“Inner Light” of Mystics and Reason Leibniz’S Engagement with Jacob Böhme

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

“Inner Light” of Mystics and Reason Leibniz’S Engagement with Jacob Böhme Aries – Journal for the Study of Western Esotericism 18 (2018) 75–95 ARIES brill.com/arie Compatibility of the “Inner Light” of Mystics and Reason Leibniz’s Engagement with Jacob Böhme Susanne Edel Independent Researcher, Frankfurt am Main, Germany [email protected] Abstract Following his conviction that the truth, in principle, could only be one truth, Leib- niz wanted to prove that the “inner Light” of “true mysticism” was compatible with philosophers’ insights into reason. He placed his own doctrine of the individual sub- stances (“Monadology”) in the tradition of philosophia perennis, and in his opinion “true” mysticism belonged to this same tradition. Through representatives of the so- called Christian Kabbala, which made Jewish and Christian mysticism part of the same lineage, Leibniz became aware of the controversial writings of Böhme. He discussed the theosopher’s thought with his correspondence partner, the Böhme adherent André Morell, and after a critical investigation, Leibniz placed Böhme in a tradition of “true mysticism” which could be measured against reason. The author posits that the result of this engagement was Leibniz’s treatise “True Mystical Theology”, a translation of his doctrine of monads in mystical terminology. Keywords Jacob Böhme – Leibniz – Cambridge Platonists – Philosophia perennis – theosophy – Christian Kabbala An Ambivalent Reception History In the 1690s Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) composed a short text that historians of philosophy have cited up to the present day to argue that the great rationalist was attracted to mysticism, or even that he may have © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2018 | doi: 10.1163/15700593-01801003Downloaded from Brill.com09/29/2021 05:32:26AM via free access 76 edel been, deep within his heart, an unrecognized mystic. In the text, entitled Von der wahren Theologia Mystica—“On True Mystical Theology”—Leibniz clearly tries to translate his doctrine of monads into mystical language by using the term “inward Light” as a synonym for reason. For Leibniz, Böhme’s thought was ultimately in harmony with the tradition of “true mysticism”. Indeed, I will go a step further and argue that it is actually Böhme that Leibniz had in mind when he wrote his “True Mystical Theology”, thus hoping to rehabilitate Böhme’s (falsified) teachings.1 To make this clear, it will be necessary to take a closer look at the history of Leibniz’s engagement with Böhme, before turning to some observations about Leibniz’s text, “On True Mystical Theology”. First, however, a look ahead: The peculiar connection between theosophy and rationalism that this essay highlights drew the attention of a later-born commentator: ‘I found … amongst the most imaginative expressions some- thing reasonable, and thought, along with Malebranche and Leibniz, that one must correct this layman’s terminology. […] Finally I saw that Jacob Böhme’s dark words had to be measured against clear ones’, wrote Friedrich Christoph Oetinger (1702–1782) in a letter following his first reading of Böhme.2 A promi- nent theologian and representative of Lutheran Pietism in Swabia, Oetinger held Böhme to be a perspicacious interpreter of Christian doctrine in the wake of the Kabbalists. Oetinger saw no contradiction between his own adherence to Böhme’s teachings and his position as practicing theologian in the official state church. Oetinger’s conviction did not correspond to the prevailing opinion of his time regarding Böhme and theosophy. In 1745, Johann Heinrich Zedler’s Univer- sal-Lexicon condemned theosophers as a “sect”—with Böhme at their head and alongside him, Paracelsus, Weigel and Franciscus Mercurius van Helmont as the most prominent leaders.3 According to Zedler, theosophers not only disdained reason, but also secretly the Scriptures. Zedler thus concluded that their systems did not deserve to be considered “philosophy”. He asserts that they have not sought philosophy in the ‘use of the acquired, purified light of 1 I have discussed the relationship between Böhme and Leibniz in detail in Edel: Die individu- elle Substanz. An article on this subject in German is published in Edel, ‘Anmerkungen’. 