Rationality and Oppression: a Defence of the Obligation to Resist

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Rationality and Oppression: a Defence of the Obligation to Resist RATIONALITY AND OPPRESSION : A DEFENCE OF THE OBLIGATION TO RESIST OPPRESSION DISSERTATION Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University BY CAROL HAY , M.A. THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY 2008 Approved by DISSERTATION COMMITTEE Professor Timothy Schroeder, Advisor Professor Louise Antony Advisor Professor Sigrún Svavarsdóttir Graduate Program in Philosophy Professor Richard Samuels COPYRIGHT BY CAROL HAY 2008 ABSTRACT In this dissertation, I argue that people who are oppressed have an obligation to resist their own oppression. While this argument is intended to hold for all people who are oppressed, I focus specifically on the obligation that women have to resist sexist oppression. I argue that this obligation is an instance of a larger species of obligation: to respect and protect some morally important feature or features of persons. In particular, I argue that Kant’s notion of humanity captures these morally important features of persons and that his arguments for the claim that humanity must be respected can be used to show that there is an obligation to protect one’s rational nature. I give an account of how oppression can harm people’s rational nature and show how resisting oppression is an instance of fulfilling the obligation to respect and protect one’s rational nature. And I emphasize how the obligation to protect rational nature applies in a special way to one’s own rational nature and thus that the obligation to resist one’s oppression is an obligation to the self. ii For Scott. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I’m grateful to the members of my dissertation committee for their feedback and their encouragement. Thanks to Louise Antony for being the first to encourage me to pursue the ideas I develop in this dissertation, and for sticking with me until the end. Thanks to Tim Schroeder for coming on board when I most needed it, and for helping me—nay, compelling me!—to see this project through to completion. Thanks to Sigrún Svavarsdóttir for reading so many drafts of this dissertation so very carefully, and for the careful and thoughtful advice that always resulted. Thanks to Richard Samuels for stepping in at the very last minute. In 2008, I presented some of the ideas found in Chapters 3 and 5 at the Society for Analytical Feminism’s conference at the University of Kentucky, at the University of Dayton’s Richard R. Baker Colloquium on the topic of “Building Coalitions Across Difference,” and to audiences at Chicago State University, Hobart and William Smith Colleges, Iowa State University, the University of Kentucky, the University of Massachusetts-Lowell, the University of Minnesota-Moorhead, The Ohio State University, and the University of Tennessee. I published a preliminary exploration of some of the main issues that motivate this dissertation as “Whether to Ignore Them and Spin: Moral Obligations to Resist Sexual Harassment,” Hypatia 20 (2005): 94-108. I presented earlier versions of that paper, in 2004 and 2005 respectively, at the Society for Analytic Feminism’s iv conference at the University of Western Ontario and the 32nd Conference on Value Inquiry at Louisiana State University. I owe additional thanks to Don Hubin and Dan Farrell for reading early versions of many of the ideas I’ve presented here. Thanks to Alison Kerr and Debbie Blickensderfer for helping me jump through some last-minute administrative hoops. Thanks to Ben Caplan for many helpful suggestions. Thanks to Anita Superson for being an early champion of this work, and for showing a continued interest in the progression of my ideas. Thanks to Joan Callahan, Ann Cudd, Jean Harvey, and Sally Haslanger for helpful feedback on some of the ideas found in Chapters 3 and 5. Thanks to Zac Cogley for countless discussions, and for being a darn fantastic roommate. Thanks to Kate Moran for several helpful discussions about Kant’s views on education, and to Ryan Muldoon for several helpful discussions about rationality. And thanks to Andy Arlig, Eric Carter, Jesse Duarte, Timmy Fuller, Dai Heide, Alison Kerr, David Merli, Cristina Moisa, Cathy Muller, Kevin Scharp, and Kelly Trogdon for all that time working together at coffee shops. Thanks to Karen HayDraude for taking such good care of me and for spoiling me absolutely rotten while I wrote this. Thanks to Jeremy HayDraude for making sure I had both the computers and the music I needed to write this. Thanks to Brian Hay for being proud of me (even though I didn’t turn out to be a dentist or a lawyer). Thanks to Kim Werker for her heroic bailout during the financial crisis. Thanks to Greg, Kim, and Cleo Werker, and to Pete Edgar, for always having a home for me in Vancouver. And thanks most of all to my partner, Scott Edgar. For being so fiercely certain that I could do this. And for not putting up with me thinking otherwise. v VITA September 30, 1977 …………….…. Born – Edmonton, AB, Canada 1999 ………….…………………… B.A. (Honours), Philosophy, University of Saskatchewan. 2000 …………………………….