The Epigenesis of Pure Reason: Systematicity in Kant's Critical

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Epigenesis of Pure Reason: Systematicity in Kant's Critical The Epigenesis of Pure Reason: Systematicity in Kant’s Critical Philosophy by Farshid Baghai A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto Copyright © 2013 by Farshid Baghai Dissertation Abstract Farshid Baghai Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto July 2013 The Epigenesis of Pure Reason: Systematicity in Kant’s Critical Philosophy Kant’s critical philosophy explicitly aspires to be systematic. Whether it achieves this aspiration is another question. Comparing pure reason to “an organized body,” Kant requires a critique of pure reason to be “entirely complete down to the least elements,” and regards this completeness or systematicity as a matter of “all or nothing” (Prol 4:263). He even speaks of critique as “a system of the epigenesis of pure reason” (KrV B167), i.e., an organic whole or system of possible ends that pure reason generates and also organizes entirely out of itself. Nonetheless, the epigenetic model of systematicity, which underlies critical philosophy, remains buried in Kant’s corpus. Neither Kant nor any interpreter of critical philosophy makes clear why and how pure reason generates and organizes itself as a self-standing operating system or whole of possible ends. They also do not explicate what this epigenetic conception of systematicity entails for the functioning of theoretical reason, practical reason, and the power of judgement. This dissertation investigates the question of the systematicity of pure reason in Kant’s critical philosophy, presenting an epigenetic interpretation of Critique of Pure Reason through the lens of the transcendental doctrine of method. It argues that, in its primary sense, a critique of pure reason is the methodological epigenesis – i.e., self- ii generation and self-organization – of pure reason as an organic system or embryonic whole of possible ends. The dissertation proceeds by discussing: 1) what motivates pure reason to generate itself as a system or whole of possible ends; 2) how pure reason generates itself as a whole of possible ends; 3) how pure reason structures this whole into organic parts; and 4) how pure reason’s self-generation and self-organization make the table of judgements transcendentally systematic. In contrast to prevalent readings of Kant, this methodological interpretation articulates the most basic – i.e., disciplinary – sense of critique, and accounts for the epigenetic systematicity of critical philosophy. In a broader philosophical sense, the account demonstrates how critique – or transcendental negativity – is the generative ground of all positivity. It suggests new ways to conceive the relation between Kant’s critical philosophy and post-Kantian philosophies in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. More specifically, this interpretation reveals that Kant’s critical philosophy is closer to German Idealism than usually thought, and yet very different when their common focus on systematicity is better understood. iii Acknowledgements While doing research for and writing this dissertation, I have received much help and support, in many different ways. I would like to thank my supervisor, Paul Franks, and my readers, Rebecca Comay and Lambert Zuidervaart. Paul saw the significance of this project in its inception, and gave me unconditional freedom to pursue my thoughts. From his work, I learned how to learn from the history of philosophy. Rebecca’s thinking has inspired me from the first year in graduate school. Her belief in and enthusiasm for the project helped me persevere through difficult times in writing. Lambert’s writings and seminars heightened my sensitivities to the redemptive significance of philosophy. His encouragement and probing comments helped improve my research significantly. Thanks are also due to Stephen Engstrom, Robert Gibbs, Margaret Morrison, Amy Mullin, and Ulrich Schlösser. Stephen Engstrom appraised the dissertation in a way that was at once generous and critical. Robert Gibbs and Ulrich Schlösser kindly agreed to read the dissertation on short notice and to be examiners at my final oral defense. Margaret Morrison, my teaching mentor, gave welcome support at various stages throughout my graduate studies. Amy Mullin warmly accepted to be on my dissertation committee before I decided to shift my focus from the third Critique to the first Critique. I am grateful to James Porter who read the dissertation draft carefully, from the beginning to the end, and made numerous useful suggestions. I am also thankful to Katayoun Baghai and Rachel Bryant whose feedback on parts of the dissertation helped improve its clarity. Margaret Opoku-Pare offered kind assistance in all administrative matters. This doctoral research has been facilitated by an Ontario Graduate Scholarship, from the Government of Ontario, and a Canada Graduate Scholarship, from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. I would like to thank my friends