The Mathematical Roots of Russell's Naturalism and Behaviorism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Mathematical Roots of Russell's Naturalism and Behaviorism Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 10 2008 The Mathematical Roots Of Russell’s Naturalism And Behaviorism James Levine Trinity College Dublin, IRE Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Levine, James (2008) "The Mathematical Roots Of Russell’s Naturalism And Behaviorism," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/ biyclc.v4i0.134 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. From Moore to Peano to Watson 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of with meaning, which in earlier days I had completely ignored” (1968, Cognition, Logic and Communication 194) when “I had regarded language as ‘transparent’ and had never examined what makes its relation to the non–linguistic world” (1959, August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy 145). pages 1-126 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.134 Until relatively recently (in particular, before the 1990’s with the publication of Hylton (1990) and Griffin (1991)), the main focus of interest in Russell’s philosophy, has been, I think it is fair to say, on JAMES LEVINE his views from his 1905 paper “On Denoting” through his 1918 lec- Trinity College, Dublin tures ”The Philosophy of Logical Atomism”1—that is, on the period that includes his acceptance of his theory of descriptions, his completing, with Whitehead, Principia Mathematica (PM), his writing the popular FROM MOORE TO PEANO TO WATSON book The Problems of Philosophy (PoP), and his active engagement with The Mathematical Roots of Russell’s Naturalism and Behaviorism Wittgenstein that leads him to abandon his 1913 manuscript, The The- ory of Knowledge (TK), and culminates in his 1918 lectures entitled “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” (PLA). Such a focus does not involve distinguishing Russell’s early Moore–influenced post–Idealist position INTRODUCTION: SOME ISSUES REGARDING RUSSELL’S PHILOSOPHICAL from the views he accepted in the wake of the 1900 Paris Congress DEVELOPMENT or considering the interplay between these two aspects of Russell’s de- velopment in his 1903 book, The Principles of Mathematics (PoM); nor Russell’s philosophical development is marked by a number of key shifts does it involve any consideration of his concerns with “the problems in his outlook that he vividly describes in his retrospective writings. connected with meaning” that are reflected in such post–1918 publica- Among these are his “becom[ing] a Hegelian” in 1894 (1944a, 10; tions as “On Propositions: What They Are and How They Mean” or The 1967, 63); his 1898 “revolt” against Idealism in which “Moore led the Analysis of Mind. way, but I followed closely in his footsteps” (1959, 54); his attending Further, given a focus on Russell’s writings from 1905–1918, es- the International Congress of Philosophy in Paris in August 1900 which pecially on his less technical writings over that period, it is perhaps he calls “the most important event” in “the most important year in my understandable that a certain picture Russell’s philosophical outlook intellectual life” and at which he was impressed by the “precision” of emerges, one according to which he embraces a foundationalist epis- Peano and his students (1944a, 12); his arriving in 1905 at his theory temology along with an “Augustinian” view of language, both of which of descriptions, which he characterizes as his “first success” in enabling reinforce the general view that the tasks of philosophy are sharply dis- him to resolve his paradox (1959, 79); his “discover[ing] the Theory of tinguished from those of science and both of which make central use Types” in 1906, after which “it only remained to write the book [Prin- of the notion of “acquaintance”. For on the foundationalist epistemol- cipia Mathematica] out” (1967, 152); his beginning in 1911 his associ- ogy that may be found in at least some of these writings, a central task ation with Wittgenstein, whom he characterizes as “perhaps the most of philosophy is to show how, or whether, the beliefs that are taken perfect example I have ever known of genius as traditionally conceived, for granted in ordinary life and science, such as our perceptual beliefs passionate, profound, intense, and dominating” (1968, 98–9); and his concerning ordinary physical objects, may be justified, given that we are “becom[ing] interested”—“during my time in prison in 1918” and in- acquainted with sense–data but not physical objects themselves. And on fluenced, at least in part, by his study at that time of the writings of the view of language that is presented in at least some of these writings, the behavioral psychologist J. B. Watson—“in the problems connected Vol. 