Journal of Philosophy, Inc

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Journal of Philosophy, Inc Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Harder Problem of Consciousness Author(s): Ned Block Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 99, No. 8 (Aug., 2002), pp. 391-425 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3655621 Accessed: 04-08-2015 15:41 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME XCIX, NO. 8, AUGUST 2002 THE HARDER PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS* H. Huxley' famously said: "How it is that anything so re- T. markable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the ap- pearance of Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp" (ibid., p. 19). We do not see how to explain a state of consciousness in terms of its neurological basis. This is the hard problemof consciousness.2 My aim here is to present another problem of consciousness. The harderproblem, as I shall call it, is more epistemological than the hard problem. A second difference: the hard problem could arise for * I would like to thank David Barnett, Paul Boghossian, Tyler Burge, Alex Byrne, David Chalmers, Hartry Field, Jerry Fodor, Paul Horwich, Brian Loar, Tom Nagel, Georges Rey, Stephen Schiffer, and Stephen White for comments on earlier drafts. I am also grateful to Alex Byrne and Jaegwon Kim for reactions when an ancestor of this paper was delivered at a Central APA meeting in 1998. My thanks to the Colloquium on Language and Mind at New York University at which an earlier version of this paper was discussed in 2000, and especially to Tom Nagel as the chief inquisitor. I am also grateful to the audience at the 2001 meeting of Sociedad Filosofica Ibero Americana (SOFIA) and especially to my respondents, Brian McLaughlin and Martine Nida-Rfimelin. And I would also like to thank my graduate class at NYU for their comments, especially Declan Smithies. In addition, I am grateful for discussion at a number of venues where earlier versions of this article were delivered, beginning with the Society for Philosophy and Psychology meeting, June 1997. 1 Lessons in ElementaryPhysiology (New York: Macmillan, 1866); see Gfiven Gfizel- dere, "The Many Faces of Consciousness: A Field Guide," in Block, Owen Flanagan and Gfizeldere, eds., The Nature of Consciousness:Philosophical Debates (Cambridge: MIT, 1997), pp. 1-67, footnote 6. 2 See Thomas Nagel, "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?" The Philosophical Review, LXXXIII(1974): 435-50. Joseph Levine introduced the "explanatory gap" terminol- ogy (to be used later)--"Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly,LxIv (1983): 354-61. David Chalmers and Galen Strawson distinguished between the hard problem and various "easy problems" of how consciousness functions-Chalmers, The ConsciousMind (New York: Oxford, 1996), pp. xxii-xxiii; Strawson, Mental Reality (Cambridge: MIT, 1994), pp. 93-96. 0022-362X/02/9908/391-425 ? 2002 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc. 391 This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 392 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY someone who has no conception of another person, whereas the harder problem is tied closely to the problem of other minds. Finally, the harder problem reveals an epistemic tension or at least discom- fort in our ordinary conception of consciousness which is not sug- gested by the hard problem, and so in one respect is harder. Perhaps the harder problem includes the hard problem and is best thought of as an epistemic add-on to it. Or perhaps they are in some other way facets of a single problem. Then my point is that this single problem breaks into two parts, one of which is more epistemic, involves other minds, and involves an epistemic tension. I. PRELIMINARIES I believe that the major ontological disputes about the nature of consciousness rest on an opposition between two perspectives: (1) Deflationismabout consciousness,in which a priori or at least armchair analyses of consciousness (or at least armchair sufficient conditions) are given in nonphenomenal terms, most prominently in terms of representation, thought, or function. (2) Phenomenalrealism, which consists in the denial of deflationism plus the claim that consciousness is something real. Phenomenal realism is metaphysical realism about consciousness and thus allows the possibility that there may be facts about the distribution of con- sciousness which are not accessible to us even though the relevant functional, cognitive, and representational facts are accessible. Phe- nomenal realism is based on one's first-person grasp of conscious- ness. An opponent might prefer to call phenomenal realism "inflationism," but I reject the suggestion of something bloated. In its most straightforward version, deflationism is a thesis of a priori conceptual analysis, most prominently analysis of mental terms in functional terms. As David Lewis,3 a well-known deflationist noted, this view is the heir of logical behaviorism. Phenomenal realism rejects these armchair, philosophical-reductive analyses. But phe- nomenal realists have no brief against scientific reduction of