A STUDY in EARLY MEDIEVAL MEREOLOGY: BOETHIUS, ABELARD, and PSEUDO-JOSCELIN DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A STUDY in EARLY MEDIEVAL MEREOLOGY: BOETHIUS, ABELARD, and PSEUDO-JOSCELIN DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of A STUDY IN EARLY MEDIEVAL MEREOLOGY: BOETHIUS, ABELARD, AND PSEUDO-JOSCELIN DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Andrew W. Arlig, M.A. The Ohio State University 2005 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Tamar Rudavsky, Adviser Professor Peter O. King ______________________________ Professor Allan Silverman Adviser Graduate Program in Philosophy Copyright by Andrew W. Arlig 2005 ABSTRACT The study of parts and wholes, or mereology, occupies two of the best philosophical minds of twelfth-century Europe, Abelard and Pseudo-Joscelin. But the contributions of Abelard and Pseudo-Joscelin cannot be adequately assessed until we come to terms with the mereological doctrines of the sixth century philosopher Boethius. Apart from providing the general mereological background for the period, Boethius influences Abelard and Pseudo-Joscelin in two crucial respects. First, Boethius all but omits mention of the classical Aristotelian concept of form. Second, Boethius repeatedly highlights a rule which says that if a part is removed, the whole is removed as well. Abelard makes many improvements upon Boethius. His theory of static identity accounts for the relations of sameness and difference that hold between a thing and its part. His theory of identity also provides a solution to the problem of material constitution. With respect to the problem of persistence, Abelard assimilates Boethius’ rule and proposes that the loss of any part entails the annihilation of the whole. More precisely, Abelard thinks that the matter of things suffers annihilation upon the gain or loss of even one part. He also holds that many structured wholes, namely artifacts, are strictly dependent upon their parts. Yet Abelard insists that human beings survive a ii variety of mereological changes. Abelard is silent about objects which are neither artifacts nor persons. I argue that Abelard has the theoretical resources to provide an account of the persistence of these types of object, so long as some forms are ontologically robust. Pseudo-Joscelin rejects the thesis that the removal of any part entails the destruction of the whole. The annihilation of a whole follows only from the removal of essential parts. Pseudo-Joscelin employs two basic principles in his theory of persistence. First, forms and the functions encoded in them play a primary role in identity and persistence. He also makes use of a genetic criterion. Pseudo-Joscelin expands both principles and employs them when he vigorously defends the thesis that a universal is a concrete whole composed of particulars from Abelard’s criticisms. iii To Tri iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Many persons have helped to make the completion of this dissertation possible. Several deserve special mention. Professor Josef Stern introduced me to medieval philosophy. While advising me on my undergraduate thesis, he also taught me the virtues of precision in thought and expression. I hope that I have not failed him much in the subsequent years. Professor Peter King introduced me to Abelard and Pseudo-Joscelin, and to the pleasures of exploring twelfth-century metaphysics. Peter’s knowledge of Abelard and twelfth-century philosophy is profound, and I have learned much from our close collaboration on this project. Without him, this specific project could not have happened. Professor Tamar Rudavsky has been a tremendous source of support as my current adviser. The final stages of my work have benefited from her able guidance. Professor Allan Silverman has been a valuable resource, and a wonderful friend and colleague. To him I owe a greater appreciation of the Greek philosophy that underwrites twelfth-century