ABSTRACT Author's Name Jack Glazbrook Title of Thesis Berkeleyts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ABSTRACT Author's Name Jack Glazbrook Title of Thesis Berkeleyts ABSTRACT Author's Name Jack Glazbrook Title of Thesis Berkeleyts Analysis of Science Department Philosophy Degree M.A. Summary The purpose of this dissertation is to examine Berkeley's philosophy of science in the context of his general philosophy (Part One) and to trace the influence of his analysis of science on later ~hought (Part Two). Part One begins by reviewing the influence of other think­ ers - Locke, Newton and r~lebranche in particular - after which his rejection of abstraction is taken up as a prelude to an examination of his metaphysics. The opening discus­ sion of Part Two concludes that Berkeley's philosophy of science is well integrated into his philosophic system. His two main critiques of Newtonian theory, the doctrine of motion and the calculus, are examined as part of his theory of scientific methodology and his concept of nature. The influence of Berkeley's analysis of science is pre­ sented less in its direct impact on individual thinkers than as a contribution to the general intellectual climate of later scientific thought. Short Title BERKELEY'S ANALYSIS OF SCIENCE BERKELEY'S ANALYSIS OF SCIENCE by Jack Glazbrook, B.A. A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of ~~ster of Arts. Department of Philosophy, McGill University, ...... r1ontreal • March, 1970 , (e) Jack G1azbrook 1970 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface i Part One. Berkeley's Philosophy in General Chapter 1. The Context of His Philosophy l Chapter 2. His Rejection of Abstraction 12 Chapter 3. On Physical Objects 22 Chapter 4. On Spirits 33 Part Two. Berkeley's Philosophy of Science Chapter 5 • The Relation of His Philosophy of 45 Science to His Philosophy in General Chapter 6. His Critique of Absolute Space, 56 Time and r1otion Chapter 7. His Critique of IvIathematics 73 Chapter 8. Scientific r1ethodology 83 Chapter 9. The Influence of His Analysis of 92 Science Bibliography i PREFACE The purpose of this dissertation is to examine Berkeley's philosophy of science in the context of his general philosophie position and to trace the influence of his analysis of science on later thought. Part One provides an account of his philosophy in gen­ eral and Part Two offers a detailed analysis of his philosophy of science. Time has been kind to Berkeley. The origi­ nality of his thought and the freshness of his style are revealed in his works as much today as when they were written over two centuries ago. Nor has the large volume of commentary dimmed his light. On the contrary, l have found even those interpretations with which l take exception to be valuable and stimulating. Without ignoring Locke, l have presented Berkeley in terms of a Newton-Malebranche axis: from Newton, the new science, from Malebranche, a divine inspiration. This cornes out in his life, guided by a sense of divine purpose, but influenced by a feeling ii of concern for his fellow man. It is reflected in his philosophy with its respect for science in its study of God's world for the benefit of mankind. Berkeley appears as a very human person, who must, incidental­ ly, have been deeply wounded by the attacks of his contemporaries and especially by their reluctance to even try to understand him. An account of Berkeleian philosophy can con­ veniently begin with his critique of abstraction, from which there are many strands leading in particular to his philosophy of science. His metaphysical system is divided, as iS customary, between his treatments of physical objècts (~ is percipi) and spirits (~ is percipere). Professor Bracken's "intentional tie" thesis has proven helpful here as it permits an expla­ nation of Berkeley's linguistic approach to metaphy-, sical problems that does not make him a phenomenalist. Bridging the gap between the general philo­ sophy and the philosophy of science at the beginning of Part Two poses little difficulty since Berkeley himself integrated his analysis of science well into his whole system despite, and even perhaps because of, his careful separation of science from metaphysics. 1 iii Further, there is no need to complicate the matter by talk of development in his writings because Berkeley reached his conclusions early in scientific theory and stuck with them. Central to Berkeley's analysis of science is his criticism of Newtonian physics. In retrospect, we can recognize Newton and Berkeley as the two great protagonists in scientific theory in the early eigh­ teenth century. Protagonists they were, but not an­ tagonists. B8rkeley, a more enthusiastic supporter of the new science in its results and even in its theory than could be justified today, criticized Newtonian physics in order to make its foundations philosophically impeccable. In kinetic theory, he accepted the value of Newton's laws of motion, but rejected the notions of absolute space, time and motion as illegitimate and unnecessary. His