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy 3 James Levine From Moore to Peano to Watson 4 the meaning of a word (in a fully analyzed sentence) is an entity cor- [D]oubts had often been expressed about Russell’s notion of responding to that word, while—in accord with his so–called “principle “knowledge by acquaintance” . These doubts only came of acquaintance”—understanding a sentence requires being acquainted to a head, however, in the early 1950s, with the appearance with the entities corresponding to the words in that sentence, and a of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, Austin’s mock- central task of philosophy consists in analyzing the meanings of our ery of “the ontology of the sensible manifold,” and Sellars’s sentences concerning physical objects, given that we are not acquainted “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”, with such objects. Moreover, against the background of this understanding of Rus- but also his views of meaning: sell’s philosophy, it is natural to regard some of the major figures in The distinction between the necessary and contingent—re- post–World War II analytic philosophy—including, for example, the vitalized by Russell and the Vienna Circle as the distinction later Wittgenstein, Quine, Austin, and Sellars—as seeking to under- between “true by virtue of meaning” and “true by virtue mine characteristic features of Russell’s position. This familiar view is of experience”—had usually gone unchallenged, and had reflected, for example, in Richard Rorty’s 1979 book Philosophy and the formed the least common denominator of “ideal language” Mirror of Nature. There Rorty presents Russell, along with Husserl, as and “ordinary language” analysis. However, also in the seeking, in different ways, to establish philosophy as the foundational early fifties, Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” challenged discipline, which through its knowledge of “apodictic truths” (Russell’s this distinction, and with it the standard notion (common “logical forms”, Husserl’s “essences”) is able to assess the standing of to Kant, Husserl, and Russell) that philosophy stood to em- other disciplines. According to Rorty, pirical science as the study of structure to the study of con- . the kind of philosophy which stems from Russell and tent. Given Quine’s doubts (buttressed by similar doubts in Frege is, like classical Husserlian phenomenology, simply Wittgenstein’s Investigations) . , it became difficult to ex- one more attempt to put philosophy in the position which plain in what sense philosophy had a separate “formal” field Kant wished it to have—that of judging other areas of cul- of inquiry and thus how its results might have the desired ture on the basis of a special knowledge of the “founda- apodictic character. (Ibid., 169) tions” of these areas. (1979, 8) According to Rorty, these challenges to Russell’s views of acquaintance along with his views of meaning “were challenges to the views idea of And the “story” Rorty “want[s] to tell” (ibid., 168) is how such founda- a ‘theory of knowledge,’ and thus to philosophy itself, conceived of as a tionalist aspirations of Russell and Husserl were called into question by discipline which centers around such a theory” (ibid.). their successors: Recently, there has been a growing awareness that Russell’s post– [I]n the end, heretical followers of Husserl (Sartre and Hei- 1918 writings call into question the sort of picture that Rorty presents degger) and heretical followers of Russell (Sellars and Quine) of the relation of Russell’s philosophy to the views of subsequent figures raised the same sorts of questions about the possibility of such as the later Wittgenstein, Quine, and Sellars. For an examination apodictic truth which Hegel raised about Kant, (ibid., 167) of those writings shows that by the early 1920’s Russell himself was advocating views—including an anti-foundationalist naturalized epis- thereby undermining the view of philosophy as having a preeminent, temology, and a behaviorist–inspired account of what is involved in un- privileged status. More specifically, for Rorty, Russell’s mid–century suc- derstanding language—that are more typically associated with philoso- cessors attacked not only his views of acquaintance and his sense-data phers from later decades whom Rorty presents as dismantling Russell’s epistemology: philosophy. www.thebalticyearbook.org Vol. 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy 5 James Levine From Moore to Peano to Watson 6 Hence, Thomas Baldwin begins his 2003 paper “From Knowledge Numerous passages support these claims of Baldwin and Dreben.2 Thus, by Acquaintance to Knowledge by Causation” by writing: for example, in his 1924 paper “Logical Atomism”, Russell writes: There are many familiar themes in Russell’s repertoire, but I began to think it probable that philosophy had erred in his later discussions of knowledge include many insights adopting heroic remedies for intellectual difficulties, and which have received little notice.