2 ‘Ich fand […] unter den imaginativsten Ausdrücken etwas Räsonables und dachte, mit Male- branche und Leibniz müsste man dieses Laien Terminos korrigieren. […] Endlich sah ich, daß Jakob Böhmes dunkle Worte nach den deutlichen müssen gemessen werden’. See Ehmann (ed.), Oetingers Leben und Briefe, 36. Unless otherwise stated, all translations into English in this article were made by Lucinda Martin. 3 Zedler, ‘Theosophici’, 1116–1121. Aries – Journal for the Study of Western EsotericismDownloaded from 18Brill.com09/29/2021 (2018) 75–95 05:32:26AM via free access compatibility of the “inner light” of mystics and reason 77 reason, but instead in an innate supernatural Divine Light and its illumination’, and, in Zedler’s words, they: looked to the fantasies of their overheated imaginations and made these into the measure of reason and revelation, and also for this reason praised a secret Divine insight, granted only to certain illuminated persons, into the deepest mysteries of nature and have allowed themselves to dream of recognizing their extraordinary effects, and also because of this, they have made a lot of noise about magic, chemistry, astrology and similar sciences, which unlock the secret access to nature, und beyond this they have (unjustifiably) subsumed such secret and Divine philosophy under the ancient secret tradition of Wisdom and the name of Kabbalah.4 The lengthy lexicon article on the Theosophici reads like an indictment, in which the dangers inherent in the “theosophical system” are methodically enumerated, including the threat to the values and accomplishments of the Enlightenment, chief among them the role of reason. In Zedler’s opinion, theosophers execute their most serious attack on reason by misusing, or even claiming the same term for themselves: Indeed, they use the word reason themselves, but understand it not as the recognition of truth derived from natural principles or the power to discern these, but instead as the inward principle, which they seek as an outflowing and spark of Divine being in the human soul, which they oppose to that which is taken to be reason in normal understanding.5 4 Zedler, ‘Theosophici’, 1116. That is: nicht ‘in Gebrauch des anerschaffenen gereinigten Ver- nunft-Lichtes, als vielmehr in einem angeborenen übernatürlichen Göttlichen Lichte und dessen Erleuchtung’. Sie haben ‘die Vorstellungen ihrer erhitzten Einbildungs-Kraft dafür angesehen, und selbige zur Richtschnur von Vernunft und Offenbarung gesetzt, auch aus diesem Grunde sich einer geheimen Göttlichen, allein gewissen erleuchteten Personen mit- geteilten Einsicht der tiefsten Geheimnisse der Natur gerühmt, und deren außerordentliche Wirkungen erkannt zu haben sich träumen lassen, auch deswegen von der Magie, Chemie, Astrologie und dergleichen Wissenschaften, welche die geheimen Zugänge der Natur auf- schließen, viel Rühmens gemacht, und noch überdies (ungerechtfertigterweise) solche ge- heime und Göttliche Philosophie für die uralte geheime Tradition der Weisheit unter dem Namen der Cabbala ausgegeben’. 5 ‘Es bedienen sich zwar dieselben auch des Wortes Vernunft, sie verstehen aber dadurch nicht die Erkenntnis derWahrheit aus natürlichen Principiis, oder die Kraft dieselbige zu erkennen, sondern das inwendige Principium, das sie als einen Ausfluss und Funken des Göttlichen Aries – Journal for the Study of Western EsotericismDownloaded 18 from (2018) Brill.com09/29/2021 75–95 05:32:26AM via free access 78 edel Finally the article cites Gottfried Arnold’s “History of Church and Heresy” (Kirchen- und Ketzer-Historie, 1699–1700) to demonstrate that the “heretics” and “enthusiasts” that Arnold rehabilitates not only discredit reason and the sciences, but also, through their sectarian ways, “true Christianity” (das wahre Christentum) itself, since such sects ‘proceed with such pride at their virulence and contemptuously bully and scorn all that does not accord with them’.6 This discourse in the middle of the eighteenth century serves above all to underscore the ambivalence of reception history. Today historians often cite Arnold’s History of Church and Heresy as a harbinger of, and source of ideas for, the deist historical view of the Enlightenment, since the work made ‘openness and tolerance into determining principles of historiography’.7 Yet, at the end of 1699—a half century before the publication of Zedler’s Universal- Lexicon, Leibniz criticized