<<

The Classical Quarterly http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ

Additional services for The Classical Quarterly:

Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here

Boethvs of Sidon

J. F. Dobson

The Classical Quarterly / Volume 8 / Issue 02 / April 1914, pp 88 - 90 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838800019686, Published online: 11 February 2009

Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0009838800019686

How to cite this article: J. F. Dobson (1914). Boethvs of Sidon. The Classical Quarterly, 8, pp 88-90 doi:10.1017/ S0009838800019686

Request Permissions : Click here

Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ, IP address: 134.176.129.147 on 05 May 2015 BOETHVS OF SIDON. THE study of post-Aristotelian is constantly confused by the perplexing way in which the names of philosophers recur. Zeno, the founder of , is sufficiently well known not be confused with either Zeno the Eleatic or the later Stoic, Zeno of Tarsus, a disciple of ; but when we come to less distinguished names the opportunity of error is greater. If two philosophers of the same name are prominent members of different schools, there ought to be no obscurity, but in an age of eclecticism one school will sometimes adopt doctrines from another, and so make classifica- tion difficult. The case of Boethus is perplexing, firstly, because there were several philosophers of that name; secondly, because the two best known seem both to have been natives of Sidon; thirdly, because of these two the Stoic grafted Peripatetic doctrine on to his system. As famous an authority as Zeller was either confused about the name, or did not succeed in explaining his views clearly.1 In the English edition {Eclectics, 1883), the index separates Boethus from , implying that Boethus the Stoic and Boethus Sidonius the Peripatetic are distinct persons, but in op. cit. p. 35 we read, ' We know that he (i.e. the Stoic) . . . approximated to the Peripatetic doctrine, so as to imperil the purity of his Stoicism.' As no dates are given, the reader might be led into supposing that the philosopher here mentioned is identical with the one who is described later as a Peripatetic; and though the index separates the two, its omission of the title Sidonius in the former case tacitly implies that the words ' of Sidon' are enough to distinguish the Peripatetic, as belonging to him only. It is, however, generally believed that the Stoic as well was a native of Sidon. This supposition is based first on a passage in [Philo], irepl axpdap- criwi Kocrfiov, § 10, p. 497, which refers to BOTJOOS 6 'XiStovios /cal TJavairios as distinguished leaders of Stoicism who denied the theory of the conflagration of the world.2

1 Zeller, Ph. d. Gr. III. 1. 46. 1. TOV xdafiov iravros i\iTO)i.b\t]aa.v. But KOX Ilocridiivios 2 Bake attached great importance to this proves to have been an attempt of Turnebus to passage owing to the vulgate reading current in restore a corrupt MS. reading, and Bernays his , Boijtfos youv /col IloaiS&vios /cai Jlaval- recovered from the Medicean the now generally TIOS, ivSpes iv T015 XTWIKOIS S6y/xa

> 0?. A7roX\oS(ft))[Joo9 XeXev (/c)e(i/)[Y] airo (T)[i

#09 where [ ] indicates the conjectural filling up of lacunae, ( ) letters which are incomplete or of which only some traces remain. If we restrict ourselves to the letters about which there was no doubt in Comparetti's mind, we have remaining only 6o

1 Diels, Doxogr. Gr., p. 107. 3 Comparetti, Pafyro inedito erculatunse, in • Maass attributes it to Sporos of Nicaea, first Rivista di Filologia (Turin) III. 523 (1875). to second century A.D, * Stoic. Vet. Fr. Ill, 265. go BOETHUS OF SIDON a-vveyaafiev ra 'Apio? avrov (Strabo xvi. p. 757) .* A passage from Diogenes has been cited to prove that the Stoic was a contemporary of Chrysippus, viz. Diog. Laert. vii. 54. 6 fiev yap Boi?#o? Kpirijpia -nXeiova airoXeiirei, vovv xal aiadr)ep6fievorjcrcv eivai aicrdrja-iv Kal irpoX^iv. Comparetti, taking these words to imply that Boethus and Chrysippus were contemporary, or Boethus the earlier of the two, decides that the passage is either corrupt or refers to an earlier Stoic also named Boethus, for a contemporary of Chrysippus could not be the successor of Apollodorus mentioned in his papyrus. It is unnecessary, however, to admit this third man, though Luthe as late as 1890 asserted a belief in him {die Erkenntnisstheorie der Stoiker, p. 22). Bake, a century ago, suggested that Diogenes did not mean to suggest, by SicKpepo/jAvo*;, a dispute between two contemporaries; he was not thinking of chronology, but, as it were, arranging parallel extracts, with the comment ' Here Chrysippus does not agree with Boethus.' Susemihl (Rhein. Mus., 1891) recognizes the tenability of Bake's theory, but thinks the translation forced, and supports the reading avrov, which he justifies by showing that Chrysippus has, in the twelfth book of his , quoted by Diogenes just before the present passage, made Kara\ij7r- riKT) (j>avra<7ia the criterion, and now in the first book vrepl \6yov sets up other criteria. We may remember that such ivavnoXoyia—self-contradiction—of Chrysippus is much insisted on by . Boethus the Stoic, therefore, may keep his place after Apollodorus, a successor of . J. F. DOBSON. THE UNIVERSITY, BRISTOL, October, 1913. 1 His views were unorthodox on some points place, as far as we know. Boethus, a compiler (Ammonius in Arist. An. Pr. i. 45). There was of Platonic X^|eis, is mentioned by. the Patriarch also an Academic Boethus (Ind. Here. col. 28), Photius (Bibl. 154, 155). but he considerately selected a different birth-