metaphysics. Portions of chapter 4 have been read before audiences at the Cornell Summer Colloquium in Medieval Philosophy in May 2003, the Department of Philosophy at the Ohio State University in November 2003, and the annual meeting of the Ohio v Philosophical Association in April 2004. I benefited immensely from the comments and questions raised by these audiences. In particular, I must thank Kevin Guilfoy for his commentary at the OPA meeting, as well as his general enthusiasm for my project. I also want to thank Scott MacDonald for his generousity and encouragement, and for providing a relaxed but intellectually stimulating environment at Cornell in which medievalists can present their work. Carol Hay helped me with final-hour formatting issues. Her knowledge of Microsoft Word spared me uncountable hours of work, and perhaps even added several years to the life of my heart. My gratitude and affection are boundless. None of this would be possible without the love and sacrifice of my parents Douglas and Patricia Arlig. A long time ago they were forced to come to terms with the fact that their son was a humanist, and not a scientist. Their support has been unwaivering ever since. Finally, I must thank my wife Rajashree Datta. She above all has given me the means to bring this project to its end. She has sacrificed much in the process. With love and gratitude, I dedicate this work to her. vi VITA November 9, 1971 ……………….….…. Born – Phoenix, AZ, USA 1994 ………….………………………… B.A. with Honors, The University of Chicago. 2002 ………………………………….… M.A. Philosophy, The Ohio State University. 1998 -1999 ………………………….….. Distinguished University Fellow, The Ohio State University 1999 - 2003 …………………………….. Graduate Teaching Associate, The Ohio State University 2003 - 2004 ………………………….…. Distinguished University Fellow, The Ohio State University 2004 - present ………………….……….. Graduate Teaching Associate, The Ohio State University FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy vii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Abstract . .ii Dedication . iv Acknowledgments . .v Vita. vii List of abbreviations. .xi Chapters: 1. Introduction . .1 2. Introduction to mereology and the metaphysics of mereology . .12 2.1 Formal mereology and the metaphysics of mereology . 13 2.2 Mereological sums, and the problem of what things are wholes . .15 2.3 When is something a part? . .27 2.4 Dependence . 35 2.4.1 Varieties of ontological dependence . .35 2.4.2 Dependence of the whole upon its parts . .36 2.4.3 Dependence of the part on the whole . 39 2.5 Synchronic and diachronic identity . .49 2.6 Conclusion to chapter 2 . .60 3. Boethius and the early mereological tradition . 62 3.1 Parts, wholes, and division . .65 3.1.1 The science of division. 66 3.1.2 Universal wholes are not integral wholes. 75 3.2 The four-fold distinction between the genus and the whole . 84 3.2.1 The genus is divided with respect to quality. 85 3.2.2 The genus is naturally prior. .89 viii 3.2.3 The genus is matter. 97 3.2.4 The species is the same thing as its genus. .101 3.2.5 Conclusion to the four differences. .109 3.3 Boethius’ metaphysics of mereology. 113 3.3.1 The problem with quantity . 113 3.3.2 On when something is a part of an integral whole. .121 3.3.3 On static identity . .127 3.3.4 The ontological dependence of wholes upon their parts. .132 3.4 Conclusion to chapter 3 . .139 4. Abelard’s mereology and its role in metaphysics . 141 4.1 Abelard’s metaphysics. 141 4.1.1 Ontology. 142 4.1.2 Hylomorphism and the constitution of things . .144 4.1.3 Integral wholes . 153 4.1.4 States and states-of-affairs . 159 4.2 Identity . .165 4.2.1 Abelard on numerical sameness . .. .165 4.2.2 Identity and material constitution . .180 4.2.3 Segue to problems of persistence and change . .195 4.3 Persistence and change . 197 4.3.1 The Growing Argument . 198 4.3.2 No temporal parts . 214 4.3.3 Substantial persistence . 227 4.3.4 The persistence of persons . 