con- sciousness. Of course, there is no sharp line here, and since the distinction is epistemic, one and the same metaphysical thesis could be held both as a philosophical-reductionist and as a scientific-reduc- tionist thesis.4 3 "An Argument for the Identity Theory," this JOURNAL, LXIII, 1 (January 6, 1966): 17-25. Deflationism with to truth is the view of 4 respect that the utility the concept of truth can be explained disquotationally and that there can be no scientific reduc- tion of truth-Paul Horwich, Truth (Cambridge: Blackwell, 1990; second edition, New York: Oxford, 1998); Hartry Field, "Deflationist Views of Meaning and Con- This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE HARDER PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS 393 I apologize for all the "isms" (deflationism, phenomenal realism, and one more to come), but they are unavoidable since my point here is that there is some tension between two of them. The tension is between phenomenal realism ("inflationism") and (scientific) nat- uralism, the epistemological perspective according to which the de- fault view is that consciousness has a scientific nature-where this is taken to include the idea that conscious similarities have scientific natures. (A view on a given subject is the default if it is the only one for which background considerations give rational ground for tenta- tive belief.) I argue for a conditional in which specifications of phenomenal realism and scientific naturalism (and a few other rela- tively uncontroversial items-including, notably, a rejection of a skep- tical perspective) appear on the left-hand side. On the right-hand side, we have a specification of the epistemic tension which I men- tioned. Deflationists who accept the argument may opt for modus tollens, giving them a reason to reject phenomenal realism. Phenom- enal-realist naturalists may want to weaken their commitment to naturalism or to phenomenal realism. To put the point without explicit "isms":many of us are committed to the idea that conscious- ness is both real and can be assumed to have a scientific nature, but it turns out that these commitments do not fit together comfortably. Modern phenomenal realism has often been strongly naturalistic (for example,Joseph Levine, Brian Loar, Colin McGinn, Christopher Peacocke, John Perry, Sydney Shoemaker, John Searle, and myself5). Daniel Dennett6 has often accused phenomenal realists of closet dualism. Georges Rey7 has argued that the concept of consciousness tent," Mind, CIII (1994): 249-85. Deflationism with respect to consciousness in its most influential form is, confusingly, a kind of reductionism-albeit armchair reductionism rather than substantive scientific reductionism-and thus the termi- nology I am following can be misleading. I may have introduced this confusing terminology in my review of Daniel Dennett's ConsciousnessExplained in this JOUR- NAL,XC, 4 (April 1993): 181-93. 5 Levine; Loar, "Phenomenal States," in Block, Flanagan, and Gfizeldere, eds., pp. 597-616; McGinn, The Problemof Consciousness(Cambridge: Blackwell, 1991); Pea- cocke, Sense and Content (New York: Oxford, 1983); Perry, Knowledge,Possibility and Consciousness(Cambridge: MIT, 2001); Shoemaker, "The Inverted Spectrum," this JOURNAL, LXXIX, 7 (July 1982): 357-81; Searle, The Rediscoveryof the Mind (Cam- bridge: MIT, 1992). 6 ConsciousnessExplained (Boston: Little Brown, 1991). 7 "A Reason for Doubting the Existence of Consciousness," in R. Davidson, G. Schwartz, D. Shapiro, eds., Consciousnessand Self-Regulation, Volume 3 (New York: Plenum, 1983), pp. 1-39. In previous publications-"On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness," The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, xviII, 2 (1995): 227-47-I have argued that Rey's alleged incoherence derives from his failure to distinguish between phenomenal consciousness and other forms of consciousness This content downloaded from 128.122.149.154 on Tue, 04 Aug 2015 15:41:39 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 394 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY is incoherent. The upshot here is that there is a grain of truth in these accusations.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Mind
    From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Philosophy of Mind Frank Jackson, Georges Rey Philosophical Concept ‘Philosophy of mind’, and ‘philosophy of psychology’ are two terms for the same general area of philosophical inquiry: the nature of mental phenomena and their connection with behaviour and, in more recent discussions, the brain. Much work in this area reflects a revolution in psychology that began mid-century. Before then, largely in reaction to traditional claims about the mind being non-physical (see Dualism; Descartes), many thought that a scientific psychology should avoid talk of ‘private’ mental states. Investigation of such states had seemed to be based on unreliable introspection (see Introspection, psychology of), not subject to independent checking (see Private language argument), and to invite dubious ideas of telepathy (see Parapsychology). Consequently, psychologists like B.F. Skinner and J.B. Watson, and