… M.A., Philosophy, Dalhousie University. 1999 - 2000 …………………….… Teaching Assistant, Dalhousie University. 2001 – 2004 …………………….… Teaching Assistant, The Ohio State University. 2004 – 2007 …………………….… Graduate Teaching Associate, The Ohio State University. 2007 – 2008 …………………….… Visiting Instructor, Bryn Mawr College. 2008 …………………….………... Sessional Instructor, University of British Columbia. 2009 ……………………………… Assistant Professor, University of Massachusetts, Lowell. PUBLICATIONS “On Whether to Ignore Them and Spin: Moral Obligations to Resist Sexual Harassment,” Hypatia , 20 (2005): 94-108. FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy vi TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE Abstract …………….…………………………….…………………………………. ii Dedication ...…………………………………….…………………………………. iii Acknowledgments ...…………………………….…………………………………. iv Vita ...…………………………………………….…………………………………. vi CHAPTER 1 – INTRODUCTION ……………………………………………… 1 CHAPTER 2 – Oppression and Rationality ……………………………………… 21 Analyzing Oppression: A Definition of Oppression …………………… 21 Unjust Group-Specific Harm …………………………………… 23 Structural and Systemic Harm …………………………………….. 34 The Historical Basis for this Account of Oppression …………………… 38 How Oppression Harms People’s Rational Nature ……………………….. 41 Oppression can cause practically significant self-deception. ……… 43 Oppression can damage capacities for instrumental deliberation. ...... 45 Oppression can damage capacities for teleological deliberation. ....… 47 Oppression can cause weakness of will. …………………………… 48 Conclusion ...………………………………………….………………….. 50 CHAPTER 3 – An Obligation to Resist One’s own Oppression ……...………….… 52 An Obligation to Respect Rational Nature …………...…………………… 53 What does this Obligation Require? ……………………………………….. 59 Why the Oppressed have an Obligation to Resist their Oppression ………. 63 Other Accounts …………………………………………………………... 71 The Very Possibility of Obligations to the Self …………………………… 83 Objection: This is an Obligation to Others, not the Self …..…….………….. 88 Another Possibility: This is an Obligation to Respect Rational Nature in General ....……………………………….. 99 Objection: This Account has things Exactly Backward …………………. 103 Conclusion ...………………………………………….………………... 107 INTERLUDE – A Feminist Defence of Kant ……………………………………... 108 CHAPTER 4 – Respect-Worthiness and Dignity …………………………………... 121 Respect-Worthiness and Dignity ……………………………………… 126 Humanity is an End in Itself ………………………………………... 128 vii Personality has Dignity ……………………………………………….. 130 Evidence for this Interpretation …………………………………………. 136 Some Textual Counterevidence ……………………………………….. 145 Competing Interpretations ………………………………………………. 150 Conclusion …………………………………………………………… 162 CHAPTER 5 – Imperfect Duties and Why the Duty to Resist Oppression is not too Demanding …………….…………….…… 165 Four Objections ………………………………………………………… 166 The Objection from Risk ……………………………………... 166 The Objection from Blaming the Victim ……………………....... 169 The Objection from Ought Implies Can ………………………… 171 The Objection from Supererogation ...…………………………… 173 Kant on Perfect and Imperfect Duties …………………………………… 176 The Obligation to Resist One’s Oppression as an Imperfect Duty ……… 185 Latitude in Which Action to Take ……………………………………….. 192 Latitude in Refraining from Action …………………………………… 200 Back to the Four Objections ……………………………………………. 207 The Objection from Risk ……………………………………... 207 The Objection from Blaming the Victim ……………………... 208 The Objection from Ought Implies Can ………………………… 211 The Objection from Supererogation …………………………….. 213 Conclusion ………………………………………….………………... 218 APPENDIX – The Division of Domestic Labour as a Case Study of Oppression … 220 BIBLIOGRAPHY ………………………………………………….…………… 235 viii CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION Let’s begin with some examples. In his essay “Getting Away from Already Being Pretty Much Away from It All,” David Foster Wallace describes his visit to the Illinois State Fair for Harper’s magazine. 1 While his friend—whom he calls Native Companion because she’s a local—is riding one of the fair’s rides the men operating the ride stop it as she’s upside down so that her dress falls over her head and they can “ogl[e] her nethers.” 2 What follows is the exchange that takes place between Wallace and Native Companion immediately after she gets off the ride. “Did you sense something kind of sexual-harassmentish going on through that whole little sick exercise?” “Oh for fuck’s sake … it was fun .” … “They were looking up your dress . You couldn’t see them, maybe. They hung you upside down at a great height
Recommended publications
  • Why Ideal Epistemology? 2
