Fellow, Psychology & Biology of Morality, Dartmouth College, Summer 2004. John Findlay Distinguished Visiting Professor, Boston University, 2000. Romanell Phi Beta Kappa Award 1998-1999. Three Lectures on “Science and the Human Image.” Wellesley College 1978-1993 Class of 1919 Reunion Professor of Philosophy, 1989-1993 Professor of Philosophy 1988-89; Assistant Professor 1978-1983; Associate Professor 1983-88. Administrative Experience -
Heather M. Wallace
Heather M. Wallace CONTACT Department of Philosophy [email protected] Duke University [email protected] West Duke Building 1 (919) 308-7054 Box 90743 Durham, NC 27708 EDUCATION Duke University, PhD Candidate Present Dissertation Advisors: Owen Flanagan (Philosophy) and Toril Moi (Literature) GPA: 3.79 Certificate in College Teaching Whitworth University, B.A. Philosophy and English 2011 GPA: 3.98 summa cum laude DISSERTATION “Barriers to Reciprocity: The Problem of Others’ Minds” Directors: Owen Flanagan (Philosophy) and Toril Moi (Literature) An abstract is included at the end of the C.V. RESEARCH Area of Specialization: Philosophy of Mind Areas of Competence: Existentialism, Philosophy of Literature, Feminist Philosophy PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE Duke Center for Philosophy, Arts, and Literature (PAL) Associate Director, present Assistant Director, 2013-2015 Critical Thinking Assessment, Trinity College of Arts & Sciences Duke University Office of Assessment Grader, Spring 2013 1 PUBLICATIONS, Co-Authored Owen Flanagan and Heather Wallace, “The Character of Consciousness” Understanding James, Understanding Modernism. ed. David Evans (Bloomsbury Press), 2017. Owen Flanagan and Heather Wallace, “William James and the Problem of Consciousness” Consciousness and the Great Philosophers. ed. Stephen Leach and James Tartaglia (Routledge Press), 2017. CONFERENCES AND PRESENTATIONS “The Problem of Others’ Minds: Simone de Beauvoir, Ambiguity, and Reciprocity” October 12, 2017: Duke Philosophy Department, hosted by the Duke Philosophy Women