Azar, Bahar, Doug, James, Katy, Mahmood, Nasrin, Paula, and Rachel. With them, I have shared my frustrations, disillusionments, excitements, and hopes, including those I experienced during my time in graduate school. I am fortunate to enjoy their friendships through the twists and turns of life. I am appreciative of the support of my sister, Fereshteh, and my brothers, Parviz and Rashid, during my graduate studies. Above all, I am thankful to my parents for their care and sacrifice. This dissertation is dedicated to my mother, Safa Bahadori, and to the memory of my father, Hamid Baghai. iv Contents Introduction 1 1. Metaphysics and the Problem of Method 63 2. Self-Generation of the Whole of Pure Reason 114 3. Self-Organization of the Parts of Pure Reason 200 4. The Systematicity of the Table of Judgements 262 Conclusion 313 Bibliography 316 v “Of course, the triadic form must not be regarded as scientific when it is reduced to a lifeless schema, a mere shadow, and when scientific organization is degraded into a table of terms. Kant rediscovered this triadic form by instinct, but in his work it was still lifeless and uncomprehended;” Hegel “… Kant has at least provided the first impulse which could carry philosophy beyond ordinary consciousness, and has at least shown the ground of the object that appears in consciousness; but he never even considered clearly, let alone explained, that this ground of explanation lying beyond consciousness is in the end no more than our own ideal activity…” Schelling “I am … certain that Kant has entertained the thought of such a system, that all of the things he has actually presented are fragments and results of this system, and that his assertions make coherent sense only on this assumption. Perhaps he himself has not thought this system through with sufficient precision and clarity to be able to present it to others; or perhaps he has indeed done so, but simply did not wish to present it to others…. ” Fichte “The greatest and perhaps only utility of all philosophy of pure reason is ... only negative.” “Transcendental philosophy is the act of consciousness whereby the subject becomes the originator of itself....” Kant vi Introduction Kant’s critical philosophy explicitly aspires to be systematic. Whether it achieves this aspiration is another question. Comparing pure reason to “an organized body,” Kant requires a critique of pure reason to be “entirely complete down to the least elements,” and regards this completeness or systematicity as a matter of “all or nothing” (Prol 4:263).1 He even speaks of critique as “a system of the epigenesis of pure reason” (KrV B167), i.e., an organic whole or system of possible ends that pure reason generates and also organizes entirely out of itself. Nonetheless, the epigenetic model of systematicity, which underlies critical philosophy, remains buried in Kant’s corpus. Neither Kant nor any interpreter of critical philosophy makes clear why and how pure reason generates and organizes itself as a self-standing operating system or whole of possible ends. They also do not explicate what this epigenetic conception of systematicity entails for the functioning of theoretical reason, practical reason, and the power of judgement. This dissertation investigates the question of the epigenesis, or genetic-systematic self-determination, of pure reason. The following introduction articulates the necessity, task, and structure of such investigation in four sections. The first section presents an overview of major responses to the question of systematicity in critical philosophy, and shows the need to take up this question in terms of the epigenesis of pure reason. The second section poses the central argument of the dissertation: critique of pure reason is in essence the methodological epigenesis – i.e., self-generation and self-organization – of pure reason as an embryonic whole or organic system of possible ends. The third section demonstrates that the failure to appreciate the epigenetic nature of the critical system lies 1 Abbreviations used in quoting and referring to Kant’s works are included in the bibliography. 1 primarily in the widespread neglect of the first Critique as a treatise on the method of metaphysics. Emphasizing the need for a close reading of the transcendental doctrine of method as the culminating section of the first Critique, the last section of the introduction outlines the task and structure of the ensuing investigation. 1. The systematicity of pure reason Kant on the systematicity of pure reason Despite characterizing the critical system in terms of the epigenesis of pure reason, Kant does not provide a clear account of the formation and functioning of this system. In fact, Kant’s own statements on the systematicity of critical philosophy seem inconsistent and contradictory. In the first edition of the first Critique, Kant claims that his comprehensive approach to the perennial problems of metaphysics makes critique systematic: “there cannot be a single metaphysical problem that has not been solved here, or at least to the solution of which the key has not been provided” (KrV Axiii).
