Honoré Fabri and the Concept of Impetus: a Bridge Between Conceptual Frameworks Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Honoré Fabri and the Concept of Impetus: a Bridge Between Conceptual Frameworks Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science HONORÉ FABRI AND THE CONCEPT OF IMPETUS: A BRIDGE BETWEEN CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORKS BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editors ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University JÜRGEN RENN, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science KOSTAS GAVROGLU, University of Athens Managing Editor LINDY DIVARCI, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Editorial Board THEODORE ARABATZIS, University of Athens ALISA BOKULICH, Boston University HEATHER E. DOUGLAS, University of Pittsburgh JEAN GAYON, Université Paris 1 THOMAS F. GLICK, Boston University HUBERT GOENNER, University of Goettingen JOHN HEILBRON, University of California, Berkeley DIANA KORMOS-BUCHWALD, California Institute of Technology CHRISTOPH LEHNER, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science PETER MCLAUGHLIN, Universität Heidelberg AGUSTÍ NIETO-GALAN, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona NUCCIO ORDINE, Universitá della Calabria ANA SIMÕES, Universidade de Lisboa JOHN J. STACHEL, Boston University SYLVAN S. SCHWEBER, Harvard University BAICHUN ZHANG, Chinese Academy of Science VOLUME 288 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/5710 HONORÉ FABRI AND THE CONCEPT OF IMPETUS: A BRIDGE BETWEEN CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORKS by MICHAEL ELAZAR Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, Germany 123 Michael Elazar Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Boltzmannstrasse 22 14195 Berlin Germany [email protected] ISSN 0068-0346 ISBN 978-94-007-1604-9 e-ISBN 978-94-007-1605-6 DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1605-6 Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York Library of Congress Control Number: 2011928368 © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Printed on acid-free paper Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com) Honoré Fabri: A Short Biography The Jesuit Honoré Fabri was born on 8 April 1608 at Le Grand Abergement, Ain, a small town in eastern France, about eighty kilometers north-east of Lyon.1 Fabri entered the Jesuit novitiate in Avignon in October 1626 and completed in 1630 his course on Scholastic philosophy (under Claude Boniel) in the Collège de la Trinité at Lyon (Fellmann 1971, p. 505). He spent the next two years teaching grammar at the Jesuit College at Roanne. In 1632 he was sent to Rome, to start his course in the- ology at the Collegio Romano, but after one year he was summoned back to Lyon, where he completed (in 1636) his theological training. Meanwhile, in 1635, he was ordained as a priest. Afterwards he was sent to the newly opened Jesuit college at Arles, where he taught logic (1636–1637) and natural philosophy (1637–1638). In Arles he lectured on the circulation of the blood, boasting thirty years later, in his Tractatus de homine (1666), that he had publicly taught it before the appearance of Harvey’s book (Lukens 1979, pp. 7–8). This vague declaration has been inter- preted – by contemporaries and historians alike – as a claim to priority over Harvey, though Fabri himself subsequently argued (as late as 1687) that “at no time did I ever say that the circulation of the blood had been first discovered by me”.2 In 1638–1639 Fabri served as a prefect at the Jesuit College in Aix-en-Provence. In 1640 Fabri was recalled to the Collège de la Trinité at Lyon, where he was promoted to professor of logic and mathematics, as well as to the office of dean. Until 1646 Fabri, “the first of many famous professors produced by the Collège de la Trinité” (Vregille 1906, p. 7), taught there logic, metaphysics, astronomy, math- ematics, and natural philosophy. In Fellmann’s words, “this period was the most brilliant and fruitful of his life; several books that he published later3 were developed from lectures delivered during this time” (Fellmann 1971, p. 505). It is there that 1Lukens 1979, p. 6. Lukens relies on documents contained in the Archivium Romanum Societatis Iesu (reproduced as plates I–III, immediately after page 5). Lukens acknowledges that other sources convey different dates or places for Fabri’s birth (for example, 1607 or Virieu-le-Grand, Dauphiné), but claims that he “cannot explain these discrepancies” (Lukens 1979, p. 6, n. 1). 2Lukens 1979, p. 9. Lukens suggests that Fabri “may have taken the 1639 Lyon edition of De motu cordis – or even the 1649 (first) edition of De circulatione sanguinis – as the first publication of Harvey’s idea” (Lukens 1979, p. 9). 