234 4.4 Conclusion to chapter 4 . .242 5. Pseudo-Joscelin and the Moderate critique of Abelard . .243 5.1 The Moderate theory of identity and persistence . .245 5.1.1 The Mereological Sorites. .246 5.1.2 Moderate responses to the Sorites . .250 5.2 The collection theory of universals . 271 5.2.1 Abelard on the collection theory . .272 5.2.2 An Abelardian critique of collective realism . 277 5.2.3 A new version of the collection theory. 283 ix 5.3 Conclusion to chapter 5. 302 6. Conclusion . .304 List of references . .316 x LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Abelard Dial. Abelard Dialectica. (1954a) Abelard Hex. Abelard Expositio in Hexaemeron. (1855) Abelard In de Div. Abelard De divisionibus incipit. (1954b) Abelard LNPS Logica ‘nostrorum petitioni sociorum’. (1933) Abelard Log. Ingr. 1 Logica ‘ingredientibus’, pt. 1: glossae super Porphyrium. (1919) Abelard Log. Ingr. 2 Logica ‘ingredientibus’, pt. 2: glossae super Praedicamenta Aristotelis. (1921) Abelard Sent. Abelard Sententiae secundum M. Petrum. (1958) Abelard Theol. Chr. Abelard Theologia Christiana. (1969) Abelard Theol. Sch. Abelard Theologia Scholarium. (1987a) Abelard TSB Abelard Theologia ‘summi boni’. (1987b) Alexander in Metaph. Alexander of Aphrodisias In Aristotelis Metaphysica commentaria. (1891) Ammonius In Cat. Ammonius In Aristotelis Categorias commentarius. (1905) Ammonius In Isag. Ammonius In Porphyrii Isagogen sive V voces. (1891) Arethas Sch. Arethas of Caesarea Scholia on Porphyry’s Isagoge and Aristotle’s Categories. (1994) xi Asclepius In Metaph. In Aristotelis Metaphysicorum libros A-Z commentaria. (1888) Boethius Contra Eut. Boethius Contra Eutychen. In Boethius 2000. Boethius De Div. Boethius De Divisione. (1998) Boethius De top. diff. Boethius De topicis differentiis. (1990) Boethius De Trin. Boethius De Sancta Trinitate. In Boethius 2000. Boethius In Cat. Boethius In Categorias Aristotelis libri quatuor. (1891) Boethius In de Int. II Boethius In librum Aristotelis Peri Hermenias pars posterior. (1880) Boethius In Isag. I Boethius In Isagogen Porphyrii Commentorum editionis primae. (1906) Boethius In Isag. II Boethius In Isagogen Porphyrii Commentorum editionis secundae. (1906) Boethius In Cic. Top. Boethius In Topica Ciceronis Commentaria.
Recommended publications
  • Projectile Motion Acc
    PHY1033C/HIS3931/IDH 3931 : Discovering Physics: The Universe and Humanity’s Place in It Fall 2016 Prof. Peter Hirschfeld, Physics Announcements • HW 1 due today; HW 2 posted, due Sept. 13 • Lab 1 today 2nd hour • Reading: Gregory Chs. 2,3 Wertheim (coursepack), Lindberg (coursepack) • HW/office hours 10:40 M,T, 11:45 W email/call to make appt. if these are bad Last time Improvements to Aristotle/Eudoxus Appolonius of Perga (~20 -190 BCE) : proposed: 1) eccentric orbits (planet goes in circle at const. speed, but Earth was off center) 2) epicycles (planet moves on own circle [epicycle] around a point that travels in another circle [deferent] around E. His model explained • variation in brightness of planets • changes in angular speed Ptolemy (AD 100 – c. 170): Almagest summarized ancient ideas about solar system. He himself proposed “equant point”: eccentric point about which planet moved with constant angular speed. Not true uniform circular motion, but explained data better. Ptolemaic universe (Equant point suppressed) • Note: this picture puts planets at a distance relative to Earth corresponding to our modern knowledge, but Ptolemaic system did not predict order of planets (or care!) • Exception: inner planets had to have orbits that kept them between Earth and Sun • Why epicycles? Not asked. Clicker quickies Q1: Ptolemy’s model explained retrograde motion of the planets. This means that A. Some planets moved clockwise while others moved counterclockwise along their orbits B. Some planets moved outside the plane of the ecliptic C. Some planets were observed to stop in the sky, move apparently backwards along their path, forward again D.