critical arguments are now substan­ tially accepted, and new positive doctrines have been developed to preserve the first and second laws of motion - the status of the third law is more debat­ able - in the more restricted context made necessary by the introduction of relativity theory. His criti- iv cism of the notion of the infinitesimal in calculus is generally agreed to be correct as far as the New­ tonian or Leibnizian formulations are concerned. How­ ever, subsequent mathematical theory has found an answer to Berkeley in a revised formulation in terms of a theory of limits that preserves the value of the calculus as a method. Berkeley's scientific methodology clearly represents an early reaction to the essentialist view of science. To what extent he contributed to the views of science which replaced essentialism is more questionable. Certainly, he anticipated Mach in the rejection of essences and of infinitesimals, but it does not follow from this that Berkeley anti­ cipated ~~chean instrumentalism, positivism or phe­ nomenalism. Further, when recent research has raised question on the influence of even the "crucial" Michelson-Morley experiment on Einstein, any claim that Berkeley through Mach influenced Einstein should be subjected to very careful re- . examination. The valuable contribution of Berkeley's analysis of science seems to me to be best regarded as an influence on the general intellectual climate PART ONE BERKELEY'S PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL 1 l Chapter 1. The Context of His Philosophy. In this outline of Berkeley's philosophy in general as a prelude to an examination of his analysis of science, it will be useful to examine his general philosophie position in its contexte To do this, we will consider in order: (1) the influence of other thinkers on his philosophy (2) the connection between his life and his philosophy (3) the response of his contemporaries to his philosophie proposals. During his years at Trinit y College, Dublin, Berkeley became well read in philosophie works in Latin, Greek, French and Hebrew, and became especially familiar with Plato's Dialogues, Malebranche's Recherche de la Vérité (1674-5) and Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690). He had also studied the Newtonian science and the mathematical calculus which dominated the scientific thought of the early eighteenth century;l that Berkeley gained a thorough gasp of these disciplines will become apparent when we turn in Part Two to his analysis of science. His attitude to earlier thinkers is best summarized by two remarks recorded in his early notebooks, written in 1707 and 1708 and not then intended lG.J. Warnock, Berk\eley ("Pelican Books"; Harmondsworth, 1953), p. 15. 2 for publication, but published first in 1871 by Professor A.C. Fraser under the title Commonplace Book of Occasional Meta­ physical Thoughts and in revised forro in 1948 by Professors A.A. Luce and T.E. Jessop as the fhilosophical Commentaries: Entry 266: Mem : that l was distrustful at 8 years old and Consequently by nature dis­ posed for these new Doctrines. Entry 682: l must acknowledge my self behold­ ing to the Philosophers have gone before me. They have given good rules tho perhaps they do not always observe them. Similitude of Adventurers who tho they them selves attained not the desir'd Port, they by their wrecks have made known the Rocks & sands, whereby the Passage of aftercomers is made more secure & easy. Pref: or 1ntrod: 2 This combination of respect mixed with criticism is most apparent in Berkeley's response to Locke, who is the sub­ ject of over seventy of the ' entries in the Philosophical Com­ mentaries, most of them sharply critical. Locke's influence on Berkeley has been so frequently recorded by commentators that Professor Frederick J.E. Woodbridge claims it to be exaggerated,3 and Professors G.J. Whitrow and Jessop insist 2George Berkeley, The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A.A. Lüëë and T.E: Jessop (London, 1948 ), 1-,-33, 83. (All references to Berkeley's works are to this edition. Subsequent footnotes refer to Works and indicate the shortened title and Berkeley's section numbers, if any). 3Frederick J.E. Woodbridge, "Berkeley's Realism," in Studies in the History of 1deas, ed. Department of Philosophy of Columbia University (New York, 1918), 1, 188. 3 that Newton's influence was at least equal to Locke's.4 Despite sorne reservations - as to the nature of space, for exarnple 5 - Locke substantially accepted the Newtonian science and atternpted, with a good rneasure of success, to formulate a philosophy co~patible with that science. As a result, both the strengths and weaknesses of Newtonian science are reflect- ed in Lockean philosophy. While Berkeley acknowledged these strengths, he concentrated on tllose weaknesses which his contempories seemed ready to overlook, his attack being di­ rected against Newton when the views of scientists or rnathe­ mati cians were primarily in question and against Locke when the philosophers were the target.
