The Transformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Transformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Fall 2009 The rT ansformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre Kenneth Angwe Agede Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Agede, K. (2009). The rT ansformation of Kant's Transcendental Idealism: Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/251 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE TRANSFORMATION OF KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM: FICHTE’S WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Kenneth Angwe Agede December 2009 Copyright by Kenneth Angwe Agede 2009 iii THE TRANSFORMATION OF KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM: FICHTE’S WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE By Kenneth Angwe Agede Approved November 6, 2008 Approved____________________________________________ Tom Rockmore, Ph.D., Dissertation Director Professor of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ Ronald Polansky, Ph.D., Reader Professor of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D., Reader Assistant Professor of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Chair, Department of Philosophy Approved____________________________________________ Christopher Duncan, Ph.D., Dean Dean, McAnulty College and Graduate Scool of Liberal Arts iv ABSTRACT THE TRANSFORMATION OF KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM: FICHTE’S WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE By Kenneth Angwe Agede December 2009 Dissertation supervised by Tom Rockmore This dissertation examines Fichte’s original philosophical system, or the Wissenschaftslehre, against the background of Kant’s transcendental idealism, and was conceived within the framework of restating Kant’s critical philosophy. Although Fichte hyperbolically claims that his philosophical view is identical with Kant’s transcendental system, the question of his relationship to Kant is a controversial one and continues to generate intense debate in the literature. Some Fichte commentators flatly reject comparisons between the two philosophical positions, claiming that Fichte’s system is a variant of Reinhold’s, whose Elementarphilosophie sought to return Kant to a Cartesian model of mind. Others, however, see striking similarities between the theories of Kant and Fichte. They maintain, though, that Fichte’s Kantianism should be qualified: for v although certain aspects of his theory look obviously Kantian, they insist that Fichte’s theory is still unique in a variety of ways. This dissertation argues the thesis that Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre is identical with and yet different from Kant’s theory. To the extent that Fichte rejects a representationalist solution to the problem of knowledge, his position is true to the spirit of Kant’s Copernican turn in philosophy. However, to the extent that his method of presentation differs from Kant’s, Fichte’s view is his own and should be evaluated on its own merit. vi ACKOWLEDGMENT This dissertation affords me the chance to pay a debt of gratitude to individuals and groups who have facilitated me in one way or another in the course of my academic pursuit. Although the individuals are too numerous to mention within the context of the present circumstance, I would like to acknowledge the contribution of the following. I am eternally grateful to Most Rev. A. A. Usuh, the Catholic bishop of the diocese of Makurdi, Nigeria, for allowing me the facility to undertake graduate studies at Duquesne University, Pittsburgh, PA, USA. My special thanks go to my professors in the Department of Philosophy at Duquesne University for their assistance and professionalism. I am immeasurably indebted to my dissertation director, Dr. Tom Rockmore, for his inspiration and guidance. I cannot thank him enough for teaching me the invaluable lesson of being a scholar. I am profoundly grateful to my readers, Dr. Ronald Polansky and Dr. Daniel Selcer, for their critical insights and useful suggestions. I would like to recognize the following, whose camaraderie I enjoyed at one point or another during the course of my graduate program in philosophy. They include Revs. Simeon Iber, Thomas Akpen, CSSp., Matthew Asemagema, Francis Iber, Michael Angula, Hyacinth Alia, Stephen Akange, Pius Ajiki, Joseph Mali, Godffrey Bonnet, Joseph Nietlong, Peter Agema, Thomas Dekaa, Daniel Asue, Vitalis Torwel, Daniel Melaba, Dominic Jir, Gregory Ugah, Matthias Idyu, CSSp, and Louis Yaya. Others are Msgr. Cletus Gotan, Revs. Angus Fraser, CSSp., David Baka, Innocent Jooji, Felix Kumai Kanyip, Stephen Ishor Herbert Bulbwa, Gabriel Gberikon, Samuel Tumba, Emmanuel Abela, Clement Iorliam, Cosmas Jooli, Simon Ikpum, Isaiah Ter, Remigius vii