3Including his important Physica (Fabri 1669–1671). v vi Honoré Fabri: A Short Biography Fabri and his students – including the future medical doctor Pierre Mousnier (who later edited Fabri’s lectures), the mathematician François de Raynaud, and the Jesuits Claude de Chales (philosopher and theologian), Jean Bertet (astronomer) and François de la Chaize (confessor to Louis XIV) – began their correspondence with figures like Pierre Gassendi, René Descartes, Huygens (Constantin and Christiaan) and Marine Mersenne. Fabri’s principal book on motion, Tractatus physicus de motu locali (Fabri 1646b), as well as his work on logic, Philosophiae tomus primus (Fabri 1646a), and his Metaphysica demonstrativa (Fabri 1648), were published in Lyon (Lukens 1979, p. 11). In 1646 Fabri was removed from his teaching office in the Collège de la Trinité, under circumstances which are not entirely clear, and sent to a bureaucratic post in Rome. In a letter dated 3 June 1647, the Minime Gabriel Thibaut informed Mersenne that Fabri was “at odds with the fathers of his order (il est traversé par les Pères de sa Compaignie), and it is believed that they did everything they could to make him leave, just as they did what they could to withhold the printing of his books”.4 Adrien Baillet, Descartes’ biographer, mentions Thibaut’s letter, and adds that Fabri’s activity in Rome, following his transfer, rehabilitated his position within his order.5 Neither Thibaut nor Baillet assert that it was specifically hold- ing Cartesian opinions which caused Fabri’s superiors to transfer him to Rome, and some historians believe that Fabri became suspected of supporting Descartes only long after the latter died.6 However, most historians tend to agree that it was “Fabri’s aggressive taste for novelties” – whether Cartesian or not – that alarmed his conservative superiors in Lyon and brought about his removal from teaching.7 In the words of Mordechai Feingold, “the removal of audacious Jesuits from teaching philosophy, as stipulated in the founding documents of the society, became a popu- lar measure against those charged with introducing novel ideas into the classroom” (Feingold 2003, p. 31). It should be emphasized that on 15 February 1643 Fabri took the fourth vow, the special vow of particular obedience to the pope, taken only by select Jesuits (in addition to the three standard vows of poverty, chastity, and obe- dience),8 and thus became practically immuned from absolute expulsion from his order. “The complicated procedures required to expel a professed father”, explains Robert Bireley, S. J., “made dismissal at the initiative of superiors extremely rare”.9 4Tannery et al. 1945–1988, vol. XV, p. 245. 5Baillet 1691, vol. 2, p. 300. 6Lukens 1979, p. 15; Sortais 1929, pp. 48–49. 7Heilbron 1979, p. 113. See also Feingold 2003, p. 31. Some historians insist that it was specifically Cartesian ideas which led to Fabri’s expulsion from Lyon (Vregille 1906, p. 8; Fellmann 1971, p. 505). 8Lukens 1979, p. 10. 9Bireley 2003, p. 257, n. 90. Honoré Fabri: A Short Biography vii Fabri arrived in Rome on 12 September 1646. He became a member of the Minor Vatican Penitentiary, a community of Jesuits responsible for hearing confessions in foreign languages, and was commissioned to hear confessions in French. In 1677 he was appointed rector of the Penitentiary, but three years later he was forced to retire after a quarrel with the Grand Penitentiary.10 While serving in the Penitentiary, Fabri continued to pursue his scientific interests. Through his acquaintance with the math- ematician Michelangelo Ricci he became (in 1660) a corresponding member of the short-lived Accademia del Cimento (1657–1667), founded by Prince Leopold de’ Medici (Fellmann 1971, p. 506). Fabri produced several important books on current mathematical topics,11 crusaded in favor of Jesuit’s bark (quinine) as a remedy for fever,12 and embarked on a bitter (and hopeless) controversy against Huygens’s dis- covery of Saturn’s rings.13 Upon his dismissal from the Penitentiary, Fabri retired to the Gesu (the Jesuit headquarters in Rome), and was appointed Latin historian of the Society. He died in Rome on 8 March 1688 (Lukens 1979, pp. 30–31). While in Rome, Fabri flourished – writing all in all more than thirty books, many of them on scientific topics – but nevertheless managed to involve himself in some unpleasant situations. In 1672 he spent almost two months in prison, following the publication of his Apologeticus doctrinae moralis eiusdem Societatis (1670), which still appears in the last edition of the Index librorum prohibitorum (published in 1948). It is not clear whether it was its vigorous attack on the Jansenists, while defending probabilism,14 which brought about Fabri’s imprisonment,15 or whether it was an issue of authority which caused this unhappy incident;16 but it should be emphasized that the reason which is given in some biographical accounts for this affair17 – namely, Fabri’s allegedly soft position towards Copernicanism – is without a doubt incorrect. Fabri claimed that if a proof were ever to be found for the motion of the earth, then the Holy Scriptures should be reinterpreted accordingly, thus only repeating Cardinal Bellarmine’s view (from 1616), “which seemed to be relatively common in Jesuit circles” (Finocchiaro 2005, p.