    1 Why Ideal Epistemology? 2 3 4 5 6 1 Ideal and nonideal epistemology 7 What are ideal and nonideal epistemology? We can begin by gesturing toward some loose sociological 8 trends: nonideal epistemology ideal epistemology informal, non-mathy formal, mathy1 talks about beliefs talks about credences2 emphasizes relation to emphasizes relation to decision knowledge theory uses “justified” uses “rational” uses “reasons” language doesn’t unimpressive babies superbabies written in Word written in LaTeX . 9 10 Ideal epistemologists are concerned with questions about what perfectly rational, cognitively ide- 11 alized, computationally unlimited believers would believe. (Note: I use the term “belief” broadly for any 12 doxastic state, including binary belief, credences, comparative confidence, etc.; mutatis mutandis for 13 “believe” and “believer”.) Often this involves presupposing or defending epistemic norms that, arguably, 14 no actual humans can satisfy: norms mandating 15 logical omniscience; ◦ 1 Note that despite this trend, the ideal/nonideal distinction in epistemology is strictly orthogonal to the formal/informal distinction. Theorists of bounded rationality often pursue formal nonideal epistemology; I personally often do informal ideal epistemology. 2 Again, despite the trend, this distinction is orthogonal to the ideal/nonideal distinction: AGM models of belief revision are a form of ideal epistemology, for example (Alchourrón et al., 1985). And much of the bounded rationality literature focuses on credence. 1 1 consistency and closure of binary beliefs; ◦ 2 infinitely precise credences; ◦ 3 credences satisfying the Kolmogorov probability axioms; ◦ 4 updating by conditionalization; ◦ 5 immediate update (rather than temporally extended reasoning); ◦ 6 closure of doxastic attitudes under boolean operations; ◦ 3 7 ...and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivity in the Feminist Philosophy of Science
    OBJECTIVITY IN THE FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requisites for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Karen Cordrick Haely, M.A. ***** The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Louise M. Antony, Adviser Professor Donald C. Hubin _______________________ Professor George Pappas Adviser Philosophy Graduate Program ABSTRACT According to a familiar though naïve conception, science is a rigorously neutral enterprise, free from social and cultural influence, but more sophisticated philosophical views about science have revealed that cultural and personal interests and values are ubiquitous in scientific practice, and thus ought not be ignored when attempting to understand, describe and prescribe proper behavior for the practice of science. Indeed, many theorists have argued that cultural and personal interests and values must be present in science (and knowledge gathering in general) in order to make sense of the world. The concept of objectivity has been utilized in the philosophy of science (as well as in epistemology) as a way to discuss and explore the various types of social and cultural influence that operate in science. The concept has also served as the focus of debates about just how much neutrality we can or should expect in science. This thesis examines feminist ideas regarding how to revise and enrich the concept of objectivity, and how these suggestions help achieve both feminist and scientific goals. Feminists offer us warnings about “idealized” concepts of objectivity, and suggest that power can play a crucial role in determining which research programs get labeled “objective”.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminism & Philosophy Vol.5 No.1
    APA Newsletters Volume 05, Number 1 Fall 2005 NEWSLETTER ON FEMINISM AND PHILOSOPHY FROM THE EDITOR, SALLY J. SCHOLZ NEWS FROM THE COMMITTEE ON THE STATUS OF WOMEN, ROSEMARIE TONG ARTICLES MARILYN FISCHER “Feminism and the Art of Interpretation: Or, Reading the First Wave to Think about the Second and Third Waves” JENNIFER PURVIS “A ‘Time’ for Change: Negotiating the Space of a Third Wave Political Moment” LAURIE CALHOUN “Feminism is a Humanism” LOUISE ANTONY “When is Philosophy Feminist?” ANN FERGUSON “Is Feminist Philosophy Still Philosophy?” OFELIA SCHUTTE “Feminist Ethics and Transnational Injustice: Two Methodological Suggestions” JEFFREY A. GAUTHIER “Feminism and Philosophy: Getting It and Getting It Right” SARA BEARDSWORTH “A French Feminism” © 2005 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 BOOK REVIEWS Robin Fiore and Hilde Lindemann Nelson: Recognition, Responsibility, and Rights: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory REVIEWED BY CHRISTINE M. KOGGEL Diana Tietjens Meyers: Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action, and Social Life REVIEWED BY CHERYL L. HUGHES Beth Kiyoko Jamieson: Real Choices: Feminism, Freedom, and the Limits of the Law REVIEWED BY ZAHRA MEGHANI Alan Soble: The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings REVIEWED BY KATHRYN J. NORLOCK Penny Florence: Sexed Universals in Contemporary Art REVIEWED BY TANYA M. LOUGHEAD CONTRIBUTORS ANNOUNCEMENTS APA NEWSLETTER ON Feminism and Philosophy Sally J. Scholz, Editor Fall 2005 Volume 05, Number 1 objective claims, Beardsworth demonstrates Kristeva’s ROM THE DITOR “maternal feminine” as “an experience that binds experience F E to experience” and refuses to be “turned into an abstraction.” Both reconfigure the ground of moral theory by highlighting the cultural bias or particularity encompassed in claims of Feminism, like philosophy, can be done in a variety of different objectivity or universality.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interpretationist Approach to the Thinking Mind DISSERTATION