Ihula, Peter Adoboh, Nicholas Tarbo, Francis Wegh, Joseph Oppong, Joseph Dube, Oliver Ortese, and Augustine Igbum. I acknowledge the support and best wishes of the following: Angela Egbikuadje, Franca Niameh, Eunice Atsu, HHCJ, Dorothy Ugbe, HHCJ, Anne Arabome, Antoinette Opara, SHCJ, Brendan Ezeigbo, DDL, Agatha Ozah, HHCJ, Mercy Akoh, SON, Margaret Dowd, Nancy Grimes, Judy Bartley, Terry Wachter, Mary Ann Soerries, Ed Hahn, Brian Giebler, Mike McCleary, Corita Holmes, Carolyne Keith, Margie Moss, Missy Little, Sue Dixon, Waren Tsafa, Patricia Suswam, John Ediri, Dr. and Mrs. Dekaa, Mr. and Mrs. Hule, and Mike Aaga. The faith community of Our Lady of the Valley Church, Donora, PA, graciously provided me with room and board while I was enrolled for graduate studies at Duquesne. For this, I am sincerely grateful. I am equally grateful to my current host community, St. John the Evangelist Church, Honesdale, PA, and its priests, Rev. Martin Boylan, pastor, and Rev. Balaraju Desam, parochial vicar, for their hospitality. My sincere thanks go to my immediate family: Kuleve, Angbiandoo, Nguetor, Kasaren, Saa-Aondo, Denen, and Atamo for graciously enduring my absence while I was pursuing advanced studies in the USA. I remember the memory of Rev. David J. Kriss, Rev. Stanley Wyczawski, Rev. Rene Desmarais, Rev. Geoffrey Iortyer, Rev. Godwin Ande, James Jogo, Ann Kusmirack, and Violet Kowall. I am deeply indebted to Liana MacKinon for painstakingly editing this work. I benefited immensely from her careful work. My parents, Mbailaave and Mnzuulga viii Agede, passed on during the course of my graduate program. To their memory I dedicate this work. ix TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Abstract-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------iv Acknowledgment------------------------------------------------------------------------------------vi General Introduction---------------------------------------------------------------------------------1 CHAPTER ONE Kant’s Transcendental Idealism-----------------------------------------------------------------6 Introduction-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------6 1.1 The Rationalism/Empiricism Debate as the Conceptual Framework for the Emergence of Kant’s Transcendental Idealism-----------------------------------------7 1.2 Kant’s Copernican Revolution in Philosophy----------------------------------------------16 1.3 The Epistemological Import of Kant’s Copernican Turn---------------------------------22 1.3.1 The Thing-in-itself and the Problem of Affection in Kant’s Critical Philosphy----26 1.4 The Immediate Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy---------------------------------31 1.4.1 Frederick Henrich Jacobi (1743–1819)---------------------------------------------------32 1.4.2 Karl Leonhard Reinhold (1757–1823)----------------------------------------------------34 Conclusion-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------41 x CHAPTER TWO The Evolution of Fichte’s Original Philosophical System: The Wissenschaftslehre---------------------------------------------------------------------------42 Introduction------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------42 2.1 Fichte’s Path to Kantianism-------------------------------------------------------------------44 2.2 Aenesidemus: A Synopsis---------------------------------------------------------------------50 2.2.1 The Review of Aenesidemus---------------------------------------------------------------53 2.3 Positing as the Hallmark of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre---------------------------------57 2.3.1 The I’s Self-Positing Activity--------------------------------------------------------------61 2.4 Fichte’s Philosophical System and the Solipsism Charge--------------------------------66 Conclusion-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------70 CHAPTER THREE The Wissenschaftslehre as Circular Epistemology------------------------------------------72 Introduction------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------72 3.1. Circular Demonstration: A Tentative Description----------------------------------------74 3.2. Circular Justification and the Question of Method in Philosophy----------------------78
Recommended publications
  • Hume's Objects After Deleuze