philosophers like W.V. Quine and Gilbert Ryle argued that scientific psychology should confine itself to studying publicly observable relations between stimuli and responses (see Behaviourism, methodological and scientific; Behaviourism, analytic). However, in the late 1950s, several developments began to change all this: (i) The experiments behaviourists themselves ran on animals tended to refute behaviouristic hypotheses, suggesting that the behaviour of even rats had to be understood in terms of mental states (see Learning; Animal language and thought). (ii) The linguist Noam Chomsky drew attention to the surprising complexity of the natural languages that children effortlessly learn, and proposed ways of explaining this complexity in terms of largely unconscious mental phenomena. (iii) The revolutionary work of Alan Turing (see Turing machines) led to the development of the modern digital computer.
    [Show full text]
  • Emergence, Function, and Realization
    To appear in Routledge Handbook of Emergence. Please cite the published version. EMERGENCE, FUNCTION, AND REALIZATION Umut Baysan “Realization” and “emergence” are two concepts that are sometimes used to describe same or similar phenomena in philosophy of mind and the special sciences, where such phenomena involve the synchronic dependence of some higher-level states of affairs on the lower-level ones. According to a popular line of thought, higher-level properties that are invoked in the special sciences are realized by, and/or emergent from, lower-level, broadly physical, properties. So, these two concepts are taken to refer to relations between properties from different levels where the lower-level ones somehow “bring about” the higher-level ones. However, for those who specialise in inter-level relations, there are important differences between these two concepts – especially if emergence is understood as strong emergence. The purpose of this chapter is to highlight these differences. Realizing a Function Realization, as an inter-level relation, is often thought to be tightly related to the notion of a function, and this is arguably due to the fact that the notion of realization was imported into the contemporary philosophy of mind literature with a defence of functionalism alongside the refutation of the view that mental properties (e.g. being in pain) are identical with physical properties (e.g. having C-fibre stimulation). It was suggested by Putnam (1967) that mental properties are multiply realizable by different physical properties in different organisms – such that it is possible for two organisms to instantiate the same mental property without having any physical properties in common – therefore, a given mental property cannot be identified with any particular physical property.
    [Show full text]
  • Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2Nd Edition, Macmillan Press, 2005
    Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition, MacMillan Press, 2005 Multiple realizability is a key issue in debates over the nature of mind and reduction in the sciences. The subject consists of two parts: “multiplicity” and “realizability.” “Multiplicity” designates a kind of variability in the mechanism and materials from which a particular type of thing can be made. “Realizability” designates a specific relation that exists when there is the stated variability. Realizability Apart from the broad folk notion of realization meaning that a thing is “made real,” philosophers apply several technical notions to paradigm cases such computational states realized by engineering states, minds realized by brains, and persons realized by their bodies. The technical notions fall into three broad traditions: “mathematical,” “logico- semantic,” and “metaphysical.” The mathematical tradition equates realization with a form of mapping between objects. Generally speaking, x mathematically realizes y because elements of y map onto elements of x. The notion is useful for many purposes, for example, when constructing a formal model of a particular domain. However, since mapping extends to models as well as reality, it fails to distinguish between “simulated” versus “genuine” realizations. Heavenly stars can be mapped onto grains of sand, but grains of sand do not realize heavenly stars in any genuine sense. Similarly, the mental states described by a cognitive program can be mapped onto unthinking groups of things, but unthinking groups of things do not realize mental states in any genuine sense (Block, 1978). Hence, to capture what is essential to genuine realization, William Lycan (1987) adds ideas about evolutionary function, while David Chalmers (1994) emphasizes facts about causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture XI: Mind As a Computer
    Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture XI: Mind as a Computer: Machine Functionalism Tim Black California State University, Northridge Spring 2004 I. MULTIPLE REALIZABILITY AND FUNCTIONALISM a. Mental states (and events and properties) are multiply realizable. That is, one and the same mental state can be realized in different ways in different physical systems. “Mental property M—say, being in pain—may be such that in humans C-fiber activation realizes it but in other species (think of octopuses and reptiles) the physiological mechanism that realizes pain may well be vastly different” (p. 74). Moreover, the multiple realizability of mental states creates a problem for the Psychoneural (Type) Identity Theory. For, if one and the same mental state can be realized in different ways in different creatures, then there is no one type of physical state with which any particular type of mental state is identical. Pain, for example, is not identical to C-fiber activation since pain is realized in other creatures by some other type of physical state. b. The multiple realizability of mental states pushes us away from the Psychoneural (Type) Identity Theory, and toward Functionalism. “According to functionalism, a mental kind is a functional kind, or a causal-functional kind, since the “function” involved is to fill a certain causal role. … Thus, the concept of pain is defined in terms of its function, and the function involved is to serve as a causal intermediary between typical pain inputs (tissue damage, trauma, etc.) and typical pain outputs (winces, groans, escape behavior, etc.). The functionalist will say that this is generally true of all mental kinds: Mental kinds are causal-functional kinds, and what all instances of a given mental kind have in common is the fact that they serve a certain causal role distinctive of that kind.
    [Show full text]
  • The Non-Reductionist's Troubles with Supervenience
    ROBERT M. FRANCESCOTTI THE NON-REDUCTIONIST'S TROUBLES WITH SUPERVENIENCE (Received in revised form 29 May 1996) Most physicalists today believe that mental properties can be neurologically realized in many different ways. If some brand of functionalism is correct, then an internal event realizes a mental property in virtue of playing the right functional role, and not because of its intrinsic physical features. This allows that events that differ in neural type might realize the same mental property, the only con- straint being that each of these event can play the functional role de®nitive of that mental property. The belief in multiple realizability is one of the main reasons for the popularity of non-reductive physicalism. If mental states are multiply realizable at the neural level, then they are also multiply realizable, and to a far greater degree, at more basic levels of physical structure ± e.g., the molecular, atomic, and subatomic levels. Of course, the properties of the physical sciences are also multiply realizable; the property of being a carbon atom, for instance, is multiply realizable with respect to subatomic features. However, the problem with mental properties is that they, unlike chemical properties, are thought to be multiply realizable with respect to the entire range of features mentioned by the physical sciences. That is, for any mental property M, and for any event of physical type P, it is possible that M is realized by an event of some physical type other than P. If so, and if this possibility is nomological as well as metaphysical, then mental properties are irreducible in the sense that (NR1) there are no nomologically true biconditionals connecting mental properties with physical properties (i.e., properties of the physical sciences).
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam Has Been One of the Most Influential Philosophers
    Putnam and Computational Functionalism For over half a century, Hilary Putnam has been one of the most influential philosophers. He started his career with several seminal papers in mathematical and philosophical logic. His further contributions, published in his numerous books, collections, and papers, span the philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of mind, psychology and language, metaphysics and epistemology, ethics and moral philosophy, practical philosophy, Jewish philosophy and more. Our focus here is on Putnam’s contributions in the philosophy of mind and psychology (though these are inevitably connected to his work in other domains). In this area, of mind and psychology, Putnam’s major impact relates to functionalism. In the 1960s Putnam promoted a central version of the view, known as computational, or machine, functionalism. The view gained immediate success. One reason why it became so attractive is that functionalism arguably does better as a theory than its two rival views at the time, logical behaviorism and reductive materialism (also known as type- identity theory). Another reason is that computational functionalism aligned with the new science of the mind at the time, namely cognitive science. In the 1980s, however, Putnam became a vocal critic of functionalism; his criticism motivated others to refine and modify the view, or to abandon it altogether. This chapter will focus on Putnam’s arguments for, and then against, functionalism. These arguments will be put in the wider context of the more general discussion about functionalism. We will start with an introduction to functionalism (part 1), then move to computational functionalism (part 2), and after that discuss Putnam’s main argument for the view (part 3).