the polemical basis and the methodological failings of Arnold’s work, although he admitted that he had not read it. In keeping with his irenic position, Leibniz emphasized the commonalities of the parties and the basis of a universal truth (philosophia perennis) in pursuing a union of the churches. He saw the sharp tones that Arnold had voiced against the official church as sectarian and not helpful for real moral improvement. In this context, Leibniz saw the “mildness” and “moderation” of Jacob Böh- me, Thomas á Kempis and Philipp Jacob Spener as exemplary and lauded the bonne intention of these authors.8 Leibniz was already familiar at this time with the controversial and divisive image of Böhme that circulated, but it appears that after some hesitation he arrived at a position of appreciation for him. At the same time, Leibniz sensed that a challenge to Böhme’s opponents would only increase their bias against the theosopher and provoke further prejudice. Wesens in der
Recommended publications
  • OPEN INDIVIDUALISM / NEOMONOPSYCHISM Iacopo Vettori
    1 OPEN INDIVIDUALISM / NEOMONOPSYCHISM Iacopo Vettori This paper summarizes my personal experience in discovering the Open Individualism. Because I found it by my own way, occasionally in the paper I refer to it as “my proposal”, but it would be intended as “the Open Individualism proposal”. By the way, because some issues represent only my personal opinion, and can be evaluated differently from other authors, I left the references as they were. This text can be considered a summary of what I wrote in my personal website dedicated to this subject, that I completed before knowing the book "I Am You" by Daniel Kolak and the other persons who collaborate in this research. The original content of the site was collected in a file in PDF format that can be downloaded at http://www.iacopovettori.it/laterzaipotesi/eng/TheThirdHypothesisSite.pdf I hope that my considerations may be useful when compared with those of people that had the same inspiration, or anyway share our persuasion, to reinforce or develop some aspects of our new vision of the life. INTRODUCTION The problem that has been the occasion to the considerations that I suggest, is expressed by the question "Why I do exist?" or rather, from its more disturbing version: "could I not exist?". As long as you continue to think about our lives in terms of individual minds or souls, you cannot find very compelling reasons that lead to a not elusive answer, that does not resort to subterfuges such as "there is a superior will that wanted me to exist" or the equivalent "I was the recipient
    [Show full text]
  • Monopsychism , Mysticism , Metaconsciousness
    MONOPSYCHISM, MYSTICISM, METACONSCIOUSNESS - aícuov- has a father; ahd by ground Plato means intelligence or the 'mixer' demiurge, who is the of the soul) and the Republic (by 'father' Plato means that which is good and transcendsintelligence ancl being) as well as Plato in general ("in many placeshe calls that which is and the intelligence idea"). He does so to prove that Plato knew that the II THREE NEOARISTOTELIAN AND NEOPLATONIC soul stems from intelligence, and intelligence from that which is one. CONCEPTS:MONOPSYCHISM, MYSTICISM, He, therefore, continues by saying: what I said here is nothing new. METACONSCIOUSNESS It was said not recently but a long time ago, though not explicitly. My present discoursesare interpretations of those ancient ones. That they are old is proven by writings of Plato hirnself. Even the historic Parmenides, Plotinus continues, already equated being and intelligence. True, he called this intelligence also one, (r) I u flepi tdiv rptóv dpXuxóvúrcooróoeav (Enn. V r) Plotinus unrler- whereas it is many. Plato's Parmenides avoíds this statement. He takes to remind the souls which have forgotten their father-god, of discerns a first from a second, and a secondfrom a third. Thus here their true origin and nature. First, every soul should contemplate the again we find the doctrine of the three realms (9úoer,6). 'enlivens' action of the universal soul as she the cosmosand rules it. Anaxagoras calls his intelligence pure and unmixed. He also posits By so doing she will becomemore aware of her own worth. Afterwards that which is first as being simple and the One as being transcendent she should realize that she is a kind of word pronouncedby intelligence (Xc,rpr,oróv).