Recommended publications
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter
    Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter Daniel Rothbart, Irmgard Scherer Abstract: Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle relationships between the experimental scientist, the modern instrument, and nature’s atomic particles. The principle of purposive- ness which governs judgment has also a role in implicitly guiding modern experimental science. In Part 1 we explore Kant’s philosophy of science as he shows how knowledge of material nature and unobservable entities is possible. In Part 2 we examine the way in which Kant’s treatment of judgment, with its operating principle of purposiveness, enters into his critical project and under- lies the possibility of rational science. In Part 3 we show that the centrality given to judgment in Kant’s conception of science provides philosophical in- sight into the investigation of atomic substances in modern chemistry. Keywords : Kant , judgment , purposiveness , experimentation , investigation of matter . Introduction Kant’s philosophy of science centers on the problem of how it is possible to acquire genuine knowledge of unobservable entities, such as atoms and molecules. “What and how much can the understanding and reason know apart from all experience?” ( CPuR , Axvii). This raises the question of the role of experiments in the knowability ( Erkennbarkeit ) and the experientiality (Erfahrbarkeit ) of nature. Kant’s insights into the character of scientific experimentation are not given the hearing they deserve. We argue that Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle inter- actions between the experimental chemist, the modern chemical instrument, and molecular substance.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Towards a Reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-03257-6 - New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism Edited by Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti Excerpt More information Introduction: towards a reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas de Warren and Andrea Staiti In the summer of 1914, T. S. Eliot arrived in Marburg from Harvard University to attend a summer course in philosophy before taking up residency at Merton College, Oxford, for a year of study with Harold Joachim, F. H. Bradley’s successor. At the University of Marburg, Eliot met Paul Natorp, who assisted him in finding affordable accommodation and lectured in his course on philosophy. The outbreak of the First World War would cut short Eliot’s stay in Marburg, but not before he had the chance to sketch a portrait of the venerable Neo-Kantian Professor. Natorp strikes a professorial pose, one arm tucked behind his back, the other slung across his waist. With elven ears and bald cranium, the philosopher appears endearing in his otherworldliness. Natorp’s face is hidden behind oval glasses, so large that they seem to constitute a hindrance rather than an aid to seeing reality. Eliot’s sketch can be seen as a visual epitome for how Neo-Kantianism appeared to a younger generation of intellectuals and philosophers who would come of age in the aftermath of a Europe laid waste through the cataclysm of the Great War. Eliot’s amusing sketch is an apt illustration for what Hans-Georg Gadamer, who wrote his PhD dissertation on Plato under Natorp in 1922, characterized as the Neo-Kantian “calm and 1 confident aloofness” engrossed in “complacent system-building.” With slightly more bite, Hannah Arendt charged Neo-Kantianism with drown- ing philosophy “in a sea of boredom,” thereby offering a softer version of the same hostility that spirited Martin Heidegger’s confrontation with 2 Ernst Cassirer at Davos in 1929.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L
    Contemporary Civilization (Ideas and Institutions Section XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period of Western Man) 1958 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L. Bloom Gettysburg College Basil L. Crapster Gettysburg College Harold A. Dunkelberger Gettysburg College See next page for additional authors Follow this and additional works at: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/contemporary_sec12 Part of the European Languages and Societies Commons, History Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Share feedback about the accessibility of this item. Bloom, Robert L. et al. "5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism. Pt XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period." Ideas and Institutions of Western Man (Gettysburg College, 1958), 53-69. This is the publisher's version of the work. This publication appears in Gettysburg College's institutional repository by permission of the copyright owner for personal use, not for redistribution. Cupola permanent link: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/ contemporary_sec12/5 This open access book chapter is brought to you by The uC pola: Scholarship at Gettysburg College. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of The uC pola. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Abstract The ideas of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) are significant enough to be compared to a watershed in Western thought. In his mind were gathered up the major interests of the Enlightenment: science, epistemology, and ethics; and all of these were given a new direction which he himself described as another Copernican revolution. As Copernicus had shown that the earth revolved around the sun, rather than the sun around the earth, so Kant showed that the knowing subject played an active and creative role in the production of his world picture, rather than the static and passive role which the early Enlightenment had assigned him.