Recommended publications
  • Re-Construction and Definition of New Branches & Hierarchy of Sciences
    Philosophy Study, July 2016, Vol. 6, No. 7, 377-416 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2016.07.001 D DAVID PUBLISHING New Perspective for the Philosophy of Science: Re-Construction and Definition of New Branches & Hierarchy of Sciences Refet Ramiz Near East University In this work, author evaluated past theories and perspectives behind the definitions of science and/or branches of science. Also some of the philosophers of science and their specific philosophical interests were expressed. Author considered some type of interactions between some disciplines to determine, to solve the philosophical/scientific problems and to define the possible solutions. The purposes of this article are: (i) to define new synthesis method, (ii) to define new perspective for the philosophy of science, (iii) to define relation between new philosophy perspective and philosophy of science, (iv) to define and organize name, number, relations, and correct structure between special science branches and philosophy of science, (v) to define necessary and sufficient number of branches for philosophy of science, (vi) to define and express the importance and place of new philosophy of science perspective in the new system, (vii) to extend the definition/limits of philosophy of science, (viii) to re-define meanings of some philosophical/scientific theories, (ix) to define systematic solution for the conflicts, problems, confusions about philosophy of science, sciences and branches of science, (x) to define new branches of science, (xi) to re-construct branches and hierarchy of science, (xii) to define new theories about science and branches of science. Author considered R-Synthesis as a method for the evaluation of the philosophy, philosophy of science, sciences and branches of science.
    [Show full text]
  • A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Fourth Edition
    A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Fourth edition John Losee OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science This page intentionally left blank A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science Fourth edition John Losee 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Athens Auckland Bangkok Bogotá Buenos Aires Calcutta Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Florence Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Paris São Paulo Shanghai Singapore Taipei Tokyo Toronto Warsaw with associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © John Losee , The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organizations. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available ISBN ––– Typeset in Adobe Minion by RefineCatch Limited, Bungay, Suffolk Printed in Great Britain by Biddles Ltd., Guildford and King’s Lynn Preface This book is a historical sketch of the development of views about scientific method.
    [Show full text]
  • Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum
    LOST IN THE LABYRINTH: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ AND THE CONTINUUM LOST IN THE LABYRINTH: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ AND THE CONTINUUM By PATRICK RIESTERER, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies In Partial Fulfillment ofthe Requirements For the Degree Master ofArts McMaster University © Copyright by Patrick Riesterer, August 2006 MASTER OF ARTS (2006) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum AUTHOR: Patrick Riesterer, B.A. (Trinity Western University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Richard Arthur NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 110 ii Abstract In this thesis, I address the extent ofSpinoza's influence on the development of Leibniz's response to the continuum problem, with particular emphasis on his relational philosophy oftime and space. I expend the first chapter carefully reconstructing Spinoza's position on infinity and time. We see that Spinoza developed a threefold definition ofinfinity to explain the difference between active substance and its passive modes. Spinoza advances a syncategorematic interpretation ofinfinity, and founds a causal theory oftime directly on this conception ofinfinity. In the second chapter, I examine the changes Leibniz's understanding ofthe continuum problem underwent during 1676 and immediately thereafter. During this period, Leibniz's interacted extensively with Spinoza's ideas. We see that several fundamental features ofLeibniz's philosophy oftime take shape at this time. Leibniz adopts a Spinozistic definition ofdivine eternity and immensity, he reevaluates several analogies in an attempt to understand how the attributes ofa substance interrelate, and he develops the notion ofthe law of the series that will become an essential feature ofmonadic appetition. Leibniz synthesizes several ofthese discoveries into a first philosophy ofmotion.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright © 2008 by Lydia R