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Nature in the Medieval Ecological Imagination Jessica Rezunyk Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations Arts & Sciences Winter 12-15-2015 Science and Nature in the Medieval Ecological Imagination Jessica Rezunyk Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/art_sci_etds Recommended Citation Rezunyk, Jessica, "Science and Nature in the Medieval Ecological Imagination" (2015). Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 677. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/art_sci_etds/677 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Arts & Sciences at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of English Dissertation Examination Committee: David Lawton, Chair Ruth Evans Joseph Loewenstein Steven Meyer Jessica Rosenfeld Science and Nature in the Medieval Ecological Imagination by Jessica Rezunyk A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts & Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2015 St. Louis, Missouri © 2015, Jessica Rezunyk Table of Contents List of Figures……………………………………………………………………………. iii Acknowledgments…………………………………………………………………………iv Abstract……………………………………………………………………………………vii Chapter 1: (Re)Defining
    [Show full text]
  • Intellect and the Structuring of Reality in Plotinus and Averroes John S
    Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU School of Architecture, Art, and Historic School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications Preservation 2012 Intellect and the Structuring of Reality in Plotinus and Averroes John S. Hendrix Roger Williams University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp Part of the Classics Commons Recommended Citation Hendrix, John S., "Intellect and the Structuring of Reality in Plotinus and Averroes" (2012). School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications. Paper 29. http://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp/29 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation at DOCS@RWU. It has been accepted for inclusion in School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DOCS@RWU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Intellect and the Structuring of Reality in Plotinus and Averroes John Hendrix Though Averroes is not generally considered to be sympathetic to Neoplatonic thinking, there are definite parallels between the philoso- phies of intellect of Averroes and Plotinus. Both can be considered to be “Idealists” in that intelligible form precedes sensible form in per- ception, and that the material intellect of Averroes or Reason Principle of Plotinus, nous hylikos or pathetikos , depends in its functioning on the agent intellect of Averroes or Intellectual Principle of Plotinus, nous poietikos . The formation of the image in the oculus mentis is co- incident with the formation of a thought, and the sensible form is a transient residue of the permanent intelligible form, as if it is reflected in a mirror and projected on a surface.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| the Simpsons and Philosophy the Doh! of Homer 1St Edition
    THE SIMPSONS AND PHILOSOPHY THE DOH! OF HOMER 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE William Irwin | 9780812694338 | | | | | The Simpsons and Philosophy: The D'oh! of Homer Changing Minds on Climate Change. Are you kidding me? Unconditional Love. Technological Immortality. Where Does Morality Come From? Heck, I felt reeeally smug reading this book Since this book consists of eleven essays by eleven different authors, it's kind of hard to rate as a whole. Religion and philosophy in popular culture. Add to Cart. Archived from the original on December 13, The Simpsons and Philosophy The DOh! of Homer 1st edition book includes contributions from 18 philosophy academics. A great collection of essays by contemporary philosophers and academics, using the episodes and characters of The Simpson's as an The Simpsons and Philosophy The DOh! of Homer 1st edition into basic philosophical principles and fundamentals. David L. This series of essays claim to use the Simpsons as a way to get the layperson to read more philosophy, and does a patently terrible job of it. List of fictional religions List of religious ideas in science fiction List of religious ideas in fantasy fiction Parody religion Philosophy of religion Popular culture Pseudophilosophy Pseudoreligion Religion and video games Religious satire. Philosophy portal The Simpsons portal. Ashley Madison, accommodation, and silencing. The authors use too much jargon considering the subject and target audience. In fact, several authors did not seem to enjoy the Simpsons at all. The book was written inso there are lots of new episodes that, of course, haven't been touched. My Discovery of the X-Files.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neoplatonic and Sufi Wisdom