    Thought Without Language: an Interpretationist Approach to the Thinking Mind DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Michael Dean Jaworski Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2010 Dissertation Committee: Neil Tennant, Advisor William Taschek Ben Caplan Copyright by Michael Dean Jaworski 2010 Abstract I defend an account of thought on which non-linguistic beings can be thinkers. This result is significant in that many philosophers have claimed that the ability to think depends on the ability to use language. These opponents of my view note that our everyday understanding of our own cognitive activities qua thought bestows upon those activities the propositional structure of sentences and the inferential norms of public linguistic practice. They hold that our attributions of thought to non-linguistic beings project non-existent structure onto the cognitive activities of those beings, and assess the beings’ activities according to standards to which the beings bear no responsibility. So, despite the complex neural and behavioral activities of many non-linguistic beings, my opponents hold that those beings are not properly described as thinkers. To respond to my opponents successfully, one must not merely cite scientific and folk practices of thought attribution that permit thought to be attributed to some non- linguistic beings. My opponents’ insights might be taken to demonstrate a need to revise those practices, or to treat the attributions of thought to non-linguistic beings made within those practices as instrumentally valuable but technically false. Instead, my strategy is to acknowledge the language-like structure and norms of thought, and show that a non- linguistic being’s cognitive activities might nonetheless have that structure and be subject ii to those norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Martha Nussbaum
    Martha Nussbaum EDUCATION 1964-1966 Wellesley College 1966-1967 New York University, School of the Arts 1967-1969 New York University, Washington Square College. B.A. 1969. 1969-1975 Harvard University, M.A. 1971, Ph.D. 1975 (Classical Philology) 1972-1975 Harvard University, Society of Fellows, Junior Fellow 1973-1974 St. Hugh's College, Oxford University: Honorary Member of Senior Common Room EMPLOYMENT 1999-- University of Chicago, Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics Appointed in Law School and Philosophy Department, 2012 -- Appointed in: Law School, Philosophy Department, and Divinity School, -2012 Associate Member, Classics Department (1995 -- ) Associate Member, Department of Political Science (2003 -- ) Associate Member, Divinity School, (2012 --) Member, Committee on Southern Asian Studies (Affiliate 1999 –2005, full Member 2006--) Board Member,, Center for Gender Studies 1999-2002 Board Member, Human Rights Program, 2002--; Co-Chair, 2007-8; Founder and Coordinator, Center for Comparative Constitutionalism, 2002 – 2007 (spring) Visiting Professor of Law and Classics, Harvard University 2004 (spring) Visiting Professor, Centre for Political Science, Jawaharlal Nehru University, New Delhi, India 1996-1998 University of Chicago, Ernst Freund Professor of Law and Ethics (Appointed in Law School, Philosophy Department, and Divinity School, Associate in Classics) 1996 (spring) Oxford University, Weidenfeld Visiting Professor 1995-1996 University of Chicago, Professor of Law and Ethics (Appointed in Law School,
    [Show full text]
  • Mentor Bios 2013
    Mentor Bios – 2013 Workshop Amy Allen is the Parents Distinguished Research Professor in the Humanities and Professor of Philosophy and Women's and Gender Studies at Dartmouth College. Her research interests are in Contemporary Continental Philosophy, social and political theory, and feminist theory. In particular, she works at the intersection of French poststructuralism, the Frankfurt School, and feminism on topics such as power, agency, subjectivity, autonomy, history and normativity. She is the author of two books: The Power of Feminist Theory: Domination, Resistance, Solidarity (1999) and The Politics of Our Selves: Power, Autonomy, and Gender in Contemporary Critical Theory (2008). She is the Co-Editor in Chief of the journal Constellations, series editor of the Columbia University Press book series New Directions in Critical Theory, and Executive Co-director of SPEP, the Society for Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Louise Antony is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts Amherst. She received her B.A. from Syracuse University in 1975, and her Ph.D. from Harvard University in 1982. Prof. Antony has research interests in the philosophy of mind, naturalistic epistemology, feminist theory, and the philosophy of religion. She has edited or co-edited three volumes: A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (with Charlotte Witt) and Chomsky and His Critics (with Norbert Hornstein), and Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life. She has contributed to the New York Times blog, “The Stone,” and to the popular website AskPhilosophers.org. Ann Cudd is University Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Associate Dean for Humanities at the University of Kansas.