    [Show full text]
  • Marburg Neo-Kantianism As Philosophy of Culture
    SamanthaMatherne (Santa Cruz) Marburg Neo-Kantianism as Philosophy of Culture 1Introduction Although Ernst Cassirer is correctlyregarded as one of the foremost figures in the Neo-Kantian movement thatdominated Germanyfrom 1870 – 1920,specifying ex- actlywhat his Neo-Kantianism amountstocan be achallenge. Not onlymustwe clarify what his commitments are as amember of the so-called MarburgSchool of Neo-Kantianism, but also giventhe shift between his earlyphilosophyof mathematics and naturalscience to his later philosophyofculture, we must con- sider to what extent he remained aMarburgNeo-Kantian throughout his career. With regard to the first task, it is typical to approach the MarburgSchool, which was foundedbyHermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, by wayofacontrast with the otherdominant school of Neo-Kantianism, the Southwest or Baden School, founded by Wilhelm Windelband and carried forward by Heinrich Rick- ert and Emil Lask. The going assumption is that these two schools were ‘rivals’ in the sense that the MarburgSchool focused exclusively on developing aKantian approach to mathematical natural sciences(Naturwissenschaften), while the Southwest School privileged issues relatingtonormativity and value, hence their primary focus on the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). If one accepts this ‘scientist’ interpretation of the MarburgSchool, one is tempted to read Cas- sirer’searlywork on mathematicsand natural science as orthodoxMarburgNeo- Kantianism and to then regardhis laterwork on the philosophyofculture as a break from his predecessors, veeringcloser
    [Show full text]
  • Humanity As an Ideal and an End in Itself
    1 Humanity as an Idea, as an Ideal, and as an End in Itself Introduction Kant’s emphatic division of moral philosophy into a purely rational ‘metaphysics of morals’ and a more empirically influenced ‘practical anthropology’ or ‘moral anthropology’ poses significant interpretive challenges.1 One problematic area is the role that humanity can play in a rationally derived metaphysics of morals, since human beings are not purely rational and their characteristics seem to be known partly through empirical observation. Difficult questions arise even at the level of basic moral principles, since Kant says that the Categorical Imperative is meant to be a supreme principle of morality that is ‘grounded on pure reason alone, independently of all experience’ (Kant 2002: 210; G 4.409), and yet gives humanity a central role in one version of the Categorical Imperative, saying that humanity (die Menschheit) in oneself and others must be treated as an end in itself (Kant 2002: 230; G 4.429). The concept of ‘humanity’ in this ‘humanity formulation’ of the Categorical Imperative presumably must be accessible through reason alone, if Kant is to maintain a partition between purely rational morality and empirical ‘moral anthropology’. Furthermore, even when Kant turns to the application of basic, purely rational, moral principles to human beings, he at least sometimes maintains that this resulting ‘metaphysics of morals’ must be ‘scrupulously cleansed of everything empirical’ (Kant 2002: 190; G 388). How humanity can be the central object of concern in a rational, a priori moral principle, or in a system of moral duties that applies such principles to humans through reason alone, without taking their empirically known features into account, is not obvious.