    119 ISSN 1648-2662. ACTA ORIENTAUA VILNENSIA. 2002 3 FROM ALEXANDRIA TO HARRAN: THE NEOPLATONIC AND SUFI WISDOM Algis UZOAVINYS Institute of Culture, Philosophy and Art The essay deals with the relationship between the Islamic philosophy and Hellenism. The influence of the Neoplatonic ideas on the early Islamic culture of spirituality is emphasized, while trying to reveal the common archetypal patterns of the Near Eastern and Mediterranean traditions. Without philosophy it is impossible to be perfectly pious. Stobaei Hermetica 11 B.2 Islamic Falsa/ah in the Light of Hellenic Sophia Plotinus used the termsophia (crocllt<X) simply as a synonym of "philosophy", hence restoring its primordial meaning. But falsafah as the continuation of CIItA.ocrocjlt<X is not just Hellenic philoso­ phy in Islamic guise. In line with Syrian and Mesopotamian translators (be they Sabians, Ori­ ental Christians or Muslims) the Greek sophia (sapientia) has been connected with Arabic root h-k-m. Sometimes sophia is rendered as 'Urn or even falsafah. Nevertheless, hikmah was chosen as the Arabic equivalent to the Greek termphilosophia, as Franz Rosenthal pointed outl . But philosophy for the Arabs meant the adherence to those philosophic doctrines which they learned chiefly from Neoplatonic commentators of Aristotle as well as Stagirit himself and Alexander Aphrodisias. The termgnosis usually is rendered as ma 'rifah, but many Sufis maintained 'Um as their goal instead of ma'rifah. However, when Sufis spoke of the union (ittihad) they meant an ontic union, not only an epistemic one (ittisal). Therefore, Philip Merlan surmises that it could even be possible that Avicenna sometimes professed both kinds of mysticism, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Mystical Experience, Religious Doctrine and Philosophical Analysis
    2 [3 181- MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE, RELIGIOUS DOCTRINE ,AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS P. C. Almond, M. A. (Lancast.er), B.D. (Hons) (London), Th. L. A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Phi tosophy The Department of Philosophy The University of Adelaide De cember, 1978. ''i,\"6-¡'(,,r-í.¡r',,' ii t ti/'i I;t . i rt ¡t(¡ ' { TABLE OF CONTENTS P age III ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS.. ..... Vi INTRODUCTION: THE PROBLEM OF UNITY AND DIVER- SITY IN RELIGIONS I CHAPTER ONE : R. C. ZAEHNER: THE VARIITIES OF MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE 30 CHAPTER TWO : N. SMART: THE MYSTICAL, THE NUMINOUS AND RELIGIOUS TRADI- TIONS... 64 CHAPTER THREE: W. T. STACE: EXTROVERTIVE AND INTROVERTIVE MYSTICISM tlt CHAPTER FOUR: R. OTTO: THE MYSTICAL, THE NUMINOUS AND METAPHYS I CS 156 CHAPTER FIVE: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS 204 CHAPTER SIX : MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE AND ITS IN- TERPRETATION: AN ANALYSIS OF POSSIBLE MODELS. 213 CHAPTER SEVEN: THE VARIETIES OF MYSTICAL EX- PERIENCE: A PHILOSOPHICAL PROLEGOMENON 254 STLECT BIBLI OGRAPHY 295 SUMMA R Y The spiritual vacuum generated by the decline of t.he Christian world-view in the West has creaLed for Western man the opportunity of taking up any one of a variety of modes of spirituality. Religious diversity has become a fact in Western religious Iife. This increasj-ng pluralism has led to a real-isation of the philosophical problem in- herent in it, a probl-em crystallised in the so-called 'con- flicting truth cl-aimsr problem:- The different religions appear to make different and incompatible cl-aims about the nature of ultimate re afity, of divinity, ofl human nature , and cosmi c destiny .