Recommended publications
  • Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 9-23-2015 12:00 AM Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought Ben Woodard The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Tilottama Rajan The University of Western Ontario Joint Supervisor Joan Steigerwald The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Theory and Criticism A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Ben Woodard 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Woodard, Ben, "Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3314. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3314 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought (Thesis Format: Monograph) by Benjamin Graham Woodard A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy in Theory and Criticism The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Ben Woodard 2015 Abstract: This dissertation examines F.W.J. von Schelling's Philosophy of Nature (or Naturphilosophie) as a form of early, and transcendentally expansive, naturalism that is, simultaneously, a naturalized transcendentalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Studia Philosophiae Religionis 21
    STUDIA PHILOSOPHIAE RELIGIONIS 21 Editores: Catharina Stenqvist et Eberhard Herrmann Ulf Zackariasson Forces by Which We Live Religion and Religious Experience from the Perspective of a Pragmatic Philosophical Anthropology UPPSALA 2002 Doctoral Dissertation in Philosophy of Religion for the Degree of Doctor of Theology at Uppsala University 2002. ABSTRACT Zackariasson, Ulf. 2002. Forces by which We Live. Religion and Religious Experience from the Perspective of a Pragmatic Philosophical Anthropology. Studia Philosophiae Religionis 21. 254 pp. ISBN 91–628–5169–1. ISSN 0346–5446. This study argues that a pragmatic conception of religion would enable philosophers to make important contributions to our ability to handle concrete problems involving religion. The term ’philosophical anthropology’, referring to different interpretative frameworks, which philosophers draw on to develop conceptions of human phenomena, is introduced. It is argued that the classical pragmatists embraced a philosophical anthro- pology significantly different from that embraced by most philosophers of religion; accordingly, pragmatism offers an alternative conception of religion. It is suggested that a conception of religion is superior to another if it makes more promising contributions to our ability to handle extra-philosophical problems of religion. A pragmatic philosophical anthropology urges us to view human practices as taking shape as responses to shared experienced needs. Religious practices develop to resolve tensions in our views of life. The pictures of human flourishing they present reconstruct our views of life, thereby allowing more significant interaction with the environment, and a more significant life. A modified version of reflective equilibrium is developed to show how we, on a pragmatic conception of religion, are able to supply resources for criticism and reform of religious practices, so the extra-philosophical problems of religion can be handled.
    [Show full text]
  • Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology
    Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology (The Contribution of Tadao Ando to the Phenomenological Discourse) Von der Fakultät Architektur, Bauingenieurwesen und Stadtplanung der Brandenburgischen Technischen Universität Cottbus zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktor-Ingenieurs genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Mohammadreza Shirazi aus Tabriz, Iran Gutachter: : Prof. Dr. Eduard Führ Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Karsten Harries Gutachter: Gastprofessor. Dr. Riklef Rambow Tag der Verteidigung: 02. Juni 2009 Acknowledgment My first words of gratitude go to my supervisor Prof. Führ for giving me direction and support. He fully supported me during my research, and created a welcoming and inspiring atmosphere in which I had the pleasure of writing this dissertation. I am indepted to his teachings and instructions in more ways than I can state here. I am particularly grateful to Prof. Karsten Harries. His texts taught me how to think on architecture deeply, how to challenge whatever is ‘taken for granted’ and ‘remain on the way, in search of home’. I am also grateful to other colleagues in L.S. Theorie der Architektur. I want to express my thanks to Dr. Riklef Rambow who considered my ideas and texts deeply and helped me with his advice at different stages. I am thankful for the comments and kind helps I received from Dr. Katharina Fleischmann. I also want to thank Prof. Hahn from TU Dresden and other PhD students who attended in Doktorandentag meetings and criticized my presentations. I would like to express my appreciation to the staff of Langen Foundation Museum for their kind helps during my visit of that complex, and to Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Golden Cord
    THE GOLDEN CORD A SHORT BOOK ON THE SECULAR AND THE SACRED ' " ' ..I ~·/ I _,., ' '4 ~ 'V . \ . " ': ,., .:._ C HARLE S TALIAFERR O THE GOLDEN CORD THE GOLDEN CORD A SHORT BOOK ON THE SECULAR AND THE SACRED CHARLES TALIAFERRO University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana Copyright © 2012 by the University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Taliaferro, Charles. The golden cord : a short book on the secular and the sacred / Charles Taliaferro. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-268-04238-7 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 0-268-04238-1 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. God (Christianity) 2. Life—Religious aspects—Christianity. 3. Self—Religious aspects—Christianity. 4. Redemption—Christianity. 5. Cambridge Platonism. I. Title. BT103.T35 2012 230—dc23 2012037000 ∞ The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources. CONTENTS Acknowledgments vii Introduction 1 CHAPTER 1 Love in the Physical World 15 CHAPTER 2 Selves and Bodies 41 CHAPTER 3 Some Big Pictures 61 CHAPTER 4 Some Real Appearances 81 CHAPTER 5 Is God Mad, Bad, and Dangerous to Know? 107 CHAPTER 6 Redemption and Time 131 CHAPTER 7 Eternity in Time 145 CHAPTER 8 Glory and the Hallowing of Domestic Virtue 163 Notes 179 Index 197 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am deeply grateful for the patience, graciousness, support, and encour- agement of the University of Notre Dame Press’s senior editor, Charles Van Hof.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): Mathematician, Logician, and Philosopher
    Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 Russell: The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): mathematician, logician, and philosopher. He's one of the founders of analytic philosophy. \On Denoting" is a founding document of analytic philosophy. It is a paradigm of philosophical analysis. An analysis of a concept/phenomenon c: a recipe for eliminating c-vocabulary from our theories which still captures all of the facts the c-vocabulary targets. FOR EXAMPLE: \The Name View Analysis of Identity." 2. Russell's target: Denoting Phrases By a \denoting phrase" I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the centre of mass of the Solar System at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. (479) Includes: • universals: \all F 's" (\each"/\every") • existentials: \some F " (\at least one") • indefinite descriptions: \an F " • definite descriptions: \the F " Later additions: • negative existentials: \no F 's" (480) • Genitives: \my F " (\your"/\their"/\Joe's"/etc.) (484) • Empty Proper Names: \Apollo", \Hamlet", etc. (491) Russell proposes to analyze denoting phrases. 3. Why Analyze Denoting Phrases? Russell's Project: The distinction between acquaintance and knowledge about is the distinction between the things we have presentation of, and the things we only reach by means of denoting phrases. [. ] In perception we have acquaintance with the objects of perception, and in thought we have acquaintance with objects of a more abstract logical character; but we do not necessarily have acquaintance with the objects denoted by phrases composed of words with whose meanings we are ac- quainted.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Knowledge in Britain from 1860 to 1950
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 5 2008 Theory Of Knowledge In Britain From 1860 To 1950 Mathieu Marion Université du Quéebec à Montréal, CA Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Marion, Mathieu (2008) "Theory Of Knowledge In Britain From 1860 To 1950," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.129 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Theory of Knowledge in Britain from 1860 to 1950 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of better understood as an attempt at foisting on it readers a particular Cognition, Logic and Communication set of misconceptions. To see this, one needs only to consider the title, which is plainly misleading. The Oxford English Dictionary gives as one August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy of the possible meanings of the word ‘revolution’: pages 1-34 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.129 The complete overthrow of an established government or social order by those previously subject to it; an instance of MATHIEU MARION this; a forcible substitution of a new form of government.
    [Show full text]
  • Using Russell's Theory of Descriptions to S
    Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú The Rise of Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames Seminar 6: From “On Denoting” to “On the Nature of Truth and Falsehood” Using Russell’s Theory of Descriptions to Solve Logical Puzzles One of Russell’s puzzles involves the law of classical logic called the law of the excluded middle. Here is his statement of the puzzle, which involves sentences (37a-c). “By the law of excluded middle, either “A is B” or “A is not B” must be true. Hence either “The present King of France is bald” or “The present King of France is not bald” must be true. Yet if we enumerated the things that are bald and the things that are not bald, we should not find the present King of France in either list. Hegelians, who love a synthesis, will probably conclude that he wears a wig.” (485) 1a. The present King of France is bald. b. The present King of France is not bald. c. Either the present King of France is bald or the present King of France is not bald. In the passage, Russell gives a reason for supposing that neither (1a) nor (1b) is true, which in turn seems to suggest that (1c) isn’t true. But that violates a law of classical logic that tells us that for every sentence S, ⎡Either S or ~S⎤ is true. Since Russell regarded the law as correct, he needed a way of defusing this apparent counterexample. The key to doing this lies in his general rule R for determining the logical form of sentences containing definite descriptions.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell: Cognitivism, Non- Cognitivism and Ethical Critical Thinking