Recommended publications
  • Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology
    Architectural Theory and Practice, and the Question of Phenomenology (The Contribution of Tadao Ando to the Phenomenological Discourse) Von der Fakultät Architektur, Bauingenieurwesen und Stadtplanung der Brandenburgischen Technischen Universität Cottbus zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktor-Ingenieurs genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Mohammadreza Shirazi aus Tabriz, Iran Gutachter: : Prof. Dr. Eduard Führ Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Karsten Harries Gutachter: Gastprofessor. Dr. Riklef Rambow Tag der Verteidigung: 02. Juni 2009 Acknowledgment My first words of gratitude go to my supervisor Prof. Führ for giving me direction and support. He fully supported me during my research, and created a welcoming and inspiring atmosphere in which I had the pleasure of writing this dissertation. I am indepted to his teachings and instructions in more ways than I can state here. I am particularly grateful to Prof. Karsten Harries. His texts taught me how to think on architecture deeply, how to challenge whatever is ‘taken for granted’ and ‘remain on the way, in search of home’. I am also grateful to other colleagues in L.S. Theorie der Architektur. I want to express my thanks to Dr. Riklef Rambow who considered my ideas and texts deeply and helped me with his advice at different stages. I am thankful for the comments and kind helps I received from Dr. Katharina Fleischmann. I also want to thank Prof. Hahn from TU Dresden and other PhD students who attended in Doktorandentag meetings and criticized my presentations. I would like to express my appreciation to the staff of Langen Foundation Museum for their kind helps during my visit of that complex, and to Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Second Philosophy of Time (1899–1913)
    Russell’s Second Philosophy of Time (1899–1913) Nikolay Milkov, Bielefeld, Germany 1. Introduction 3. The History of Russell’s Seconds Russell’s second philosophy of time (1899–1913), which Philosophy of Time will be the subject of this paper, is of special interest for Though idealistic, Russell’s philosophy was pluralistic from two reasons. (1) It was basic to his New Philosophy, later the very beginning. His motivation for accepting pluralism called the “philosophy of logical atomism”. In fact, this were two early beliefs of his: First, in order for thinking to philosophy didn’t initially emerge in the period of 1914– be possible at all, its object must be complex. Indeed, a 1919, as many interpreters (e.g. A. J. Ayer) suggest, but simple thing “is unthinkable, since every object of thought with the introduction of Russell’s second philosophy of time can only be thought by means of some complexity”. (1896, (and space). The importance of Russell’s second philos- 564) Secondly, this complexity can be achieved only when ophy of time for his early and middle philosophy can be referring to unique individuals (terms), which are different seen from the fact that it survived the dramatic changes in from any other individual. This was the kernel of Russell’s his philosophy of August–December 1900, and of July atomism.1 1905. There is of course no surprise about this point: it served as their fundament. (2) Russell’s second philos- Thus Russell’s The Foundations of Geometry ophy of time is a locus classicus of all so called B-theories (finished in October 1896) claimed that the objects of of time which define it in terms of the relations of before, cognition have to be complex: in order to know them, we after and simultaneous between events or moments.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absolute Theory of Time Is Intimately Connected With
    The Absolute and the Relational Theories of Space and •rime 1. ·rhe Absolute Theory of Space and Time ; The absolute theory of time is intimately connected with the absolute theory of space, which is to be found first, in 1 clear terms, in Newton's conception of space and time. In Newton • s theory space and time are real indepe~dent entities; each of them constitutes a continuum such that any one part of that continuum is indistinguishab~e from any such other part. The different parts of space and time are due to the things that occupy place and. the events. that happen at moments; they are not due to space apd time themselves. Both space and time are absolutely immutable and homogeneous. · The basic attributes of space and time follow 1 from their h01rogenei ty : "their irtde·pendence from physical contents, their uniformity, continuity and infinity. As 7 space is independent of rnatter, time is also independent in regard to the concrete c.'langes that take place in it. 