    [Show full text]
  • Aelius Aristides , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 27:3 (1986:Autumn) P.279
    BLOIS, LUKAS DE, The "Eis Basilea" [Greek] of Ps.-Aelius Aristides , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 27:3 (1986:Autumn) p.279 The Ei~ BauLAea of Ps.-Aelius Aristides Lukas de Blois HE AUTHENTICITY of a speech preserved under the title El~ Ba­ T utAia in most MSS. of Aelius Aristides (Or. 35K.) has long been questioned.1 It will be argued here that the speech is a basilikos logos written by an unknown author of the mid-third century in accordance with precepts that can be found in the extant rhetorical manuals of the later Empire. Although I accept the view that the oration was written in imitation of Xenophon's Agesilaus and Isoc­ rates' Evagoras, and was clearly influenced by the speeches of Dio Chrysostom on kingship and Aristides' panegyric on Rome,2 I offer support for the view that the El~ BautAia is a panegyric addressed to a specific emperor, probably Philip the Arab, and contains a political message relevant to a specific historical situation. After a traditional opening (§ § 1-4), the author gives a compar­ atively full account of his addressee's recent accession to the throne (5-14). He praises the emperor, who attained power unexpectedly while campaigning on the eastern frontier, for doing so without strife and bloodshed, and for leading the army out of a critical situation back to his own territory. The author mentions in passing the em­ peror's education (1lf) and refers to an important post he filled just before his enthronement-a post that gave him power, prepared him for rule, and gave him an opportunity to correct wrongs (5, 13).
    [Show full text]
  • Philoponus on Topos
    Philoponus on τόπος. Redefining Place in Late Antiquity D i s s e r t a t i o n zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) eingereicht an der Philosophischen Fakultät I der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin und verteidigt am 25. October 2013 von Ioannis Papachristou Der Präsident der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Prof. Dr. Jan-Hendrik Olbertz Der Dekan der Philosophischen Fakultät I Prof. Michael Seadle, PhD Gutachter Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Christoph Helmig Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Christian Wildberg The dissertation attempts to interpret afresh, on the one hand, the form, methodology and structure of Philoponus’ commentary on the Physics and, on the other hand, to study in depth his theory of place (topos). The book extends over five chapters and includes a preface, an epilogue and a bibliography. Philoponus attempts a double determination of place. He distinguishes between the place which is void, three-dimensional extension that is ontological different from bodies, and the concept of place that is filled by bodies. Philoponus wishes to redefine the relationship between place and body and he underlines the ontological difference that a bodiless extension should have from a bodily extension. The thesis also focuses on Philoponus’ critique of Aristotle’s definition of place and the Peripatetic tradition (Eudemus, Themistius) regarding the place of the heavens. The book concludes that, Philoponus’ strategy in the digressions of the commentary, but also in certain parts of his exegeses, can be seen in three stages: first, he repudiates the cogency of Aristotle’s and Themistius’ critique to the concept of local extension; second, he attacks the Aristotelian definition of place by showing its weaknesses and inconsistencies with the nature of things; and third, he establishes his own theory of place.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Boundary Between Mereology and Topology
    On the Boundary Between Mereology and Topology Achille C. Varzi Istituto per la Ricerca Scientifica e Tecnologica, I-38100 Trento, Italy [email protected] (Final version published in Roberto Casati, Barry Smith, and Graham White (eds.), Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences. Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium, Vienna, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1994, pp. 423–442.) 