    ARTICLE BERTRAND RUSSELL: COGNITIVISM, NON- COGNITIVISM AND ETHICAL CRITICAL THINKING Angelo Nicolaides University of South Africa [email protected] ABSTRACT Bertrand Russell converted from ethical cognitivism to ethical non-cognitivism and this was historically important, as it gave rise in part, to meta-ethics. It also clarified the central problem between cognitivism and non-cognitivism. Russell’s view was that defining “good” is the basic problem of ethics. If “good” is not amorphous, the rest of ethics will follow. He did not believe in ethical knowledge per se and asserted that reason is, and must only be, the servant of desire. A factual statement is thus true if there is an equivalent fact, but as ethical statements do not state facts, there is no issue of a corresponding fact or the statement being true or false in the sense in which factual statements are. Ethics has no statement whether true or false, but consists only of desires of a general kind and people know intuitively what is “right” or “wrong”. To Russell critical thinking is entrenched in the structure of philosophy. His epistemological conviction was that knowledge is difficult to attain, while his ethical conviction showed that people should be expected to exercise freedom of inquiry when arriving at conclusions of something being either “good” or “bad”. Keywords: Ethics; cognitivism; non-cognitivism; utilitarianism; desire INTRODUCTION Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) was one of the great British thinkers of the twentieth century. He wrote more than 50 books, over 74 years, and established the terms of the debate in logic and philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Second Philosophy of Time (1899–1913)
    Russell’s Second Philosophy of Time (1899–1913) Nikolay Milkov, Bielefeld, Germany 1. Introduction 3. The History of Russell’s Seconds Russell’s second philosophy of time (1899–1913), which Philosophy of Time will be the subject of this paper, is of special interest for Though idealistic, Russell’s philosophy was pluralistic from two reasons. (1) It was basic to his New Philosophy, later the very beginning. His motivation for accepting pluralism called the “philosophy of logical atomism”. In fact, this were two early beliefs of his: First, in order for thinking to philosophy didn’t initially emerge in the period of 1914– be possible at all, its object must be complex. Indeed, a 1919, as many interpreters (e.g. A. J. Ayer) suggest, but simple thing “is unthinkable, since every object of thought with the introduction of Russell’s second philosophy of time can only be thought by means of some complexity”. (1896, (and space). The importance of Russell’s second philos- 564) Secondly, this complexity can be achieved only when ophy of time for his early and middle philosophy can be referring to unique individuals (terms), which are different seen from the fact that it survived the dramatic changes in from any other individual. This was the kernel of Russell’s his philosophy of August–December 1900, and of July atomism.1 1905. There is of course no surprise about this point: it served as their fundament. (2) Russell’s second philos- Thus Russell’s The Foundations of Geometry ophy of time is a locus classicus of all so called B-theories (finished in October 1896) claimed that the objects of of time which define it in terms of the relations of before, cognition have to be complex: in order to know them, we after and simultaneous between events or moments.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absolute Theory of Time Is Intimately Connected With
    The Absolute and the Relational Theories of Space and •rime 1. ·rhe Absolute Theory of Space and Time ; The absolute theory of time is intimately connected with the absolute theory of space, which is to be found first, in 1 clear terms, in Newton's conception of space and time. In Newton • s theory space and time are real indepe~dent entities; each of them constitutes a continuum such that any one part of that continuum is indistinguishab~e from any such other part. The different parts of space and time are due to the things that occupy place and. the events. that happen at moments; they are not due to space apd time themselves. Both space and time are absolutely immutable and homogeneous. · The basic attributes of space and time follow 1 from their h01rogenei ty : "their irtde·pendence from physical contents, their uniformity, continuity and infinity. As 7 space is independent of rnatter, time is also independent in regard to the concrete c.'langes that take place in it. 'I'his has been explicitly formulated by Newton in the following sentences : 11 Absolute, true and mathematical >cime of itself and by its ·own nature flows uniformly, without regard to anything external. It is called duration. Relative, apparent and vu.lgax- time is sane sensible and external measure of absolute time (duration), estimated by the motions of bodies ••• , and is c~m~nly .ll.s.~d .i~stead of true time, 11 2 such as· an hour, a day, a month a week • According to this theory time flows irrespective of the events or changes occurring or not in it.
    [Show full text]
  • Libertarianism Does It Involve Crazy Metaphysics?
    Libertarianism Does it involve crazy metaphysics? 1 Do they look crazy to you? … a little? 2 A war on two fronts • Libertarians have to fight off two enemies, both the soft and hard determinists. I.e. 1. Libertarians need to show that the compatibilist’s definition of free will is wrong (insufficient). 2. Then they need to show that there is some viable libertarian notion of free will. 3 1. Attacking compatibilism • Attacking compatibilism is the easier part. For example: – Richard Taylor’s control box argument, where a person’s desires are under the control of an “ingenious physiologist”. – Peter van Inwagen’s consequence argument • The basic point is that (if determinism is true) we can be controlled through our own desires and choices just as effectively as through direct external forces. 4 2. Show that libertarianism is viable • It needs to be shown that there is some coherent notion of freedom that involves: – Self-determination. (My action isn’t determined, or selected, by external causes, but only by me, the self, at the moment of decision.) – Authorship. We select our actions on the basis of intentionality (rational understanding), personal goals, and so on. Not “randomly”, “haphazardly”, “by chance”, etc. 5 What are free acts? • Libertarians have pursued two approaches to free will. – Agent causation libertarians (ACL) have said that the person (i.e. agent) is the only cause of their free actions. Free acts are self-caused. – Event causation libertarians (ECL) deny that causes always determine their effects. Thus free actions have prior external causes, but are self- determined.
    [Show full text]