    [Show full text]
  • Catholic Theology in the Thirteenth Century and the Origins of Secularism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Mary Immaculate Research Repository and Digital Archive Article Catholic Theology in the Thirteenth Century and the Origins of Secularism Rik Van Nieuwenhove Mary Immaculate College, Limerick Abstract This article examines two distinct responses to the reception of Aristotle in the thirteenth century: the Bonaventurean and the Thomist. The outcome of this debate (and the Condemnations of 1277) led to the modern separation of faith and reason. Rather than seeing voluntarism and nominalism as the cause of the modern separation of faith and reason, and theology and philosophy, it will be suggested that it is actually the other way around: the Bonaventurean response indirectly resulted in the growing separation of faith and reason, which led, in turn, to voluntarism. It is important not to confuse the Thomist and Franciscan responses, as sometimes happens in recent scholarship, including in the work of Gavin D’Costa, as will be shown. Both the Thomist and the Bonaventurean approaches are legitimate resources to respond to the (post)-secular context in which we find ourselves, and the former should not be reduced to the latter. Keywords Aquinas and Bonaventure, faith and reason, origins of modernity n this article I want to revisit debates that took place at the end of the thirteenth cen- Itury. From a historical point of view it is exactly in this period that we find the origins of secularism and modernity, especially the growing separation of faith
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter the MIND–SOUL PROBLEM
    200437. Ashgatebundel Paul Bakker; 02_Chapter2. Proef 1. 14-11-2006:11.02, page 1. chapter THE MIND–SOUL PROBLEM Robert Pasnau . Introduction Few notions about the history of philosophy are more widely held than the no- tion that Descartes began something important in the way we think about the mind. But what exactly did he begin? A good place to look for an answer to this question is the start of his caustic set of replies to Gassendi, where Descartes cla- rifies a point of terminology. On his usage, he explains, the term ‘mind’ should be taken not in the traditional way, as referring to a part of the soul, but as refer- ring to the whole soul. Hence the two terms, ‘mind’ (mens)and‘soul’(anima), are to be treated as co-referential: ‘I consider the mind not as a part of the soul, but as the whole soul that thinks’.1 To be sure, this is no mere point of terminology. On the contrary, his erasure of the distinction between mind and soul constitutes the most fundamental respect in which Descartes’s conception of mind has influ- enced our own. In fact, one might reasonably think of this passage as marking out a kind of dividing line between medieval psychology and modern philosophy of mind. In what follows I will consider some of the medieval background to Descartes’s position, and show how this dividing line, though significant, is less clear than one might suppose. But before turning back to that earlier tradition, it is worth a closer look at how Descartes accounts for his choice of terminology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Types and Functions of Samizdat Publications in Czechoslovakia, 1948–1989
    The Types and Functions of Samizdat Publications in Czechoslovakia, 1948–1989 Martin Machovec Czech Literature, Charles University, Prague Abstract The term samizdat, now widespread, denotes the unofficial dissemination of any variety of text (book, magazine, leaflet, etc.) within “totalitarian” political sys- tems, especially those after World War II. Such publishing, though often not explic- itly forbidden by law, was always punishable through the misuse of a variety of laws under various pretexts. It occurred first in the Soviet Union as early as the 1920s, before the term was used, and then, labeled as such, from the 1950s onward. While samizdat publication occurred in Czechoslovakia after 1948, the word itself was used there only from the 1970s on. This article seeks to clarify the term and the phenome- non of samizdat with regard to the Czech literary scene to trace its historical limits and the justification for it. I will first describe the functions of Czech samizdat during the four decades of the totalitarian regime (1948–89), that is, examine it as a non- static, developing phenomenon, and then I will offer criteria by which to classify it. Such texts are classifiable by motivations for publishing and distributing