'I'his has been explicitly formulated by Newton in the following sentences : 11 Absolute, true and mathematical >cime of itself and by its ·own nature flows uniformly, without regard to anything external. It is called duration. Relative, apparent and vu.lgax- time is sane sensible and external measure of absolute time (duration), estimated by the motions of bodies ••• , and is c~m~nly .ll.s.~d .i~stead of true time, 11 2 such as· an hour, a day, a month a week • According to this theory time flows irrespective of the events or changes occurring or not in it.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics at the International Con- Gress Of
    1901.] THE PARIS CONGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY. 157 MATHEMATICS AT THE INTERNATIONAL CON­ GRESS OF PHILOSOPHY, PARIS, 1900. THE first international congress of philosophy was held at Paris, August 1-5, 1900, under the presidency of M. E. BOUTROUX, professor at the Sorbonne. The proceedings of the third section, devoted to logic and history of the sciences, are of especial interest to mathematicians. The delibera­ tions of this section were directed by Professor JULES TANNERY. In his inaugural address as president of the section, after the usual felicitations and customary acknowl­ edgments, Professor Tannery emphasized the union be­ tween science and philosophy, a union which, he said, is better designated by the term unity. Any separation be­ tween scientists and philosophers is only apparent. The savants of the present century have set most important re­ sults before philosophers for speculation. Count the power­ ful geniuses who from the beginning of the century to its end have attacked the notion of space ; measure how much the critique of this notion has done for the problem of knowledge. "What illumination has been thrown upon the notion of function and, ascending farther, on the notion of number, by the revision of the principles of analysis ! Will not the theory of ensembles show somewhat how we ought to think of infinity? Will not mathematical logic furnish us a sure instrument for the discernment and transformation of the data of intuition ? Will not the al­ gebra of logic enable us to penetrate deeper into the mech­ anism of deduction? Every hope seems legitimate, after what has been accomplished in the foundations of geometry.
    [Show full text]
  • On Models, Objects, Fantasy Christina Vagt & Robert M
    This is an unpublished working paper, please do not circulate it further. We appreciate written feedback to [email protected] or [email protected] ​ ​ ​ On Models, Objects, Fantasy Christina Vagt & Robert M. T. Groome This article presumes that a media theoretical discourse on modeling can be effectively stated in structural and functional terms that are shared to a certain extent by mathematics and science. This leads to constructions in non-classical logic, set theory, and topology that are necessary to understand questions that are usually excluded from scientific discourses because they challenge the dominant paradigms of causality, representation, or identity. We are primarily interested in writing practices or media operations that demonstrate different aspects of model-object relations, and not in models as immaterial, purely formal, non-temporal, or non-spatial entities or ideas. The insight that practices such as writing, diagramming, counting, imaging, etc. predate any specific philosophical or scientific concept or theory of text, image, and number is not new: it belongs to the premises of so-called ‘German media theory’ that emerged among European philosophers, historians, and literary scholars in the late 1980s around questions of textuality, structuralism, technology, knowledge, and science.1 Even though a few scholars in this field have successfully engaged with the history and philosophy of science, mathematics, logic, or engineering to a degree that one could say the subject of media theory is science, mathematics, and technology, the discourse over all has so far failed to formulate any consistent methods that would enable an actual dialogue with mathematics, logic, or science beyond the individual scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strong Theory of Relative Identity