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School March 2021 Hume's Objects After Deleuze Michael P. Harter Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Harter, Michael P., "Hume's Objects After Deleuze" (2021). LSU Master's Theses. 5305. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/5305 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME’S OBJECTS AFTER DELEUZE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael Patrick Harter B.A., California State University, Fresno, 2018 May 2021 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Human beings are wholly dependent creatures. In our becoming, we are affected by an incredible number of beings who aid and foster our growth. It would be impossible to devise a list of all such individuals. However, those who played imperative roles in the creation of this work deserve their due recognition. First, I would like to thank my partner, Leena, and our pets Merleau and the late Kiki. Throughout the ebbs and flows of my academic career, you have remained sources of love, joy, encouragement, and calm.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter
    Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter Daniel Rothbart, Irmgard Scherer Abstract: Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle relationships between the experimental scientist, the modern instrument, and nature’s atomic particles. The principle of purposive- ness which governs judgment has also a role in implicitly guiding modern experimental science. In Part 1 we explore Kant’s philosophy of science as he shows how knowledge of material nature and unobservable entities is possible. In Part 2 we examine the way in which Kant’s treatment of judgment, with its operating principle of purposiveness, enters into his critical project and under- lies the possibility of rational science. In Part 3 we show that the centrality given to judgment in Kant’s conception of science provides philosophical in- sight into the investigation of atomic substances in modern chemistry. Keywords : Kant , judgment , purposiveness , experimentation , investigation of matter . Introduction Kant’s philosophy of science centers on the problem of how it is possible to acquire genuine knowledge of unobservable entities, such as atoms and molecules. “What and how much can the understanding and reason know apart from all experience?” ( CPuR , Axvii). This raises the question of the role of experiments in the knowability ( Erkennbarkeit ) and the experientiality (Erfahrbarkeit ) of nature. Kant’s insights into the character of scientific experimentation are not given the hearing they deserve. We argue that Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle inter- actions between the experimental chemist, the modern chemical instrument, and molecular substance.
    [Show full text]
  • JACOBI and FICHTE on PHILOSOPHY and LIFE Rolf Ahlers
    VITALISM AND SYSTEM: JACOBI AND FICHTE ON PHILOSOPHY AND LIFE Rolf Ahlers Abstract: This paper thematizes the crucial agreement and point of depar- ture between Jacobi and Fichte at the height of the “atheism controversy.” The argument on the proper relationship between philosophy and existence or speculation and life had far-reaching consequences in the history of thought after Jacobi and Fichte in German Idealism on the one hand, primarly advo- cated by Schelling and Hegel, and on the other hand by existentialism and vitalism. The essay focuses first on Jacobi’s philosophy of life, which cen- trally influenced and attracted Fichte to Jacobi. Jacobi’s dualism between speculation, of which he was skeptical, and life, became Fichte’s dualism. Fichte’s transcendentalism, however, prioritized, contrary to Jacobi, both speculation and systematicity. Both of these elements became central for later forms of German Idealism. In the last part of the essay Hegel’s absolute idealism becomes the platform affording a critical perspective on Fichte’s transcendental philosophy. The immediacy of life could for Fichte in 1799 not have any reality without the abstraction from life accomplished by speculative philosophy. Both “speculation” and “life” do not really have any common ground between them—a position which Reinhold attempted to find—because both oppose each other but are also dependent upon another. As “life” could not be had without speculation, so “speculation” is impossible without life, for it needs life to be able to abstract from it. Fichte made this very clear at the height of the “atheism-controversy,” in a letter to Jacobi of April 22, 1799,1 in which he says this (1799:61):2 The original duality, which traverses through the whole system of reason, and which is grounded in the duality of the subject-object is here on its highest plateau.