samizdat; the originator; traditionally recognized types of printed material; date of production and of issuance, if different; textual content; occurrence in the chronology of politi- cal and cultural events under the totalitarian regime; and type of technology used in production. The applicability of such criteria is tested against the varied samizdat activities of the Czech poet and philosopher Egon Bondy. Both in Czech literary history and, as far as we know, in the literary his- tories of other countries as well there is a tendency to claim what is more or less obvious: that samizdat books, periodicals, leaflets, and recordings 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Early History of an Important Concept of Transpersonal Psychology in the West בפידיאף Harald Walach
    Higher Self – Spark of the Mind – Summit of the Soul: Early History of an Important Concept of Transpersonal Psychology in the West בפידיאף Harald Walach In: The International Journal of Transpersonal Studies, 2005, Volume 24 הפסיכואנליטיקאי האיטלקי Roberto Assagioli (1888-1974), מייסד התחום המכונה psychosynthesis, הכניס לראשונה את המונח Higher Self לתחום של פסיכולוגיה בין-אישית (transpersonal psychology) כדי להתייחס למסורת הנוצרית המיסטית ולתאר את העצמי שאופייני לחוויות מיסטיות. "העצמי הגבוה יותר" מרכז נפשי אקטיבי, שאחראי לאינטרגרציה נפשית ולהתפתחות רוחנית. From introduction: Harald Walach writes in “Higher Self" about the historical origins of the notion of the higher Self as introduced by Roberto Assagioli in psychosynthesis. This notion has origins stemming from antiquity, especially through the neo-Platonic tradi- tion. The importance of transpersonal psychologists understanding the traditional roots for many of the field’s core concepts is emphasized. The Higher Self is a concept introduced into transpersonal psychology by Roberto Assagioli, the founder of psychosynthesis. This notion is explained and linked up with the Western mystical tradition. Here, coming from antiquity and specifically from the neo-Platonic tradition, a similiar concept has been developed which became known as the spark of the soul, or summit of the mind. During the middle ages [the term] was developed into a psychology of mysticism by Thomas Gallus, popularized by Bonaventure, and radicalized by the Carthusian writer Hugh of Balma. Spark of the soul signifies an "organ of the mystical experience." It is argued that the split introduced into history between outer and inner experience has lain dormant ever since the 13th century, with inner experience relegated to the private and mystical realm.
    [Show full text]
  • Saybrook Journal 20
    THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF Transpersonal Studies Volume 24, 2005 Table of Contents Editors’ Introduction ii Harris Friedman and Douglas A. MacDonald Nondualism and the Divine Domain 1 Burton Daniels Higher Self—Spark of the Mind—Summit of the Soul: Early History of an Important Concept of Transpersonal Psychology in the West 16 Harald Walach The Myth of Nature and the Nature of Myth: Becoming Transparent to Transcendence 29 Dennis Patrick Slattery Myth, Archetype and the Neutral Mask: Actor Training and Transformation in Light of the Work of Joseph Campbell and Stanislav Grof 37 Ashley Wain The Sources of Higher States of Consciousness 48 Steve Taylor Fear No Spirits: A Pilgrim’s Journey through the Brazilian Churches of Ayahuasca 61 Robert Tindall Why Does the Universe Exist? An Advaita Vedantic Perspective 69 Adam J. Rock SPECIAL TOPIC: RUSSIAN SOUL: A REPORT FROM THE EUROPEAN TRANSPERSONAL ASSOCIATION 2005 CONFERENCE IN MOSCOW 77 Russian Soul: Introduction 77 Glenn Hartelius The Transpersonal Tradition in Russian Culture 78 Vladimir Maykov Synthesis and Plurality: Stories of the Self 79 Jason Wright The Psychic Defense 82 Vitor Rodrigues On Therapy by Means of Spiritual Culture 85 Mark E. Burno Creativity Lies at the Edge of Disintegration: Addressing the Shadow of Power and Leadership within Psychotherapy Training Organisations 87 Rupert Kinglake Tower We Were Made for These Times 90 Tanna Jakubowicz-Mount READER’S COMMENTARY A Love Letter 92 Kidder Smith About Our Contributors 94 Board of Editors 96 Editorial Policy and Manuscript Submission Guidelines 97 Back Issues 98 Editors’ Introduction his volume of the International Journal of explores actor training using the “neutral mask” from a Transpersonal Studies includes an eclectic group transpersonal perspective based on the works of Joseph Tof writings from a variety of areas within Campbell and Stanislav Grof.
    [Show full text]