1. Introduction Much recent work aimed at providing a formal ontology for the common-sense world has emphasized the need for a mereological account to be supplemented with topological concepts and principles. There are at least two reasons under- lying this view. The first is truly metaphysical and relates to the task of charac- terizing individual integrity or organic unity: since the notion of connectedness runs afoul of plain mereology, a theory of parts and wholes really needs to in- corporate a topological machinery of some sort. The second reason has been stressed mainly in connection with applications to certain areas of artificial in- telligence, most notably naive physics and qualitative reasoning about space and time: here mereology proves useful to account for certain basic relation- ships among things or events; but one needs topology to account for the fact that, say, two events can be continuous with each other, or that something can be inside, outside, abutting, or surrounding something else. These motivations (at times combined with others, e.g., semantic transpar- ency or computational efficiency) have led to the development of theories in which both mereological and topological notions play a pivotal role. How ex- actly these notions are related, however, and how the underlying principles should interact with one another, is still a rather unexplored issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Proclus on the Elements and the Celestial Bodies
    PROCLUS ON THE ELEMENTS AND THE CELESTIAL BODIES PHYSICAL TH UGHT IN LATE NEOPLAT NISM Lucas Siorvanes A Thesis submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy to the Dept. of History and Philosophy of Science, Science Faculty, University College London. Deuember 1986 - 2 - ABSTRACT Until recently, the period of Late Antiquity had been largely regarded as a sterile age of irrationality and of decline in science. This pioneering work, supported by first-hand study of primary sources, argues that this opinion is profoundly mistaken. It focuses in particular on Proclus, the head of the Platonic School at Athens in the 5th c. AD, and the chief spokesman for the ideas of the dominant school of thought of that time, Neoplatonism. Part I, divided into two Sections, is an introductory guide to Proclus' philosophical and cosmological system, its general principles and its graded ordering of the states of existence. Part II concentrates on his physical theories on the Elements and the celestial bodies, in Sections A and B respectively, with chapters (or sub-sections) on topics including the structure, properties and motion of the Elements; light; space and matter; the composition and motion of the celestial bodies; and the order of planets. The picture that emerges from the study is that much of the Aristotelian physics, so prevalent in Classical Antiquity, was rejected. The concepts which were developed instead included the geometrization of matter, the four-Element composition of the universe, that of self-generated, free motion in space for the heavenly bodies, and that of immanent force or power.
    [Show full text]
  • PROCLUS and the ANCIENTS Steven K. Strange Emory
    PROCLUS AND THE ANCIENTS Steven K. Strange Emory University My title may be somewhat misleading. My subject will not be Pro- clus in general, but only his Parmenides Commentary, and I will only be concerned with those figures whom he calls in this commentary “the ancients” ( ? παλαι ), i.e., the older commentators on the dialogue, a group that certainly includes Porphyry, Amelius Gentilianus, and other early Neoplatonists, and perhaps Iamblichus, and some others whom we might suppose to be Middle Platonists, pre-Plotinian commentators. Who exactly is to be included in this category is, however, a some- what difficult and interesting question, which I wish to take up. I will examine the principal passages in which Proclus uses the expression ? παλαι in his commentary on the Parmenides,inorder,Ihope,topoint to some of the ways that they might be exploited to yield information about the earlier history of Parmenides-interpretation. I will be building throughout on the work of John Dillon in his notes and introductory material to his and Morrow’s translation of the Commentary,butIhope to be able to advance the discussion a little farther than he has done. There would be no difficulty, of course, if only Proclus had named the previous commentators whom he discusses, as he had done throughout his commentary on the Timaeus, which seems to have been among his earliest works. But the targets of his discussions in the Par- menides Commentary, in general, remain anonymous, their positions being introduced only by phrases like “some people say”, “others say”, and so forth: as Dillon argues in his Introduction,1 not naming names appears to have become Proclus’ standard practice in his later commentaries.