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Towards a Reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-03257-6 - New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism Edited by Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti Excerpt More information Introduction: towards a reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas de Warren and Andrea Staiti In the summer of 1914, T. S. Eliot arrived in Marburg from Harvard University to attend a summer course in philosophy before taking up residency at Merton College, Oxford, for a year of study with Harold Joachim, F. H. Bradley’s successor. At the University of Marburg, Eliot met Paul Natorp, who assisted him in finding affordable accommodation and lectured in his course on philosophy. The outbreak of the First World War would cut short Eliot’s stay in Marburg, but not before he had the chance to sketch a portrait of the venerable Neo-Kantian Professor. Natorp strikes a professorial pose, one arm tucked behind his back, the other slung across his waist. With elven ears and bald cranium, the philosopher appears endearing in his otherworldliness. Natorp’s face is hidden behind oval glasses, so large that they seem to constitute a hindrance rather than an aid to seeing reality. Eliot’s sketch can be seen as a visual epitome for how Neo-Kantianism appeared to a younger generation of intellectuals and philosophers who would come of age in the aftermath of a Europe laid waste through the cataclysm of the Great War. Eliot’s amusing sketch is an apt illustration for what Hans-Georg Gadamer, who wrote his PhD dissertation on Plato under Natorp in 1922, characterized as the Neo-Kantian “calm and 1 confident aloofness” engrossed in “complacent system-building.” With slightly more bite, Hannah Arendt charged Neo-Kantianism with drown- ing philosophy “in a sea of boredom,” thereby offering a softer version of the same hostility that spirited Martin Heidegger’s confrontation with 2 Ernst Cassirer at Davos in 1929.
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic Philosophy and the Hegelian Turn Author(S): Tom Rockmore Source: the Review of Metaphysics, Vol
    Analytic Philosophy and the Hegelian Turn Author(s): Tom Rockmore Source: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 55, No. 2 (Dec., 2001), pp. 339-370 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20131711 Accessed: 13-11-2016 14:01 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics This content downloaded from 200.16.5.202 on Sun, 13 Nov 2016 14:01:37 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE HEGELIAN TURN TOM ROCKMORE I. HE BEGINNING OF THE NEW CENTURY provides a good time to reflect on the most influential philosophers of this period, or those most likely to survive, or again whom we should be reading in a hundred years. The answer one gives to this type of question obviously de pends on what one thinks philosophy is about. I would like to suggest that at the beginning of the new century, at the start of the new millen nium, the philosopher we will and should still be reading at the end of the new century is not one of the obvious candidates, like Russell, Wit tgenstein, Quine, Heidegger, Peirce, or Dewey, Rorty's favorite, but the nineteenth century German thinker, G.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L
    Contemporary Civilization (Ideas and Institutions Section XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period of Western Man) 1958 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Robert L. Bloom Gettysburg College Basil L. Crapster Gettysburg College Harold A. Dunkelberger Gettysburg College See next page for additional authors Follow this and additional works at: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/contemporary_sec12 Part of the European Languages and Societies Commons, History Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Share feedback about the accessibility of this item. Bloom, Robert L. et al. "5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism. Pt XII: The osP t-Enlightenment Period." Ideas and Institutions of Western Man (Gettysburg College, 1958), 53-69. This is the publisher's version of the work. This publication appears in Gettysburg College's institutional repository by permission of the copyright owner for personal use, not for redistribution. Cupola permanent link: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/ contemporary_sec12/5 This open access book chapter is brought to you by The uC pola: Scholarship at Gettysburg College. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of The uC pola. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 5. Immanuel Kant and Critical Idealism Abstract The ideas of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) are significant enough to be compared to a watershed in Western thought. In his mind were gathered up the major interests of the Enlightenment: science, epistemology, and ethics; and all of these were given a new direction which he himself described as another Copernican revolution. As Copernicus had shown that the earth revolved around the sun, rather than the sun around the earth, so Kant showed that the knowing subject played an active and creative role in the production of his world picture, rather than the static and passive role which the early Enlightenment had assigned him.