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Judgment PHI 502: Spring 2017
    Critique of Judgment PHI 502: Spring 2017 Instructor Information: Course information: Instructor: Des Hogan Seminar time and location: Office: 206 Marx Hall Friday 10-12:50, Marx 201 Phone: 258-4295 Email: [email protected] Description: A study of Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790). Our topics will include Kant’s motivations for a critique of judgment; principles of ‘reflective’ and ‘determining’ judgment; theory of aesthetic judgment, including epistemology and metaphysics of the beautiful and sublime; theory of genius; teleology in the critical philosophy—including harmony of the cognitive faculties, organisms, scope and limits of mechanical explanation, physico- and ethico-theology; the relation of ethics, aesthetics and teleology. A basic familiarity with Kant’s theoretical philosophy is presupposed. Required text: Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment (Cited as KU by Akademie pagination, volume and page number, e.g. KU Ak. 5:200) I recommend the translation by Guyer and Matthews in the Cambridge University Press edition of Kant’s works (New York: CUP 2000. Paperback ISBN 0-521-34892-7) Other primary texts: Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason Kant, Critique of Practical Reason Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Kant, Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime Kant, On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy Reading Schedule: Below I append a suggested reading schedule for working through the main text. (The bracketed pagination refers to the Guyer/Matthews translation.) Additional primary and secondary readings will be made available on Blackboard as we proceed. We will be joined later in the semester by Professor Thomas Teufel (Baruch College/CUNY Graduate Center), who will lead a session on Kant and teleology.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte's Position
    Fichte’s Position: Self-Awareness and the Space of Reasons Paul Franks I: Introduction Of all the famous figures in the history of philosophy, Johann Gottlieb Fichte may perhaps have the worst reputation. Others have been accused of equivocations, inconsistencies, non sequiturs and other blunders. But Fichte’s view has the distinction that it has regularly been described as verging upon insanity, sometimes even as attaining it. Here, for example, is Bertrand Russell: “Kant’s immediate successor, Fichte, abandoned ‘things in themselves’ and carried subjectivism to a point which seems almost to involve a kind of insanity. He holds that the Ego is the only ultimate reality, and that it exists because it posits itself; the non-Ego, which has a subordinate reality, also exists only because the Ego posits it. The Ego as a metaphysical concept easily became confused with the empirical Fichte . .”i Later, I will cite Jean Paul, a contemporary of Fichte’s, who also associates Fichteanism with a literally crazy subjectivism. Now I want to note that a view of Fichte surprisingly like Russell’s -- and indeed a view of the development of modern philosophy somewhat similar to Russell’s -- can also be found on what we Englishmen quaintly call the continent. Thus Heidegger, like Russell, sees the development of philosophy since Descartes as the ascent of subjectivism, and, again like Russell, Heidegger regards Fichte’s philosophy as a high-point of a regrettable journey.ii For all their differences, both Anglo-American and continental traditions of twentieth century philosophy have shared a common enemy: subjectivism.iii By subjectivism, I think it is fair to say, both traditions have meant the extension of the Cartesian view of the mind to the whole of reality.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Fall 2009 The rT ansformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre Kenneth Angwe Agede Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Agede, K. (2009). The rT ansformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/251 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE TRANSFORMATION OF KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM: FICHTE’S WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Kenneth Angwe Agede December 2009 Copyright by Kenneth Angwe Agede 2009 iii THE TRANSFORMATION OF KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM: FICHTE’S WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE By Kenneth Angwe Agede Approved November 6, 2008 Approved____________________________________________ Tom Rockmore, Ph.D., Dissertation Director Professor of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ Ronald Polansky, Ph.D., Reader Professor of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D., Reader Assistant
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendental Idealism, Transcendental Realism, and the Possibility of Objective Reference