    ABSTRACT Analogy, Causation, and Beauty in the Works of Lucy Hutchinson Evan Jay Getz, Ph.D. Dissertation Chairperson: Phillip J. Donnelly, Ph.D. Lucy Hutchinson's translation of the ancient epic De Rerum Natura is remarkable in light of her firm commitments to Calvinist theology and the doctrine of Providence. David Norbrook and Jonathan Goldberg offer strikingly different explanations for the translation exercise. For instance, Norbrook argues that Hutchinson translates Lucretius in order that she might learn from the false images in Lucretius and make better ones in such works as Order and Disorder (Norbrook, “Margaret” 191). In contrast, Goldberg argues for compatibility between Lucretian atomism and Hutchinson‟s Christianity, seeing no contradiction or tension (Goldberg 286). I argue that neither critic accounts for the aesthetics of beauty in Hutchinson's poetry; both critics instead attribute an aesthetics of the sublime to Hutchinson. In making this argument, I show that Hutchinson's theory of causation has much in common with Reformed Scholasticism, whereby she is able to restore a metaphysics of formal and final cause. Hutchinson also revives the doctrine of the analogy of being, or analogia entis, in order to show that the formal cause of creation is visible as God's glory. After a discussion of her metaphysics and ontology, I then show that Hutchinson's poetry reflects a theological aesthetics of beauty and not the aesthetics of the sublime. In the fourth chapter, I compare the typological accounts of Abraham found in Thomas Hobbes' Leviathan and Hutchinson's Order and Disorder with a view to virtue as the proper basis of authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives Edited by Mary Helen Mcmurran and Alison Conway MIND, BODY, MOTION, MATTER
    Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives edited by Mary Helen McMurran and Alison Conway MIND, BODY, MOTION, MATTER Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives EDITED BY MARY HELEN MCMURRAN AND ALISON CONWAY UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO PRESS Toronto Buffalo London © University of Toronto Press 2016 Toronto Buffalo London www.utppublishing.com Printed in the U.S.A. ISBN 978-1-4426-5011-4 (cloth) Printed on acid-free, 100% post-consumer recycled paper with vegetable-based inks. ___________________________________________________________________ Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication Mind, body, motion, matter : eighteenth-century British and French literary perspectives / edited by Mary Helen McMurran and Alison Conway. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-4426-5011-4 (cloth) 1. English literature – 18th century – History and criticism. 2. French literature – 18th century – History and criticism. 3. Philosophy in literature. 4. Materialism in literature. 5. Vitalism in literature. 6. Aesthetics in literature. I. Conway, Alison Margaret, editor II. McMurran, Mary Helen, 1962–, author, editor PR448.P5M55 2016 820.9'384 C2015-908168-8 ___________________________________________________________________ CC-BY-NC-ND This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution Non-commercial No Derivative License. For permission to publish commercial versions please
    [Show full text]
  • Materialism and “The Soft Substance of the Brain”: the Case of Diderot Charles T. Wolfe Department of Philosophy and Moral S
    Materialism and “the soft substance of the brain”: the case of Diderot Charles T. Wolfe Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences Sarton Centre for History of Science Ghent University Longer draft (2015) of paper forthcoming in British Journal of History of Philosophy (a number of additional citations appear in published version) Abstract Materialism is the view that everything that is real, is material or is the product of material processes. It tends to take either a ‘cosmological’ form, as a claim about the ultimate nature of the world, or a more specific ‘psychological’ form, detailing how mental processes are brain processes. I focus on the second, psychological or cerebral form of materialism. In the mid-to-late eighteenth century, the French materialist philosopher Denis Diderot (1713-1784) was one of the first to notice that any self-respecting materialist had to address the question of the status and functional role of the brain, and its relation to our mental, affective, intellectual life. After this the topic grew stale, with knee-jerk reiterations of ‘psychophysical identity’ in the nineteenth-century, and equally rigid assertions of anti-materialism. In 1960s philosophy of mind, brain-mind materialism reemerged as ‘identity theory’, focusing on the identity between mental processes and cerebral processes. In contrast, Diderot’s cerebral materialism allows for a more culturally sedimented sense of the brain, which he describes in his late Elements of Physiology as a “book – except it is a book which reads itself”. Diderot thus provides a lesson for materialism as it reflects on the status of the brain, science and culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Cinema in the Digital Age: a Rebuttal to Lev Manovich ! ! ! ! ! ! ! a Senior Project