    [Show full text]
  • Marburg Neo-Kantianism As Philosophy of Culture
    SamanthaMatherne (Santa Cruz) Marburg Neo-Kantianism as Philosophy of Culture 1Introduction Although Ernst Cassirer is correctlyregarded as one of the foremost figures in the Neo-Kantian movement thatdominated Germanyfrom 1870 – 1920,specifying ex- actlywhat his Neo-Kantianism amountstocan be achallenge. Not onlymustwe clarify what his commitments are as amember of the so-called MarburgSchool of Neo-Kantianism, but also giventhe shift between his earlyphilosophyof mathematics and naturalscience to his later philosophyofculture, we must con- sider to what extent he remained aMarburgNeo-Kantian throughout his career. With regard to the first task, it is typical to approach the MarburgSchool, which was foundedbyHermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, by wayofacontrast with the otherdominant school of Neo-Kantianism, the Southwest or Baden School, founded by Wilhelm Windelband and carried forward by Heinrich Rick- ert and Emil Lask. The going assumption is that these two schools were ‘rivals’ in the sense that the MarburgSchool focused exclusively on developing aKantian approach to mathematical natural sciences(Naturwissenschaften), while the Southwest School privileged issues relatingtonormativity and value, hence their primary focus on the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). If one accepts this ‘scientist’ interpretation of the MarburgSchool, one is tempted to read Cas- sirer’searlywork on mathematicsand natural science as orthodoxMarburgNeo- Kantianism and to then regardhis laterwork on the philosophyofculture as a break from his predecessors, veeringcloser
    [Show full text]
  • Humanity As an Ideal and an End in Itself
    1 Humanity as an Idea, as an Ideal, and as an End in Itself Introduction Kant’s emphatic division of moral philosophy into a purely rational ‘metaphysics of morals’ and a more empirically influenced ‘practical anthropology’ or ‘moral anthropology’ poses significant interpretive challenges.1 One problematic area is the role that humanity can play in a rationally derived metaphysics of morals, since human beings are not purely rational and their characteristics seem to be known partly through empirical observation. Difficult questions arise even at the level of basic moral principles, since Kant says that the Categorical Imperative is meant to be a supreme principle of morality that is ‘grounded on pure reason alone, independently of all experience’ (Kant 2002: 210; G 4.409), and yet gives humanity a central role in one version of the Categorical Imperative, saying that humanity (die Menschheit) in oneself and others must be treated as an end in itself (Kant 2002: 230; G 4.429). The concept of ‘humanity’ in this ‘humanity formulation’ of the Categorical Imperative presumably must be accessible through reason alone, if Kant is to maintain a partition between purely rational morality and empirical ‘moral anthropology’. Furthermore, even when Kant turns to the application of basic, purely rational, moral principles to human beings, he at least sometimes maintains that this resulting ‘metaphysics of morals’ must be ‘scrupulously cleansed of everything empirical’ (Kant 2002: 190; G 388). How humanity can be the central object of concern in a rational, a priori moral principle, or in a system of moral duties that applies such principles to humans through reason alone, without taking their empirically known features into account, is not obvious.