    [Show full text]
  • The Joint Philosophical Program of Russell and Wittgenstein and Its Demise
    The Joint Philosophical Program of Russell and Wittgenstein and Its Demise Abstract Between April and November 1912, Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein were en- gaged in a joint philosophical program. Wittgenstein‘s meeting with Gottlob Frege in De- cember 1912 led, however, to its dissolution – the joint program was abandoned. Section 2 of this paper outlines the key points of that program, identifying what Russell and Wittgenstein each contributed to it. The third section determines precisely those features of their collabora- tive work that Frege criticized. Finally, building upon the evidence developed in the preced- ing two sections, section 4 recasts along previously undeveloped lines Wittgenstein‘s logical– philosophical discoveries in the two years following his encounter with Frege in 1912. The paper concludes, in section 5, with an overview of the dramatic consequences the Frege- Wittgenstein critique had for Russell‘s philosophical development. 1. Introductory Remarks The subject of our investigation is the interaction between the three founding fathers of analytic philosophy, Russell, Wittgenstein and Frege, in a most important period of their philosophical development. We discuss the joint program that Russell and Wittgenstein worked on from April till November 1912, as well as its collapse after Wittgenstein visited Frege in Jena in December the same year. Frege‘s criticism of elements of the program underpinned and motivated Wittgenstein‘s attack on Russell‘s approach in philosophy that culminated in May and June 1913 when, facing Wittgenstein‘s criticism, Russell stopped writing the Theory of Knowledge book project. Frege‘s arguments also urged Wittgenstein to rethink and reformulate his own philosophical ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract 1. Russell As a Mereologist
    THE 1900 TURN IN BERTRAND RUSSELL’S LOGIC, THE EMERGENCE OF HIS PARADOX, AND THE WAY OUT Prof. Dr. Nikolay Milkov, Universität Paderborn, [email protected] Abstract Russell‘s initial project in philosophy (1898) was to make mathematics rigorous reducing it to logic. Before August 1900, however, Russell‘s logic was nothing but mereology. First, his acquaintance with Peano‘s ideas in August 1900 led him to discard the part-whole logic and accept a kind of intensional predicate logic instead. Among other things, the predicate logic helped Russell embrace a technique of treating the paradox of infinite numbers with the help of a singular concept, which he called ‗denoting phrase‘. Unfortunately, a new paradox emerged soon: that of classes. The main contention of this paper is that Russell‘s new con- ception only transferred the paradox of infinity from the realm of infinite numbers to that of class-inclusion. Russell‘s long-elaborated solution to his paradox developed between 1905 and 1908 was nothing but to set aside of some of the ideas he adopted with his turn of August 1900: (i) With the Theory of Descriptions, he reintroduced the complexes we are acquainted with in logic. In this way, he partly restored the pre-August 1900 mereology of complexes and sim- ples. (ii) The elimination of classes, with the help of the ‗substitutional theory‘,1 and of prop- ositions, by means of the Multiple Relation Theory of Judgment,2 completed this process. 1. Russell as a Mereologist In 1898, Russell abandoned his short period of adherence to the Neo-Hegelian position in the philosophy of mathematics and replaced it with what can be called the ‗analytic philoso- phy of mathematics‘, substantiated by the logic of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Doctrine of Homonyma in the Categories
    JOHN P. ANTON THE ARISTOTELIAN DOCTRINE OF HOMONYMA IN THE CATEGORIES AND ITS PLATONIC ANTECEDENTS * ι The Aristotelian doctrine of h ο m ο η y m a is of particular historical in­ terest at least for the following reasons : (1) It appears that the meaning of homo n.y m a was seriously debated in Aristotle's times aud that his own formu­ lation was but one among many others. Evidently, there were other platonizing thinkers in the Academy who had formulated their own variants. According to ancient testimonies, the definition which Speusippus propounded proved to be quite influential in later times 1. (2) The fact that Aristotle chose to open the Categories with a discussion, brief as it is, on the meaning of homonyma, synonyma, and paronym a, attests to the significance]he attached to this preli­ minary chapter. Furthermore, there is general agreement among all the commen­ tators on the relevance of the first chapter of the Categories to the doctri­ ne of the categories. (3) The corpus affords ample internal evidence that the doctrine of homonyma figures largely in Aristotle's various discussions on the nature of first principles and his method of metaphysical analysis. This being the case, it is clear that Aristotle considered this part of his logical theory to have applications beyond the limited scope of what is said in the Cate­ gories. Since we do not know the actual order of Aristotle's writings it is next to the impossible to decide which formulation came first. It remains a fact that Aristotle discusses cases of homonyma and their causes as early as the Sophistici * To παρόν άρθρον εστάλη υπό τοϋ συγγραφέως, φίλου του αειμνήστου Κ.