    [Show full text]
  • Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind
    Proposal for Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind Edited by Jonathan Cohen∗and Brian McLaughliny This volume will introduce the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind. The volume will include ten pairs of newly commissioned essays ad- vocating opposing viewpoints | one for each of the ten topics listed below. In addition, the editors will provide a substantive introduction that will lay out the necessary background for the debates and locate the individual topics within philosophy of mind and in relation to one another. The essays will each be around 6000 to 8000 words in length, and will be accessible to upper-level undergraduates and graduate students. Consequently, we expect that the volume could be used as text for advanced courses in phi- losophy of mind. However, the essays will also represent the state of play in the areas, and will contain original argumentation by eminent philosophers, so it will also be an important text for academics working in philosophy of mind and adjoining areas. We have organized our questions under the three headings that, in our minds, structure the central debates in contemporary philosophy of mind: questions about the ontology of the mental, questions about the nature of mental content, and questions about the nature of consciousness. For many of the questions on our list, we have suggested a number of backup authors in case our first choices are unable to write the essays. Although some names appear more than once on our list (including appearances as backup authors) we would not allow more than one piece by a single author in the volume.
    [Show full text]
  • The Structure of Consciousness
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Open Access Dissertations 9-2013 The trS ucture of Consciousness Lowell Keith Friesen University of Massachusetts Amherst, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/open_access_dissertations Part of the Other Neuroscience and Neurobiology Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Friesen, Lowell Keith, "The trS ucture of Consciousness" (2013). Open Access Dissertations. 794. https://doi.org/10.7275/5389-r721 https://scholarworks.umass.edu/open_access_dissertations/794 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Access Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STRUCTURE OF CONSCIOUSNESS A Dissertation Presented by LOWELL KEITH FRIESEN Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 2013 Philosophy c Copyright by Lowell Keith Friesen 2013 All Rights Reserved THE STRUCTURE OF CONSCIOUSNESS A Dissertation Presented by LOWELL KEITH FRIESEN Approved as to style and content by: Joseph Levine, Chair Louise Antony, Member Hilary Kornblith, Member Erik Cheries, Member Hilary Kornblith, Department Chair Philosophy To Pam, Lyndon, and Kira. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would, first of all, like to thank the faculty, students, and support staff at the University of Massachusetts philosophy department for creating the positive study environment I had the privilege of being a part of during my time there. Not all graduate students in philosophy have this good fortune.
    [Show full text]
  • Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Volume 90, November 2016
    Things Oughta Make Sense1 Louise Antony UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Presidential Address delivered at the one hundred twelfth Eastern Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in Washington, DC, on January 8, 2016. When I first started doing philosophy, I didn’t really know what I was doing. Some will say that not much has changed. And it is true that I don’t have a worked-out metaphilosophy. It’s still the case that I’m flummoxed by innocent questions about what I do. (On airplanes, I used to sometimes lie and say that I was a nurse or a lawyer or something else people could recognize. But I eventually found that if all I want is for my neighbor to leave me alone, it’s far more effective to tell him the truth: “I’m a philosopher. Let me explain my theory of mental causation: it all starts with Descartes. .”) But even if there are many big questions about philosophy that I can’t answer, I still do think that I’ve gained some insight into what philosophy is. Or, at least, what it could be. Or what it should be. I had the enormous good fortune as a beginning student of philosophy to fall under the tutelage of some extraordinary philosophers (as well as some extraordinary teachers who were not philosophers—for example, the flutist John Oberbrunner.) My very first philosophy teacher, and perhaps my harshest critic even to this day, was/is Peter van Inwagen. He paid me the immense compliment of taking me—my questions, my objections, my arguments, and even my confusions—seriously.