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Judgment PHI 502: Spring 2017
    Critique of Judgment PHI 502: Spring 2017 Instructor Information: Course information: Instructor: Des Hogan Seminar time and location: Office: 206 Marx Hall Friday 10-12:50, Marx 201 Phone: 258-4295 Email: [email protected] Description: A study of Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790). Our topics will include Kant’s motivations for a critique of judgment; principles of ‘reflective’ and ‘determining’ judgment; theory of aesthetic judgment, including epistemology and metaphysics of the beautiful and sublime; theory of genius; teleology in the critical philosophy—including harmony of the cognitive faculties, organisms, scope and limits of mechanical explanation, physico- and ethico-theology; the relation of ethics, aesthetics and teleology. A basic familiarity with Kant’s theoretical philosophy is presupposed. Required text: Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment (Cited as KU by Akademie pagination, volume and page number, e.g. KU Ak. 5:200) I recommend the translation by Guyer and Matthews in the Cambridge University Press edition of Kant’s works (New York: CUP 2000. Paperback ISBN 0-521-34892-7) Other primary texts: Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason Kant, Critique of Practical Reason Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Kant, Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime Kant, On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy Reading Schedule: Below I append a suggested reading schedule for working through the main text. (The bracketed pagination refers to the Guyer/Matthews translation.) Additional primary and secondary readings will be made available on Blackboard as we proceed. We will be joined later in the semester by Professor Thomas Teufel (Baruch College/CUNY Graduate Center), who will lead a session on Kant and teleology.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Department
    PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT 3 0 3 DUQUESNE GRADUATE PHILOSOPHY NEWS Spring 2011 • Volume 4, Issue 1 DEPARTMENT NEWS The Philosophy Department welcomes the Rev. Brian Cronin, C.S.Sp., as a visiting associate professor. Fr. Cronin received a Ph.D. in philosophy from Boston College and has taught for numerous years at the Spiritan Mission Seminary in Arusha, Tanzania. His primary scholarly work has involved the philosophy of Bernard Lonergan. In addition to teaching classes in the Philosophy Department, he will also serve as our liaison to the Spiritan Mission Seminary in Arusha. The department continues its Fulbright Scholar Louis Butler (left) and Dr. Patrick Miller, the teacher who inspired him to collaboration major in philosophy, sharing a lighter moment with a stuffed toy raccoon, an animal that with the Spiritan Dr. Miller says serves as a reminder of Aristotelian philosophy’s roots in biology. Missionary Seminary in Arusha, Tanzania. Louis Butler, who earned his bachelor’s degree in 2011, received a Fulbright Kathy Weber, a Scholarship to study in Munich. He will use the scholarship to follow a program graduate teaching of study he designed with a professor at the University of Munich, which focuses assistant, will be teaching full time in its on the thinking of the pre-Socratic philosopher Heraclitus and the 19th-century undergraduate program this upcoming German philosophers Friedrich Nietzsche and G.W.F. Hegel. Since his freshman academic year. year he has worked closely with Dr. Patrick Miller. In conjunction with the initiative for teaching in Tanzania and Kenya, we are continuing our African Book Project, for which we will accept We welcome any news from alumni.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte's Contribution to Higher Education in Germany and the Foundation of the University of Berlin, 1810
    Seeking Originality: Fichte’s Contribution to Higher Education in Germany and the Foundation of the University of Berlin, 1810 By Laura Eakes Utrecht University Department of History W.W. Mijnhardt, Ph.D. Adviser Leen Dorsman, Ph.D. Second Reader 2015 Abstract Seeking Originality: Fichte’s Contribution to Higher Education in Germany and the Foundation of the University of Berlin, 1810 By Laura Eakes Under the crisis of the failing university system and subsequent Napoleonic war, a number of German thinkers formulated a new idea of the university that spawned the modern concept of the research university. Among these thinkers, one man distinguished himself as a pedagogical giant in his own right due to the complexity and thoroughness of his plan. Yet, in history, his contributions are widely overlooked, in large part because his ideas were not implemented by his contemporary, Wilhelm von Humboldt. That man’s name was J.G. Fichte—a thinker perhaps best known for his extremist tendencies and his overwhelming desire to unite all existence under his philosophical system, the Wissenschaftlehre. This thesis is devoted to uncovering Fichte’s originality as an educational thinker, utilizing a methodology inspired by Quentin Skinner, so as to locate Fichte’s intentions within the intellectual matrix in which he found himself in 1807-1808. 2 Table of Contents 1. Introduction………………………………………………………………………….…………..……………4 2. Problems and Solutions……………………………………………………….…………...……………22 3. Fichte’s Contribution……………………………………………………...….………………………….48 4. Seeking Fichte’s Originality…………………………………………………………..………………..71 5. Epilogue……………………………………………………………………………………………………….90 Bibliography…………………………………………………………………………………………………96 3 Introduction Around the turn of the nineteenth century, a number of civic-minded members of the German professoriate took it upon themselves to find a solution to the problems posed by a failing German education system, against the backdrop of the disappearance of the university as an institution all across Europe.
    [Show full text]