    [Show full text]
  • B Philosophy (General) B
    B PHILOSOPHY (GENERAL) B Philosophy (General) For general philosophical treatises and introductions to philosophy see BD10+ Periodicals. Serials 1.A1-.A3 Polyglot 1.A4-Z English and American 2 French and Belgian 3 German 4 Italian 5 Spanish and Portuguese 6 Russian and other Slavic 8.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z Societies 11 English and American 12 French and Belgian 13 German 14 Italian 15 Spanish and Portuguese 18.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z 20 Congresses Collected works (nonserial) 20.6 Several languages 20.8 Latin 21 English and American 22 French and Belgian 23 German 24 Italian 25 Spanish and Portuguese 26 Russian and other Slavic 28.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z 29 Addresses, essays, lectures Class here works by several authors or individual authors (31) Yearbooks see B1+ 35 Directories Dictionaries 40 International (Polyglot) 41 English and American 42 French and Belgian 43 German 44 Italian 45 Spanish and Portuguese 48.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z Terminology. Nomenclature 49 General works 50 Special topics, A-Z 51 Encyclopedias 1 B PHILOSOPHY (GENERAL) B Historiography 51.4 General works Biography of historians 51.6.A2 Collective 51.6.A3-Z Individual, A-Z 51.8 Pictorial works Study and teaching. Research Cf. BF77+ Psychology Cf. BJ66+ Ethics Cf. BJ66 Ethics 52 General works 52.3.A-Z By region or country, A-Z 52.5 Problems, exercises, examinations 52.65.A-Z By school, A-Z Communication of information 52.66 General works 52.67 Information services 52.68 Computer network resources Including the Internet 52.7 Authorship Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • 000 (London, 2009)
    Aristotle from York to Basra An investigation into the simultaneous study of Aristotle’s Categories in the Carolingian, the Byzantine and the Abbasid worlds by Erik Hermans A dissertation submitted in partial ful@illment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Institute for the Study of the AnCient World New York University May, 2016 _________________________ Robert Hoyland © Erik Hermans All Rights Reserved, 2016 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation is the produCt of a new and interdisCiplinary graduate program at the Institute for the Study of the AnCient World (ISAW) at New York University. Without the vision and generosity of Leon Levy and Shelby White ISAW would not have existed and this dissertation would not have been written. I am therefore greatly indebted to these philanthropists. At ISAW I was able to Create my own graduate CurriCulum, whiCh allowed me to expand my horizon as a ClassiCist and explore the riChness of Western Europe, Byzantium and the Middle East in the early medieval period. My aCademiC endeavors as a graduate student would not have been successful without the reliable, helpful and impeCCable guidanCe of Roger Bagnall. Without him AmeriCan aCademia would still be a labyrinth for me. I Consider myself very fortunate to have an interdisCiplinary Committee of supervisors from different institutions. Helmut Reimitz of PrinCeton University and John Duffy of Harvard University have voluntarily Committed themselves to the supervision of both my Comprehensive exams and my dissertation. I would like to thank them deeply for their time and assistanCe. However, I am most indebted to my primary advisor, Robert Hoyland.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereology and the Sciences SYNTHESE LIBRARY
    Mereology and the Sciences SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor-in-Chief LUCIANO FLORIDI, University of Oxford, Oxford Internet Institute, United Kingdom Editors THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen Fac. Philosophy, The Netherlands TEDDY SEIDENFELD, Carnegie Mellon University Dept. Philosophy, USA PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University Ctr. Study of Language & Information, USA JAN WOLEÑSKI, Jagiellonian University of Kraków Institute of Philosophy, Poland DIRK VAN DALEN, Utrecht University Department of Philosophy, The Netherlands VOLUME 371 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6607 Claudio Calosi Pierluigi Graziani Editors Mereology and the Sciences Parts and Wholes in the Contemporary Scientific Context 123 Editors Claudio Calosi Pierluigi Graziani Department of Basic Sciences and Department of Basic Sciences and Foundations Foundations University of Urbino University of Urbino Urbino Urbino Italy Italy ISBN 978-3-319-05355-4 ISBN 978-3-319-05356-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05356-1 Springer Cham Heidelberg New York Dordrecht London Library of Congress Control Number: 2014939928 c Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. Exempted from this legal reservation are brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis or material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
    [Show full text]