    [Show full text]
  • On Physical Multiple Realization
    ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION BY RONALD P. ENDICOTT Perhaps no argument has done more to set the direction of contemporary philosophy of mind than the “multiple realizability argument.” First championed by Hilary Putnam and later reformulated by Jerry Fodor, the argument begins with the observation that a given psychological property can be realized by any number of diverse physical systems, and then ends with the conclusion that psychological properties are irreducible vis-à-vis the physical sciences.^ Its target, in other words, is type physicalism and the unity of science, as traditionally conceived. According to one popular criticism, however, the multiple realizability argument has been discredited by the fact that physical properties are also multiply realized} But this, I believe, is a mistake. While the criticism does serve to bring a number of important issues into better focus, it can be shown that the facts about physical multiple realization are perfectly consistent with the Putnam-Fodor style argument, and that, when such facts are rightly understood, they do not vitiate the original point about the irreducibility of psychological properties. /. Multiple Realization In spite of much talk about multiple realization, philosophers have generally been content to leave this central concept unanalyzed. I shall try to remedy this situation by indicating the two most salient features of the concept. First, there is the idea that a property is realized by a number of diverse states, which I take to mean that different state types can provide lawfully sufficient conditions for the instantiation of the multiply realized property. And second, there is the idea that among this range of diverse Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989) 212-224 0279-0750/89/0300-0212 $01.30 Copyright © 1989 University of Southern California ON PHYSICAL MULTIPLE REALIZATION 213 states, there are no lawfully necessary and sufficient conditions for the instantiation of that property.
    [Show full text]
  • Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
    Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind Edited by Jonathan Cohen∗and Brian McLaughliny This volume will introduce the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume will include ten pairs of newly commissioned essays ad- vocating opposing viewpoints | one for each of the ten topics listed below. In addition, the editors will provide a substantive introduction that will lay out the necessary background for the debates and locate the individual topics within philosophy of mind and in relation to one another. The essays will each be around 6000 to 8000 words in length, and will be accessible to upper-level undergraduates and graduate students. Consequently, we expect that the volume could be used as text for advanced courses in phi- losophy of mind. However, the essays will also represent the state of play in the areas, and will contain original argumentation by eminent philosophers, so it will also be an important text for academics working in philosophy of mind and adjoining areas. We have organized our questions under the three headings that, in our minds, structure the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind: questions about the ontology of the mental, questions about the nature of mental content, and questions about the nature of consciousness. For many of the questions on our list, we have suggested a number of backup authors in case our first choices are unable to write the essays. Although some names appear more than once on our list (including appearances as backup authors) we would not allow more than one piece by a single author in the volume.