    [Show full text]
  • Dr. Louise Antony Opens Midwest Philosophy Colloquium University Relations
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Minnesota, Morris (UMM): Digital Well University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well University Relations News Archive External Relations 9-30-2004 Dr. Louise Antony opens Midwest Philosophy Colloquium University Relations Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/urel_news Recommended Citation University Relations, "Dr. Louise Antony opens Midwest Philosophy Colloquium" (2004). University Relations News Archive. Paper 2029. http://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/urel_news/2029 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the External Relations at University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. It has been accepted for inclusion in University Relations News Archive by an authorized administrator of University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Contact Melissa Weber, Director of Communications Phone: 320-589-6414, [email protected] Jenna Ray, Editor/Writer Phone: 320-589-6068, [email protected] Dr. Louise Antony opens Midwest Philosophy Colloquium Summary: (September 30, 2004)-Dr. Louise Antony, professor of philosophy at Ohio State University, Columbus, will give the Fall Midwest Philosophy Colloquium lecture on Monday, Oct. 11. She will present a campus seminar at 2:30 p.m. in the Alumni Room of Oyate Hall in the UMM Student Center, and an evening lecture at 7 p.m. at First Lutheran Church in Morris. Dr. Antony is also a faculty in the Women's Studies and Comparative Literature Departments at Ohio State. She earned her doctoral degree in philosophy from Harvard University in 1982 and a bachelor's degree in philosophy from Syracuse University in 1975.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul K. Moser Ed
    Paul K. Moser ed. The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford: Oxford University Press 2002 end p.iii Preface Epistemology, also known as the theory of knowledge, will flourish as long as we deem knowledge valuable. We shall, I predict, continue to value knowledge, if only for its instrumental value: it gets us through the day as well as the night. Indeed, it's hard to imagine a stable person, let alone a stable society, indifferent to the real difference between genuine knowledge and mere opinion, even mere true opinion. The study of knowledge, then, has a very bright future. In the concept-sensitive hands of philosophers, epistemology focuses on the nature, origin, and scope of knowledge. It thus examines the defining ingredients, the sources, and the limits of knowledge. Given the central role of epistemology in the history of philosophy as well as in contemporary philosophy, epistemologists will always have work to do. Debates over the analysis of knowledge, the sources of knowledge, and the status of skepticism will alone keep the discipline of epistemology active and productive. This book presents some of the best work in contemporary epistemology by leading epistemologists. Taken together, its previously unpublished essays span the whole field of epistemology. They assess prominent positions and break new theoretical ground while avoiding undue technicality. My own work on this book has benefited from many people and institutions. First, I thank the nineteen contributors for their fine cooperation and contributions in the face of numerous deadlines. Second, I thank Peter Ohlin, Philosophy Editor at Oxford University Press, for helpful advice and assistance on many fronts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reference and Content of Proper Names: a Social and Pragmatic Approach
    THE REFERENCE AND CONTENT OF PROPER NAMES: A SOCIAL AND PRAGMATIC APPROACH DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Yimin Kui, M.A. The Ohio State University 2005 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Joseph Levine, Adviser Professor Louise Antony Professor Robert Kraut ____________________________ Adviser Graduate Program in Philosophy ABSTRACT The goal of my dissertation is to propose and defend a unified account of the semantic content of proper names that can address all the following six problems facing various theories of proper names: The Modal Argument, the Epistemic Argument, the Semantic Argument, Frege’s Puzzle, Belief Puzzles, and Empty Names. I first defend a theory of reference concerning proper names. I argue that for every proper name, there is a structured web of community uses associated with it. Among the objects involved in the Kripkean causal network of the name, the object that stands out as the dominant bearer of the web of community uses is the referent of the name. Roughly, an object becomes the dominant bearer of the web of uses, if it either satisfies or causes the weighted most of the properties/uses in the web. Secondly, I examine Nathan Salmon’s and Scott Soames’s defenses of the direct reference theory. For their strategies to succeed, they need the assumption that all the properties/beliefs (or at least the specific ones) in the web of community uses of a name are pragmatically imparted information and thus semantically irrelevant information.
    [Show full text]