    The Strong Theory of Relative Identity Daniel Molto PhD University of York Philosophy September 2014 2 0.1 Abstract This dissertation considers a theory of numerical identity, first presented by P.T. Geach (1962). I label this theory `the strong theory of relative identity'. I suggest that the strong theory of relative identity involves three theses, which I name `GT', `RI', and `SRI'. I argue that each of these theses is logically independent. I consider arguments for and against each of these theses in turn. I conclude that none of the arguments for GT, RI, or SRI are conclusive. However, I also argue that the arguments against GT, RI and SRI are unsuccessful. I argue, further, that the strong theory of relative identity, and GT in particular, is incompatible with classical semantics and classical first-order logic with identity. I consider alternative non-classical logical systems and semantics which might be compatible with the strong theory of relative identity. Finally, I consider the philosophical applications of the strong theory of relative identity. I focus on one area, specifically philosophical theology, and I argue, with respect to the logical problem of the Trinity, that either GT is true or orthodoxy is false. 3 CONTENTS 0.1 Abstract . 3 0.2 Acknowledgements . 5 0.3 Declaration . 6 0.4 Introduction . 7 0.4.1 Chapter 1: The Strong Theory of Relative Identity . 8 0.4.2 Chapter 2: Geach's Argument Against Absolute Identity 11 0.4.3 Chapter 3: RI . 12 0.4.4 Chapter 4: SRI . 12 0.4.5 Chapter 5: Objections to Relative Identity .
    [Show full text]
  • "Scientific Rationality and Methodological Change
    "Scientific Rationality and Methodological Change: A Critical Examination of Some Recent Attempts to Naturalize Methodology11 By Kolapo Ogunniyi Abimbola (London School of Economics and Political Science) Submitted in August 1993 to the University of London for the Degree of Ph.D in Philosophy of Science UMI Number: U055801 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U055801 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 Abstract Following the work of Popper and especially of Kuhn in the 1960s, the attention of philosophers of science has been very much concentrated onchange in science. Popper’s picture was of constant change ("revolution in permanence") at the level of scientific theories, but constant change in accordance with fixed methodological standards of evaluation. Drawing on Kuhn’s work, however, many recent philosophers of science have held that the phenomenon of scientific change is much more radical and far-reaching than anything allowed by Popper: specifically, that there have been major changes in methodological standards during the history of science alongside changes in accepted fundamental theory.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Roots of Russell's Naturalism and Behaviorism
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 10 2008 The Mathematical Roots Of Russell’s Naturalism And Behaviorism James Levine Trinity College Dublin, IRE Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Levine, James (2008) "The Mathematical Roots Of Russell’s Naturalism And Behaviorism," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/ biyclc.v4i0.134 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. From Moore to Peano to Watson 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of with meaning, which in earlier days I had completely ignored” (1968, Cognition, Logic and Communication 194) when “I had regarded language as ‘transparent’ and had never examined what makes its relation to the non–linguistic world” (1959, August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy 145). pages 1-126 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.134 Until relatively recently (in particular, before the 1990’s with the publication of Hylton (1990) and Griffin (1991)), the main focus of interest
    [Show full text]
  • Information to Users
    INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is included in reduced form at the back of the book. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy. Higher quality 6" x 9" black and white photographic prints are available for any photographs or illustrations appearing in this copy for an additional charge. Contact UMI directly to order. University Microfilms International A Bell & Howell Information Company 30 0 North Z eeb Road. Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 USA 313/761-4700 800/521-0600 Order Number 9427800 Newton’s “De gravitatione” argument: Cartesian relationalist dynamics and the structure of space and time Slowik, Edward Steven, Ph.D.