    [Show full text]
  • Empirical Evidence and the Multiple Realization of Mental Kinds
    Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 6-20-2018 1:30 PM Empirical Evidence and the Multiple Realization of Mental Kinds Danny Booth The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Viger, Christopher David The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Danny Booth 2018 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Booth, Danny, "Empirical Evidence and the Multiple Realization of Mental Kinds" (2018). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 5428. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/5428 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract This thesis explores the use of the concept 'realization' in the philosophy of mind. The primary focus is on the role realization plays in assessing or opposing identity theory. The history of the use of the concept of realization in the philosophy of mind is reviewed, and from that a set of desiderata to be used for assessing accounts of realization is extracted. The desiderata are applied to a sample account of realization proposed by Sydney Shoemaker (2007). Next the application of 'realization' in contemporary contexts is considered,
    [Show full text]
  • Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected]
    Georges Rey, Philosophy, Univ of Maryland, College Park 20742; [email protected] NEW 2009 VERSION (an expansion of the version that appeared in Martin, R. and Kolak, D., The Experience of Philosophy, 6th ed., Oxford UP, 2005) 21 October 2009 Meta-atheism: Religious Avowal as Self-Deception (Long Version)1 1. Introduction I’m not a professional philosopher of religion and have no special knowledge of theology. However, I regularly teach an introductory course in philosophy in which I discuss the standard arguments for the existence of God. The exercise has produced in me a certain incredulity: I have come increasingly to wonder how such extremely smart people, like Aquinas or Descartes, could advance such patently bad arguments, as I think most philosophers (even those who claim to “believe”) would take those arguments to be. At any rate, I find it hard to believe that anyone really buys the “ontological argument,” or any of Aquinas’ “five ways.” Existence may or may not be a predicate, and there may or may not be unmoved movers, uncaused causers, and undesigned teleological systems, but these arguments don’t remotely establish their intended conclusion, the existence of anything like the traditional Christian God with His astounding properties of, e.g., eternality, omniscience, omnipotence and necessary benevolence (for brevity, I’ll refer to these latter properties as “omni” properties, a being possessing them as an “omni” being). And “religious experiences” or “intuitions” no matter how ecstatic or profound, could obviously be explained by any number of other far more modest hypotheses (I'll briefly discuss all these issues in §2 below).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Epiphenomenalism
    Epiphenomenalism – the Do’s and the Don’ts Larry Shapiro and Elliott Sober University of Wisconsin, Madison Abstract: When philosophers defend epiphenomenalist doctrines, they often do so by way of a priori arguments. Here we suggest an empirical approach that is modeled on August Weismann’s experimental arguments against the inheritance of acquired characters. This conception of how epiphenomenalism ought to be developed helps clarify some mistakes in two recent epiphenomenalist positions – Jaegwon Kim’s (1993) arguments against mental causation, and the arguments developed by Walsh (2000), Walsh, Lewens, and Ariew (2002), and Matthen and Ariew (2002) that natural selection and drift are not causes of evolution. A manipulationist account of causation (Woodward 2003) leads naturally to an account of how macro- and micro-causation are related and to an understanding of how epiphenomenalism at different levels of organization should be understood. 1. The Weismann Model August Weismann (1889) is widely credited with disproving the Lamarckian theory of the inheritance of acquired characteristics. In one of his famous experiments, Weismann cut off the tails of newborn mice; when the mice grew up and reproduced, their offspring had tails as long as their parents’ had prior to surgery. These results remained constant over many generations. Weismann saw the same pattern, and the same evidence against the inheritance of acquired characteristics, in the fact that circumcision over many centuries had not caused boys to be born without foreskins. He also thought that his theory of the continuity of the germ plasm threw further doubt on the inheritance of acquired characteristics, though it is worth asking whether this theory was evidence against Lamarckianism (as Gould 2002 argues) or merely assumed that Lamarckian inheritance does not occur.
    [Show full text]
  • Global Consciousness: a Functionalist Neurophilosophical Perspective Connor C
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2019 Global Consciousness: A Functionalist Neurophilosophical Perspective Connor C. Bowen Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Bowen, Connor C., "Global Consciousness: A Functionalist Neurophilosophical Perspective" (2019). CMC Senior Theses. 2198. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/2198 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Claremont McKenna College Global Consciousness: A Functionalist Neurophilosophical Perspective submitted to Professor Amy Kind and Professor Brian Keeley by Connor Bowen for Senior Thesis in Neuroscience & Philosophy Spring 2019 April 28, 2019 Bowen, “Global Consciousness” 2 Bowen, “Global Consciousness” Dedication: This thesis is dedicated to my loving and supportive parents. They deserve a major shout-out of appreciation, for their support and encouragement throughout the years. They have helped me in my development as a person and in my pursuit of an education. Without them, I would not be the man I am today. Thank you. 3 Bowen, “Global Consciousness” 4 Bowen, “Global Consciousness” Table of Contents: ABSTRACT ............................................................................................................... 7 INTRODUCTION .....................................................................................................
    [Show full text]