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2008 Transcendental Idealism, Transcendental Realism, and the Possibility of Objective Reference Eric Dane Walker The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Walker, Eric Dane, "Transcendental Idealism, Transcendental Realism, and the Possibility of Objective Reference" (2008). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 1137. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/1137 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM, TRANSCENDENTAL REALISM, AND THE POSSIBILITY OF OBJECTIVE REFERENCE By Eric Dane Walker B.S. Cell Biology and Neuroscience, Montana State University, Bozeman, MT, 2003 B.A. Philosophy, Montana State University, Bozeman, MT, 2003 Thesis presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy The University of Montana Missoula, MT Spring 2008 Approved by: Dr. David A Strobel, Dean Graduate School Dr. Stephen Grimm, Chair Philosophy Dr. Albert Borgmann Philosophy Dr. Gordon G. Brittan, Jr. Philosophy, Montana State University, Bozeman, MT Walker, Eric, M.A., May 2008 Philosophy Transcendental Idealism, Transcendental Realism, and the Possibility of Objective Reference Chair: Dr. Stephen Grimm The goal of my thesis is to understand why Kant thinks that transcendental idealism can secure empirical realism, the idea that there really exists an objective world that we can come to know through experience.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY and the PHENOMENON of MIND
    THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY and the PHENOMENON OF MIND It would have been foolish even to think of the solution of such a problem without having prepared myself by a thorough study of the means and by busying myself with less difficult problems Weierstrass THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY and the PHENOMENON OF MIND Richard B. Wells Copyright © 2006 by Richard B. Wells All Rights Reserved This book is dedicated to my loving sisters, Sherri and Melody, who are the talented members of our family. Contents Preface xxv 1. First Prolegomenon: The Phenomenon of Mind 1 § 1. Common Views of the Mind 1 § 2. Different Views of the Mind 2 § 3. Empirical Materialism 3 § 4. Scientific Materialism 5 § 4.1 The Mind Dust Theory 7 § 4.2 The Behaviorist Theory 8 § 4.3 The Functionalism Theory 8 § 5. The Mentalist Views 13 § 5.1 Theme I: Mind is Intelligence or Reason and is Part of the Soul 13 § 5.2 Theme II: Mind is a Thinking Substance 16 § 5.3 Francis Bacon and the Dawn of the Age of Reason 17 § 5.4 Rationalism and Mind as Substance 19 Descartes 20 Leibniz 23 The Supersensible 25 Monads 28 Leibniz' "Art of Discovery" 33 § 5.5 Theme III: Mind is a Soul or Spirit, Having the Power of Cognition and Action 35 Representationalism 37 Subjective Idealism 41 Hume's Skepticism 43 § 5.6 Two Other Rationalist Themes 47 Theme IV: Mind as a Particular Mode of God's Thought 47 Theme V: Mind as Self-Consciousness, Knowing Itself as Universal 49 § 6. The Unified Themes 51 v Contents § 6.1 Theme VI: Mind as an Organization of Mental Phenomena 53 Advantages and Shortcomings of Kant's Critical Philosophy 60 § 6.2 Theme VII: Mind as the Totality of Mental Processes and the Principle of Meaningful and Purposive Behavior 62 Mind as the Stream of Thought 63 Genetic Epistemology 69 Summary of Theme VII 72 § 7.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Critique? Critical Turns in the Age of Criticism
    OUTLINES - CRITICAL PRACTICE STUDIES • Vol. 18, No. 1 • 2017 • (28-60) • http://www.outlines.dk What is Critique? Critical Turns in the Age of Criticism Sverre Raffnsøe Copenhagen Business School Abstract: Since the Enlightenment, critique has played an overarching role in how Western society understands itself and its basic institutions. However, opinions differ widely concerning the understanding and evaluation of critique. To understand such differences and clarify a viable understanding of critique, the article turns to Kant’s critical philosophy, inaugurat- ing the “age of criticism”. While generalizing and making critique unavoidable, Kant coins an unambiguously positive understanding of critique as an affirmative, immanent activity. Not only does this positive conception prevail in the critique of pure and practical reason and the critique of judgment; these modalities of critique set the agenda for three major strands of critique in contemporary thought, culminating in among others Husserl, Popper, Habermas, Honneth, and Foucault. Critique affirms and challenges cognition and its rationality, formulates ethical ideals that regulate social interaction, and further articu- lates normative guidelines underway in the ongoing experimentations of a post-natural history of human nature. In contradistinction to esoteric Platonic theory, philosophy at the threshold of modernity becomes closely linked to an outward-looking critique that examines and pictures what human forms of life are in the process of making of themselves and challenges
    [Show full text]