    [Show full text]
  • BPY-012 Philosophy of Science and Cosmology
    BLOCK 1 Today science is considered as one of the best sources of reliable knowledge, especially for providing the knowledge of the reality around us. But today’s science and philosophy has its basis in the mythology of the past. The ancient people were in search of an explanation of the nature that was externally obvious to them, yet the origin, nature and structure was too transcendent to their limited minds. This is the reason they took refuge in the myths. Although these myths were not so clear and satisfactory, these gave them the momentum to go ahead and search for more convincing answers. This is the story of the development and growth of science. Today’s science was the myth of the past. Both strive to explain the reality; both have the same goal; but the methods followed are different. Myths when elaborated and rationalized become philosophy. Also philosophy becomes a reflection on the data furnished by science which will help in furthering human knowledge. Philosophy and science are the two sides of the same coin i.e. knowledge. Even this discipline of knowledge has its foundation laid down long ago by the Greek thinkers, by 6th century BC. This block consists of four units introducing us to the philosophy of science and the Greek roots from which it developed. Unit 1 will introduce the course that we will study: Introduction to Philosophy of Science and Cosmology. It gives the various stages of how the so called contemporary science has developed. Beginning with an analysis of myths, it will show the relationship that exists between philosophy and science, philosophical cosmology and what we understand by philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • General Covariance and the Foundations of General Relativity: Eight Decades of Dispute
    Rep. bog. Phys. 56 (1993) 791458. Printed in the UK General covariance and the foundations of general relativity: eight decades of dispute John D Norton Department of History and Philosophy of Science, Univeniry of Pinsburgh. Pinsburgh. PA 15260, USA Abstract Einstein offered the principle of general covariance as the fundamental physical principle of his general theory of relativity and as responsible for extending the principle of relativity to accelerated motion. This view was disputed almost immediately with the counter-claim that the principle was no relativity principle and was physically vacuous. The disagreement persists today. This article reviews the development of Einstein’s thought on general covariance, its relation to the foundations of general relativity and the evolution of the continuing debate over his viewpoint. This review was received in March 1993. 00344885/93M70791+68$30.00 63 1993 IOP Publishing Ltd 79 1 792 J D Norton Contents Page 1. Introduction 794 2. The background of special relativity 796 2.1. Lorentz covariance and the relativity of inertial motion 796 2.2. Minkowski’s introduction of geometrical methods 196 2.3. Covariance versus invariance in special relativity 797 3. Einstein’s development of general relativity 797 3.1. The early years 1907-1912 principle of equivalence and the relativity of inertia 798 3.2. The ‘Entwuff theory 1912-1915 general covariance gained and lost 799 3.3. The hole argument: general covariance condemned 801 3.4. Einstein’s 1916 account of the foundations of general relativity: general covariance regained 802 3.5. The point-coincidence argument 804 3.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Absolute Reaction Rate Theory
    The Unity of Chemistry and Physics: Absolute Reaction Rate Theory Hinne Hettema Abstract: Henry Eyring’s absolute rate theory explains the size of chemical re- action rate constants in terms of thermodynamics, statistical mechanics, and quantum chemistry. In addition it uses a number of unique concepts such as the ‘transition state’. A key feature of the theory is that the explanation it pro- vides relies on the comparison of reaction rate constant expressions derived from these individual theories. In this paper, the example is used to develop a naturalized notion of reduction and the unity of science. This characterization provides the necessary clues to the sort of inter-theoretic linkages that are pre- sent in the theory of reaction rates. The overall theory is then further charac- terized as a theory network, establishing connections between non-reductive notions of inter-theory connections. This characterization also sheds new light on the unity of science. Keywords: reduction of chemistry to physics, unity of science, chemical kinetics, absolute theory of reaction rates, explanation . Introduction The unity of chemistry and physics should be paradigmatic for the unity of science. With the advent of atomic theory, quantum theory, and statistical mechanics, the fields of chemistry and physics have become increasingly in- tertwined, perhaps even up to the point where, as Needham (2010) argues, it would be hard to imagine chemistry with the physics removed. Hence it is a valid question to ask how this unity of science is constituted in terms of the inter-relationship between theories. In the present paper, these inter-relations will be considered for theories of chemistry and physics, specifically focusing on Eyring’s theory of absolute reaction rates.
    [Show full text]