    ! ! ! ! Cinema in the Digital Age: A Rebuttal to Lev Manovich ! ! ! ! ! ! ! A Senior Project presented to the Faculty of the Philosophy Department California Polytechnic State University, San Luis Obispo ! ! ! ! ! In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Bachelor of Arts ! ! by! Barbara! Cail December, 2013! ! ! © 2013 Barbara Cail ! Cail "1 I. Introduction! ! Philosophy of film has been in upheaval since the early days of digital post- production effects and manipulation in the 1980s. Although shot and released on celluloid, many feature films of the 1990s were transferred to video in a process known as telecine. Telecine effectively turned the film image into an analog video image which could then be digitized and ingested into a computer for post-production editing and visual effects. Concurrent rapid innovations in non-linear editing software and hardware dramatically accelerated the post-production editing process, while decreasing costs and increasing profits for film studios. End-to-end digital filmmaking gained industry credibility when George Lucas embraced digital for his 1999 release of Star Wars Episode I: The Phantom Menace. The film was partially recorded on digital cameras, edited and composited on computers and distributed digitally to select movie theaters.1 ! ! As technologies continued to mature and cinema became increasingly digital, film philosophy entered a crisis. Classical film theories that depend upon the acknowledged indexical relationship of an analog photo to its referent in reality were unable to accommodate the move to digital. This quandary has renewed interest in these classical theories, returning them to the forefront of film philosophy.! ! Lev Manovich, a preeminent digital media philosopher, has posited that cinema has been fundamentally changed by cinema’s digital revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • A Discussion on Berkeley's Account of Time a Thesis Presented to The
    A Discussion on Berkeley’s Account of Time A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Nicholas L. Shooner August 2020 © 2020 Nicholas L. Shooner. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled A Discussion on Berkeley’s Account of Time by NICHOLAS L. SHOONER has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by James M. Petrik Associate Professor of Philosophy Florenz Plassmann Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 Abstract SHOONER, NICHOLAS L., M.A., August 2020, Philosophy A Discussion on Berkeley’s Account of Time Director of Thesis: James M. Petrik We examine what George Berkeley says about the nature of time and weigh two competing interpretations of his theory to determine which is closer to his intended meaning. Berkeley presents a theory of time that is idealist (time consists in ideas and their motions), subjectivist (time is contained within subjects), and relationalist (time is not an absolute entity, but is a description of the relations between events). While these features of Berkeley’s theory are not in dispute, there is a debate concerning whether he accepts an inter-subjective, universal ordering of events which grounds the temporal experiences of all human subjects. H. Scott Hestevold argues that, for Berkeley, such an order is to be found in the all-encompassing subject, God, whereas Darren Hynes argues that no such ordering is needed in Berkeley’s system. We evaluate these interpretations in light of Berkeley’s other metaphysical commitments and conclude that Hestevold’s interpretation is superior since it is better able to accommodate Berkeley’s commitment to the meaningfulness of temporal language in ordinary discourse and his commitment to the possibility and success of the natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • The Scientific Worldview Also by Glenn Borchardt
    The Scientific Worldview Also by Glenn Borchardt The Ten Assumptions of Science The Scientific Worldview Beyond Newton and Einstein Glenn Borchardt, Ph.D., Director, Progessive Science Institute iUniverse, Inc. New York Lincoln Shanghai The Scientific Worldview Beyond Newton and Einstein Copyright © 2007 by Glenn Borchardt All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced by any means, graphic, electronic, or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, taping or by any information storage retrieval system without the written permission of the publisher except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. iUniverse books may be ordered through booksellers or by contacting: iUniverse 2021 Pine Lake Road, Suite 100 Lincoln, NE 68512 www.iuniverse.com 1-800-Authors (1-800-288-4677) ISBN-13: 978-0-595-39245-2 (pbk) ISBN-13: 978-0-595-83773-1 (cloth) ISBN-13: 978-0-595-83637-6 (ebk) ISBN-10: 0-595-39245-8 (pbk) ISBN-10: 0-595-83773-5 (cloth) ISBN-10: 0-595-83637-2 (ebk) Printed in the United States of America Grateful acknowledgment is made to the following for permission to reprint pre- viously published material: Allen & Unwin Inc.: Excerpts from Where is Science Going? by Max Planck. Reprinted by permission of the publisher, Allen & Unwin Inc. Progress Publishers: Excerpts from Dialectics of Nature by Frederick Engels.. Reprinted by permission of the publisher, Progress Publishers. Philosophical Library Publishers: Excerpts from Dictionary of Philosophy edited by D. D. Runes. Copyright ©1960 by Philosophical Library Publishers. Reprinted by permission of the publisher, Philosophical Library Publishers.
    [Show full text]
  • Returning to Lucretius My Talk Is Divided up Into Two Parts
    Returning to Lucretius My talk is divided up into two parts: the first part tries explain about why I think we should return to Lucretius and where I am coming from in my own approach; the second part poses three heterodox “counter-theses” about Lucretius 1) that he was not an atomist, 2) that he did not believe in a spontaneous swerve in a rain of atoms through the void, 3) and that, for Lucretius, there is no ethical “peace of mind” or ataraxia, as Epicurus called it. Why Return to Luc retius? I think a new Lucretius is coming into view today. Every period in Western history since Lucretius has returned to him like bees returning to their flower fields in search of nourishment. Each time, though, our return is different—like the expanding arc of a spiral. We bring new questions, find new answers, and make Lucretius speak to us again as if for the first time. We make Lucretius’ epic poem De Rerum Natura into the mellifluous honey of a liquid antiquity that always has coursed through the veins of modern history like a spring of fresh meaning and inspiration.i We thus return to Lucretius today not as though he were an unchanging figure carved in stone but as if he were a rush of new life at the cutting edge of the 21st century. We stand in front of Lucretius’ breathtaking and revolutionary poem not as passive students of unchanging relics in a museum but as active participants in a history of our present. Today, we are asking Lucretius again to tell us something about nature.ii I recently returned to Lucretius in 2014, when I taught Book II of De Rerum Natura for a class on what I called “the philosophy of movement.” I added Lucretius to the syllabus because he was an overlooked figure in the history of philosophy who wrote about motion.
    [Show full text]
  • J. B. S. Haldane and the Thomistic Argument from Motion for the Existence of God
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1941 J. B. S. Haldane and the Thomistic Argument from Motion For the Existence of God Cletus F. Hartmann Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Hartmann, Cletus F., "J. B. S. Haldane and the Thomistic Argument from Motion For the Existence of God" (1941). Master's Theses. 203. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/203 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1941 Cletus F. Hartmann J.B.S.Haldane and the Thomistic Argument from Motion for the Existence of God by Cletus F. Hartmann, S.J., A.B. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master ·of Arts in Loyola University Chicago, Ill. June, 1941 • • • • • l'amor che muove il Sole e l'altre stella. (Par. XXXIII, 145) ~ Auctoris Cletus Francis Hartmann, S.J., A.B., was born at Belle­ vue, Ky., August 22, 1912. He received his elementary train­ ing at St. Anthony's School, Madisonville, Cincinnati, o., 1918-1919; at St. Joseph's School, Toledo, o., 1919; at St. Michael's School, Toledo, o., 1919-1921; and at St. Charles' School, Toledo, o., 1921-1926.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Philosophy
    Natural philosophy Natural philosophy or philosophy of nature (from Latin philosophia naturalis) was the philosophical study of nature and the physical universe that was dominant before the development of modern science. It is considered to be the precursor of natural science. From the ancient world, starting with Aristotle, to the 19th century, the term "natural philosophy" was the common term used to describe the practice of studying nature. It was in the 19th century that the A celestial map from the 17th century, by the concept of "science" received its modern shape with Dutch cartographer Frederik de Wit new titles emerging such as "biology" and "biologist", "physics" and "physicist" among other technical fields and titles; institutions and communities were founded, and unprecedented applications to and interactions with other aspects of society and culture occurred.[1] Isaac Newton's book Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687 ), whose title translates to "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", reflects the then-current use of the words "natural philosophy", akin to "systematic study of nature". Even in the 19th century, a treatise by Lord Kelvin and Peter Guthrie Tait, which helped define much of modern physics, was titled Treatise on Natural Philosophy (1867 ). In the German tradition, Naturphilosophie (philosophy of nature) persisted into the 18th and 19th century as an attempt to achieve a speculative unity of nature and spirit. Some of the greatest names in German philosophy are associated with this movement, including Goethe, Hegel and Schelling. Naturphilosophie was associated with Romanticism and a view that regarded the natural world as a kind of giant organism, as opposed to the philosophical approach of figures such as John Locke and Isaac Newton who espoused a more mechanical view of the world, regarding it as being like a machine.
    [Show full text]